Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rcrh6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T15:17:18.513Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

“Filling the Ranks”: Moral Risk and the Ethics of Military Recruitment

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 November 2023

JONATHAN PARRY*
Affiliation:
London School of Economics and Political Science, United Kingdom
CHRISTINA EASTON*
Affiliation:
The University of Warwick, United Kingdom
*
Corresponding author: Jonathan Parry, Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, Logic and Scientific Method, London School of Economics and Political Science, United Kingdom, [email protected].
Corresponding author: Jonathan Parry, Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, Logic and Scientific Method, London School of Economics and Political Science, United Kingdom, [email protected].
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

If states are permitted to create and maintain a military force, by what means are they permitted to do so? This article argues that a theory of just recruitment should incorporate a concern for moral risk. Since the military is a morally risky profession for its members, recruitment policies should be evaluated in terms of how they distribute moral risk within a community. We show how common military recruitment practices exacerbate and concentrate moral risk exposure, using the UK as a case study. We argue that the British state wrongs its citizens by subjecting them to excessively morally risky recruitment practices. Since, we argue, this risk exposure cannot be justified by appealing to the benefits of a military career for recruits, our argument calls for reform of existing practices. Our method of evaluation is generalizable and therefore can be used to assess other states’ practices.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the American Political Science Association

INTRODUCTION

If states are permitted to create and maintain a military force, by what means may they do so? This question is surprisingly neglected by moral and political theorists.Footnote 1 The just war literature focuses on the justification of initiating and conducting war. But though states place themselves in a position to go to war by recruiting and training a military, this aspect of war-making has received relatively little attention.Footnote 2 Theorists of distributive justice evaluate the allocation of benefits and burdens within a society. But this work tends to focus on the distribution of resources, rather than occupational roles.Footnote 3 And among theorists who do consider the distribution of occupations, the military occupation is largely ignored.

This article does not offer a general theory of just recruitment. Rather, we aim to shed light on an important, and underappreciated, consideration that should inform such a theory: Recruitment policies involve the state exposing its members to moral risk. Moral risk is the risk of engaging in serious moral wrongdoing. Our central proposal is that recruitment policies can be evaluated in terms of how they distribute a morally risky occupation within a community.

To make the proposal more concrete, our discussion centers on four features of military recruitment that are common (to varying degrees) to many states’ practices:

  • The youth of typical recruits.

  • The concentration of recruitment activities in areas of socioeconomic deprivation.

  • The involvement of the military and military-related industries in educational settings.

  • That recruitment takes place within a wider culture of celebration and reverence for the military.

These practices are often subject to moral criticism. We agree with the critics that these features are intuitively objectionable, but the rationale is rather inchoate. What grounds this judgment? Our proposal offers a novel diagnosis: These features are distinctively objectionable insofar as they exacerbate and concentrate moral risk exposure. This objection demands either special justification or reform of current practices.

The article proceeds as follows. The following section serves to motivate our moral risk-based proposal, by contrasting it with an alternative moral critique of recruitment. The subsequent sections develop the proposal in more detail and draw out its implications. We start by defending the background assumption that the military is a morally risky occupation for its members. We then argue that persons have a presumptive claim against exposure to moral risk, which grounds duties not to expose others to moral risk (and to take positive steps to reduce their exposure). This duty is grounded in persons’ weighty interest in avoiding serious moral wrongdoing and in the importance of respecting others’ moral capacities. Next, we outline a range of mechanisms by which we can expose others to moral risk. With these in place, we then illustrate how these mechanisms are frequently manifested in military recruitment policies. To do so, we critically examine military recruitment as practiced in the UK. Though our general approach and conclusions are applicable much more widely, we think this is a particularly illuminating case study, because the four features of recruitment outlined above are particularly salient in the UK context. We argue that UK practices are presumptively unjust, insofar as they transgress would-be recruits’ claims against moral risk exposure. This injustice is aggravated by the fact that the state has a special duty to safeguard the interests and capacities of its young people. We then consider and reject a common defense of recruitment practices, which holds that risk exposure can be justified by appealing to the overall benefits of giving young persons the opportunity for a military career. In the absence of this justification, states wrong their members by subjecting them to UK-style recruitment practices. We conclude by drawing out some of the implications of our approach.

