Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T17:36:39.167Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Natural Law: A Functional Interpretation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 August 2014

Burke Inlow*
Affiliation:
Princeton University

Extract

This study represents a preliminary inquiry into certain of the functional aspects of the natural law doctrine, particularly as it applies to American constitutional development. Throughout, the conceptual considerations, as such, will be ignored. Instead, the basic consideration will be one of usage. How does natural law work? What does it do? If this distinction seems arbitrary, the writer can only point out that law and politics are not theoretical studies; that they are the bone and sinew of society; that if the social order is to serve humanity with the greatest possible direction, it should know the proper functioning of its constituent elements. Natural law, like atomic energy, is important because it works, not because it was invented. And by the same token, it is best understood by a respectable familiarity with its usage, not by memorizing the symbols of its essence.

The easy identification of natural law with the constitutional development of this country is apparent from even a cursory examination of the great body of constitutional doctrine. We have, for example, the whole concept of property relationships as they have come to us from the eighteenth century. We have a similar form-pattern in the development of certain processes of the law itself. We talk of the “reasonable man,” or we invoke the “rule of reason.” But the decisive characteristic of American constitutional development has been none of these. Rather it has been the acceptance of the working principle of negation. To avoid an enactment or a statute is considered, in this country at least, a valid exercise of authority. While it might be difficult to seek the legitimate derivation of such an action, or even to justify it, it is possible to consider its assumptions.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 1947

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 However, see Wright, B. F., American Interpretations of Natural Law (Cambridge, 1931)Google Scholar.

2 Cooley, T. M., A Treatise on Constitutional Limitations (Boston, 1868), p. iv Google Scholar. See also Cardozo, B., The Nature of the Judicial Process (New Haven, 1921), p. 92 Google Scholar.

3 Chipman, N., Principles of Government (Burlington, 1833), p. 71 Google Scholar.

4 Morris, R. E., Studies in the History of American Law (New York, 1930), p. 28 Google Scholar.

6 “It is evident that there is a close relation between the law of constitutional limitations and the law of fundamental rights in America.” Thorpe, F. N., Essentials of American Constitutional Law (New York, 1917), p. 202 Google Scholar.

6 Winthrop, John, Journal, II, p. 438 Google Scholar, quoted in Morris, op. cit., p. 35.

7 John Locke, An Essay Concerning the True Original, Extent and End of Civil Government (2d Treatise), sec. 135.

8 “[These] principles impressed themselves upon American constitutional law by the limitations they laid down upon the legislative power.” Corwin, E. S., “Higher Law Background of American Constitutional Law,” Harvard Law Rev., Vol. 42 (19281929), p. 389 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9 Locke, for example, denied the validity of New England claims. See Gettell, R. G., History of Political Thought (New York, 1924), p. 226 Google Scholar.

10 “It is evident … that a belief in natural right found ready lodgment in the minds of residents along the frontier.” Paxson, F. L., History of the American Frontier (New York, 1924), p. 100 Google Scholar. Also see Paxson, , “Influence of Frontier Life on the Development of American Law,” State Bar Assoc. of Wis., Reports, XIII (191919201921)Google Scholar; Pound, R., Spirit of the Common Law (Boston, 1921)Google Scholar, Chap. V.

11 McIlwain, C. H., The American Revolution (New York, 1924)Google Scholar.

12 Jefferson, Thomas, Writings (Ford, P. L., ed., New York, 1898), IX, p. 474 Google Scholar.

13 Otis, James, “The Rights of the Colonists Asserted and Proved,” p. 69 Google Scholar. Reproduced in Mullett, C. F., “Some Political Writings of James Otis,” University of Missouri Studies, IV, No. 3 (1929), p. 325 Google Scholar.

14 Mullet, op. cit., p. 335.

15 Ibid., p. 334.

16 Bland, Richard, An Inquiry Into the Rights of the British Colonies (Williamsburg, 1776), p. 26 Google Scholar.

17 Ibid., p. 12.

18 Adams, John, Works (ed. by Adams, C. F., Boston, 1865), III, p. 449 Google Scholar.

19 Ibid., III, p. 480.

20 Ibid., III, p. 481.

21 Adams, R. G., Selected Political Essays of James Wilson (New York, 1930), p. 71 Google Scholar.

22 Ibid., p. 288.

23 Ibid., p. 251.

24 Winthrop, John, History of New England (ed. by Savage, J., Boston, 1853), I, p. 388 Google Scholar. Quoted in Morris, op. cit., p. 19.

25 3rd sec.

26 For an analysis of this problem, see Smith, J. Allen, Growth and Decadence of Constitutional Government (New York, 1930), pp. 1226 Google Scholar.

27 In re Dorsey, 7 Porter (Alabama) 377-378.

28 Pound, R., Introduction to the Philosophy of Law (New Haven, 1922), pp. 5052 Google Scholar.

29 Haines, C. G., The American Doctrine of Judicial Supremacy (Berkeley, 1932), Chap. IIIGoogle Scholar.

30 Calder v. Bull, 3 Dallas 385. Also Justice Iredell's concurring opinion.

31 4 Dallas 414.

32 Wilkinson v. Leland, 2 Peters 657.

33 Fletcher v. Peck, 6 Cranch. 87.

34 Hurtado v. California, 110 U.S. 536.

85 Butcher's Union Company v. Crescent City Co., 111 U.S. 759.

36 Cummings v. Missouri, 4 Wall. 321. Also see Barbier v. Connolly, 113 U.S. 31.

37 Address before the Bar, N. Y., New York Bar Assoc., Proceedings, 1893, p. 46 Google Scholar.

38 They were, of course, not confined to the federal judiciary. The Massachusetts supreme court declared during this time that “there are certain fundamental rights of every citizen which are recognized in the organic law of all our free American states. A statute which violates any of the rights is unconstitutional and void, even though the enactment of it is not expressly forbidden.” Commonwealth v. Perry, 155 Mass. 125.

39 U.S. v. Cruikshank, 92 U.S. 554.

40 Chicago, B & Q R. R. Co. v. Chicago, 166 U.S. 226.

41 Loan Assoc. v. Topeka, 20 Wall. 663.

42 However, see Haines, C. G., Revival of Natural Law Concepts (Cambridge, 1930), pp. 232234 Google Scholar.

43 Willoughby, W. W., The Constitutional Law of the United States (New York, 1929), pp. 1683 ffGoogle Scholar.

44 Hughes, C. E., The Supreme Court of the United States (New York, 1928), p. 187 CrossRefGoogle Scholar. (Italics mine.)

45 Whitney v. California, 274 U.S. 372. Justice Brandeis, for discussion.

46 However, see Swisher, Carl Brent, The Growth of Constitutional Power in the United States (Chicago, 1946)Google Scholar, Chap. V.

47 Wilson, W., Constitutional Government in the United States (New York, 1921), p. 8 Google Scholar.

Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.