BEYOND HARM: THE CASE FOR MORAL RISK

We begin by highlighting the limitations of a common and very natural line of criticism of military recruitment practices. This view emphasizes that the military is a potentially dangerous profession. The objection has two strands. The first points out that military personnel are exposed to increased risks of death or physical injury, as well as psychological trauma and mental illness. Moreover, there is evidence that the younger a person joins the military, the greater the risks.Footnote 4 The second part of the objection casts doubt on whether the typical recruit validly consents to these risks, given their immaturity, lack of full information, and paucity of alternative options (Gee Reference Gee2007; Medact 2016). States’ recruitment practices are thus charged with failing to take seriously their obligations not to expose young people to risks of harm.

Though undoubtedly correct, we contend that this harm-based critique is importantly incomplete, for two reasons. First, it fails to capture the intuitive asymmetry between military service and other dangerous professions. Consider hazardous careers (such as deep-sea fishing or playing professional American football) and jobs that involve significant risks of psychological trauma (such as online content moderators). These roles are plausibly at least as physically or psychologically dangerous as many military careers, but it nonetheless seems more objectionable to recruit disadvantaged young people into the military profession than for other risky jobs (holding the means of recruitment constant). Harm-based objections to military recruitment seem unable to account for this moral difference.

Second, the harm-based view struggles to explain the intuition that military recruitment would remain objectionable even if the risks of physical and psychological harms were eliminated from military service. Imagine, for example, that a military develops fully remote capabilities, whereby all dangerous roles are performed by drones and robots, operated by human personnel in complete safety. Imagine, furthermore, that personnel are given an entirely safe medication, which will prevent them from suffering any psychological trauma or distress.Footnote 5 In this (not wildly) hypothetical military, personnel would not be exposed to any risk of harm. Yet there remains something intuitively morally objectionable about recruiting disadvantaged young people into a zero-risk military. Harm-based objections cannot explain this.

A full normative evaluation of military recruitment therefore requires moving beyond a focus on harm. We propose that the missing objection to recruitment practices lies in the fact that the military is a morally risky profession. A profession is morally risky insofar as its members are subject to an increased likelihood of committing serious moral wrongs. On this view, we should not only be concerned about exposing young people to the risk of being killed and injured, but also about exposing them to an increased risk of becoming (wrongful) killers and injurers. This emphasis on moral risk accounts for the two cases that the harm-based view struggled with. While other hazardous professions may be at least as dangerous as a military career, there remains an asymmetry of moral risk. And even if a military were able to eliminate all risks of physical and psychological harm, the profession remains morally risky for its members.

THE MILITARY AS A MORALLY RISKY PROFESSION

We take our starting assumption—that serving in the military involves significant moral risk—to be relatively uncontroversial.Footnote 6 War involves killing and maiming, destroying homes and livelihoods, forcing people to become refugees, and many other horrors. If a war is unjustified, these constituent harms are serious moral wrongs.Footnote 7 These wrongs are carried out by military personnel. Given the significant risk that any operation will be morally unjustified, military personnel are subject to a significant risk of engaging in serious moral wrongdoing.Footnote 8 Note that this is compatible with the claim that combatants are often not blameworthy for participating in unjust wars. Excused wrongdoing is still wrongdoing. So, a profession that carries a significant risk of excused wrongdoing remains morally risky in the relevant sense.

This view relies on the idea that the moral status of combatants’ actions in war depends on the moral status of the war itself. This is sometimes called a “revisionist” view of the ethics of war (McMahan Reference McMahan2009). We find this extremely plausible, as do many other theorists who have considered the issue (indeed, the “revisionist” label is something of a misnomer). Moreover, the idea that fighting in an unjust war involves personal wrongdoing is also endorsed by many combatants (Dannenbaum Reference Dannenbaum2018, 40–9; Strawser Reference Strawser, Welsh, Akande and RodinForthcoming). However, one might deny that the military is a morally risky profession by denying that the moral status of participating in war is sensitive to the moral status of the war. According to so-called “orthodox” just war theory, it is morally permissible to participate in a war—whether just or unjust—provided one follows the norms of jus in bello (Walzer Reference Walzer2006). Hence, the risk of being ordered to participate in unjustified operations is not a significant source of personal moral risk.

As indicated, we think that this view is simply mistaken. But here are two responses which do not rely on this claim. First, almost all military operations carry a significant risk of violating jus in bello norms (such as inflicting disproportionate or unnecessary harm, as well as committing war crimes). On an orthodox account, participating in these wrongs is a source of serious personal wrongdoing. So, even on an orthodox view, the military profession includes a significant element of moral risk.

The second response appeals to moral uncertainty. Even if one is convinced that the orthodox view is correct, one’s confidence cannot be unreasonably high. The revisionist view rests on an extremely plausible general principle that seems obviously true in contexts other than war: other things being equal, the wrongfulness of an activity transmits to participation in that activity. Many intelligent and well-informed people (our “epistemic peers”) conclude that this principle applies in war too. So, even if we are ultimately persuaded by the orthodox view, we should accept that there is a non-negligible chance that we are wrong about this. This moral uncertainty is enough to render the military a morally risky profession. As long as there is a decent chance that the revisionist view is correct, there is a decent chance that participating in unjustified military operations will involve serious personal wrongdoing.Footnote 9

THE WRONG OF MORAL RISK EXPOSURE

The mere fact that the military is a morally risky profession neither entails that military recruitment policies stand in need of special justification, nor provides grounds for morally evaluating specific recruitment practices. These require an additional step in the argument: that persons have a presumptive claim against being exposed to moral risk. This claim grounds negative duties to avoid increasing the probability that others will engage in serious wrongdoing, as well as positive duties to reduce this probability. Moreover, these duties will be more stringent with respect to persons to whom we have independent duties to protect and support.

To illustrate the basic idea, consider two simple examples:

Lift: Carl is angry at Boss for firing him. He asks his friend Tony to give him a lift to Boss’s house. Tony suspects that Carl will lose his temper and beat up Boss.

Music: Carl is angry at Boss for firing him and drives to Boss’s house. His friend Tony is in the passenger seat and suspects that Carl will lose his temper and beat up Boss. Tony can play some soothing music on the car stereo which will calm Carl down.

Our claim is that Tony has a (pro tanto) duty, owed to Carl, to reduce the probability that Carl wrongfully assaults Boss, either by refraining from helping him to assault Boss (Lift) or by preventing him from doing so (Music).

What is the source of these duties? Drawing on existing work, we offer two complementary proposals. First, according to interest-based views, persons have claims to not be exposed to moral risk because committing serious wrongs is bad for the wrongdoer (Brownlee Reference Brownlee2019; Munch Reference Munch2022; Tadros Reference Tadros2016b; Reference Tadros2020). To clarify, the claim here is not that acting wrongly is bad for a person insofar as it causes other bads, such as feelings of distress and guilt, or punishment and social sanction. Rather, the idea is that committing a serious wrong itself sets back a person’s interests.

There are two ways to interpret the interest-based view. On one version, wrongdoing is a negative component of well-being (Brownlee Reference Brownlee2019). Acting wrongly diminishes a person’s prospects of leading a prudentially good or flourishing life. Though this view might seem unorthodox, it is worth noting that it is compatible with a fairly wide range of theories of well-being. Most obviously, it seems at home within “objective list” theories of well-being. These theories hold that a person’s well-being is determined by whether their life contains certain goods, such as achievements, valuable relationships, and knowledge. Alongside these items, we might add avoiding serious wrongdoing to the list. But the idea that wrongdoing is a negative component of well-being is also compatible with “desire-satisfaction” views. These hold, very roughly, that well-being consists in getting what one wants (or would want, under certain conditions). Since it seems plausible that most people have a strong desire to avoid committing serious wrongs—such as unjustified killing and injuring—it follows that their well-being is diminished by so acting. The only theories which rule out the possibility that wrongdoing is a negative component of well-being are thoroughgoing subjectivist views. These hold that only negatively valenced experiences can diminish well-being (and so wrongdoing is only prudentially bad insofar as it causes such experiences).

Even if one rejects the idea that wrongdoing is a negative component of well-being, this need not undermine the interest-based view. It can be understood in a second way, which distinguishes between our reasons to promote a person’s well-being and our reasons to act “for their sake” in some broader sense. On this view, persons’ interests outstrip their well-being (Tadros Reference Tadros2020). Hence, acting wrongly sets back persons’ interests in leading a life free of wrongdoing, even if it does not affect their well-being.

The core argument for the interest-based view appeals to judgments about trade-offs between avoiding wrongdoing and avoiding other kinds of costs. Consider the kind of trade-off you would prefer for yourself in the following case:

Revelation: You wake up from unconsciousness. Your memory of last night’s events is hazy. You know that somebody was wrongfully assaulted and injured. But you do not know if you were assaulted or if you committed the assault. You will shortly be given a tonic, that will restore last night’s memories for 30 seconds, before you permanently forget what happened (adapted from Tadros Reference Tadros2020, 231–2).

Would you hope to discover that you were the victim of the assault or the perpetrator? We find it very intuitive that, for some level of physical injury, we would strongly prefer the former over the latter. This outcome would be better for us. This is not explained by our interest in avoiding negative feelings of guilt, but rather by our interest in not committing wrongs. The intuition persists when it comes to making trade-offs on behalf of others, especially those whom we have special duties to care for, such as our children. For some level of cost, we would strongly prefer, for their sake, that our child suffer that cost, rather than commit a serious moral wrong.

Alongside interest-based views, there is a second kind of argument for duties not to expose others to moral risk. On this alternative view, these duties are grounded in our reasons to respect persons’ moral capacities (Howard Reference Howard2016). A person’s moral capacities include her ability to appreciate morally relevant reasons, evaluate her actions in light of those reasons, and conform her actions to those reasons.Footnote 10 Respect for those capacities demands (at minimum) that we do not set back a person’s success at acting in accordance with morality. We wrong a person when we, as Howard (Reference Howard2016) puts it, “subvert” the proper function of these capacities, by increasing the probability that they will act wrongly. Respect for a person’s moral capacities may also require that we take steps to help her avoid acting wrongly, such as by maintaining an environment that enables her to better develop and exercise those capacities.

For our purposes, we need not adjudicate between interest-based and respect-based explanations of the duty to avoid exposing others to moral risk. Both deliver similar results in cases such as Lift and Music. Moreover, these views are not exclusive. Exposing persons to moral risk is plausibly objectionable for both interest- and respect-based reasons.

One further point of clarification is in order. On our view, the duty to help others avoid serious wrongdoing extends to cases of non-culpable wrongdoing. To see this, consider variations on our earlier cases:

Revelation 2: The same as in Revelation, except that you know that the assault was entirely permissible relative to the perpetrator’s evidence, even though the assault was objectively wrongful. (Imagine that the perpetrator’s evidence strongly indicated that the victim was about to kill several innocent people, and that assaulting the victim was the only way to prevent this. In fact, the victim was entirely innocent.)

Music 2: The same as Music, except that Carl is fully justified in believing that assaulting Boss is morally justified. (Imagine that Carl’s evidence strongly indicates that beating up Boss is the only way to prevent Boss from killing several innocent people. In fact, Boss is entirely innocent). Tony (who is aware of the facts) can play soothing music that will calm Carl down and prevent him from carrying out the (fully excused) assault.

Our judgments match those in the original cases. In Revelation 2, we would strongly prefer—for our own sake—to discover that we were the victim, rather than the perpetrator, of a wrongful (but fully excused) assault. Similarly, in Music 2 we find it intuitive that Tony owes it to Carl to prevent Carl from (fully excusably) assaulting Boss.

VARIETIES OF MORAL RISK IMPOSITION

We have argued that we owe it to persons not to expose them to moral risk. But what is the precise content of this duty? In what ways can we expose others to moral risk, either intentionally or unintentionally? We think there are (at least) five broad mechanisms.

  1. 1. Situational: This involves simply placing someone in an environment where there are more background opportunities to engage in wrongdoing.

  2. 2. Practical: This involves giving people new practical reasons to act wrongly. Two obvious examples are incentivization (“Help me rob the bank and I’ll give you half the loot”) or coercion (“Help me rob the bank or I’ll post intimate photos of you online”) (Howard Reference Howard2016, 31).

  3. 3. Epistemic: This involves causing others to form false beliefs that increase their likelihood of wrongdoing. This might involve inducing ignorance of morally relevant nonmoral facts (e.g., telling somebody that factory farming does not inflict pain on animals, thereby influencing their decision to purchase factory-farmed meat), or it may involve inducing ignorance of relevant moral facts (e.g., telling somebody that animals lack moral status and so animal pain is not morally significant, thereby influencing their decision to purchase factory-farmed meat). Howard (Reference Howard2016, 31) suggests that “epistemic subversion” can also take place when someone is misled about the role that morality ought to play in decision-making, such as when someone is led to assign disproportionate weight to nonmoral reasons, such as self-interest (e.g., telling somebody that their love for bacon is sufficient to overcome their moral qualms about eating factory-farmed pigs).

  4. 4. Deliberative: This involves increasing someone’s likelihood of wrongdoing by inhibiting their deliberative abilities. Unlike epistemic forms of moral risk imposition—which shape a person’s evidence—the deliberative type involves impacting a person’s capacities to rationally govern their conduct. This involves interfering with a person’s ability to reason successfully about right and wrong in light of their evidence and to regulate their conduct in accordance with their conclusions (Howard Reference Howard2016, 29). On the former, for example, a person’s ability to engage in moral reasoning may be inhibited as a result of a restrictive education that failed to expose them to a diversity of reasonable opinions on moral matters, thereby depriving them of the opportunity to practice critical moral reflection. In terms of the latter, someone may have their confidence in their ability to make moral judgments systematically undermined, or have been trained to suppress their moral qualms and follow authority.

  5. 5. Distributive: The duty not to expose others to moral risk also has an important distributive dimension. A person’s exposure to moral risk is not only affected by changes in their circumstances (via the four mechanisms outlined above), but also by patterns of moral risk distribution within a population. In one kind of case, moral risks might be concentrated on a subset of the population. For example, government policies that lead to economic deprivation in certain areas can have predictable criminogenic effects on the (disproportionately young and male) residents of those areas, thereby increasing their opportunities and incentives for wrongdoing.Footnote 11 In another kind of case, a morally risky task might be distributed toward persons who are at a disadvantage in terms of avoiding wrongdoing. For example, a politician might deliberately make asylum criteria vague, so that inexperienced junior immigration staff are left to engage in morally risky decision-making instead. In fact, in cases like this, those subjected to moral risk may have two distinct complaints. Not only do they bear more moral risk (in virtue of their vulnerability), but others benefit from the moral burden being shifted onto the vulnerable party. As Robillard and Strawser (Reference Robillard and Strawser2022) have recently argued, this can be understood as a distinctive form of exploitation, which they call moral exploitation.

MILITARY RECRUITMENT PRACTICES AS DRIVERS OF MORAL RISK

With the preceding elements in place, we can now illustrate how our moral risk framework can be used to evaluate military recruitment practices. To do so, we take a critical look at recruitment as practiced in the UK.

Targeting Young Persons from Deprived Backgrounds

The UK is an international outlier in terms of its age of recruitment. Young people can serve from their sixteenth birthday and may sign up five months in advance of that date. No member of the EU recruits this young, and the UK is the only permanent member of NATO to do so. But the UK is distinctive not only for its low age threshold but also for the proportion of military personnel who are recruited young. Both the United States and France recruit from the age of 17, but only 6% and 3% of their armed forces enlist as minors, respectively (Gee and Taylor Reference Gee and Taylor2016, 36). By contrast, 23% of British Armed Forces recruits in the 2021/2022 intake signed up before their 18th birthday (rising to 30% for the army) (Ministry of Defence 2022).Footnote 12 Despite criticism from children’s rights organizations, political commentators, and (some) political parties, there are few signs of reform, with some in government calling for increased efforts to recruit young people to fill shortfalls.Footnote 13

Alongside the youthfulness of its intake, the UK military focuses its recruitment in areas of socioeconomic deprivation (Oxford Economics 2021, 34). In particular, those recruited as minors are disproportionately enlisted from these areas.Footnote 14 As a result, many recruits come from a background of low educational achievement. For example, three-quarters of junior recruits assessed in 2015 had a reading age of 11 or below (with some as low as 5) (Child Soldiers International 2019, 26).

Since the military profession presents opportunities for serious wrongdoing, all forms of military recruitment involve the situational variety of moral risk imposition. However, the demographic profile of British recruits elevates this risk. One key reason is that minors are more likely to be directed into combat roles, compared with those who join as adults (Child Soldiers International 2019, 4). Alongside the increased nonmoral risk (such as being injured or traumatized), these roles are additionally morally risky, since combat operations are a key locus of wrongdoing in ad bellum unjust military operations. Moreover, combat roles involve making difficult “on the ground” decisions and so have some of the highest levels of moral risk attached (e.g., having to make split-second decisions about whether to treat an approaching person as a civilian or enemy combatant).

In addition, young people are less equipped for moral decision-making. Their brains are still in a process of development that continues until roughly age 25 (with male brains taking approximately 2 years longer to develop than female brains) (Arain et al. Reference Arain, Haque, Johal, Mathur, Nel, Rais and Sandhu2013; Johnson, Blum, and Giedd Reference Johnson, Blum and Giedd2009; Medact 2016, 7–8). In particular, the prefrontal cortex—the area of the brain responsible for long-term planning, assessing risk, regulating emotion, and controlling impulsive behavior—undergoes significant developments for a decade after the age at which British children can apply to join the army (Johnson, Blum, and Giedd Reference Johnson, Blum and Giedd2009; Medact 2016; Steinberg Reference Steinberg2008). This unfinished process of neural, cognitive, and psychological development “leaves some adolescents particularly susceptible to making ill-judged decisions” (Medact 2016, 14).

Alongside these factors, there is reason to think that socioeconomic disadvantage exacerbates recruits’ exposure to moral risk. There is some evidence that heightened stress and adversity in childhood have developmental effects, which render individuals more likely to make important decisions (such as the decision to join the military) based on “emotive appeal rather than rational evaluation” (Child Rights International Network 2019, 13).Footnote 15 Rates of childhood adversity are high among members of the UK military, especially members of infantry and combat units. One major study found that among male military personnel as a whole, 37.5% reported being in trouble with the police, 29.8% reported being shouted at a lot at home, 25.5% reported often having been in fights at school, 17.9% had been suspended or expelled from school, and 3.3% had spent time in local authority care (Iverson et al. Reference Iverson, Fear, Simonoff, Hull, Horn, Greenberg and Hotopf2007). This adversity was concentrated among personnel who were young, in the army, and of lower ranks.Footnote 16 Insofar as adversity-related effects on decision-making increase one’s exposure to moral risk, there is reason to think that targeting recruitment among young people from backgrounds of socioeconomic deprivation involves selecting individuals who are less equipped to avoid moral risk.

More generally, there is evidence that economic deprivation imposes a “mental bandwidth” tax on the disadvantaged, where the need to attend to constant short-term crises depletes one’s stock of cognitive resources to devote to other things. This has significant effects on both cognition and self-control (Mullainathan and Shafir Reference Mullainathan and Shafir2013). Insofar as cognition and self-control are relevant to a person’s moral decision-making, recruiting from areas of socioeconomic deprivation involves selecting individuals subject to an externally imposed disadvantage in terms of avoiding moral risk.

Educational disadvantage also plausibly correlates with a moral risk disadvantage. For one thing, low educational attainment places an additional barrier to accessing relevant information for assessing the moral riskiness of the military profession.Footnote 17 Put crudely, if a recruit cannot read, it will be much harder for them to assess their employer’s moral track record. In addition, there is some evidence that schools in more deprived areas offer fewer opportunities to practice critical reflection. For example, Harris and Williams (Reference Harris and Williams2012) found that teachers in affluent schools ask more open questions and wait longer for children to respond, evidence of (and contributing to) higher-quality dialog. Moreover, since military involvement in educational settings is concentrated in deprived areas, and since (as we argue below) this involvement exacerbates moral risk, there is a further reason to think that young people’s socioeconomic disadvantage exacerbates moral risk.

Role of the Military and Arms Industry in Providing Careers Services, Training, and Educational Resources

The military has a growing presence in UK education. Over 500 schools already have Combined Cadet Forces (extracurricular programs run by the Ministry of Defence). The government invested an additional £50 million into expanding the programs between 2015 and 2020 (Scott Reference Scott2015), and additional funding has been pledged to continue the expansion (Department for Education 2021). Alongside the cadet program, the military maintains an extensive program of school visits and provides educational materials to schools. Military recruiters are often present at school career events, and significant funding for STEM education and career training comes from the military and military-related industries.

We contend that involving the military (and military-related industries) in educational settings serves to occlude the moral riskiness of military (and military-related) professions. The integration of war-related work into more general career training (e.g., a British Army stall at a careers fair) portrays this work as a job like any other. But as the House of Commons Defence Committee (2005, 28) puts it, “The Armed Forces require a fundamentally different commitment from that required in any other sphere of activity,” referring explicitly to the fact that the military profession involves the risk of killing (and not just the risk of being killed). The same point applies to the sponsorship of educational and career resources by arms manufacturers, which has been defended as a way of helping “inspire the next generation of engineers” (Doward Reference Doward2018). This portrays arms engineering as just one more socially productive form of engineering, ignoring the distinctive moral riskiness of participating in the arms industry.

In the same vein, recruitment materials have faced criticism for giving a one-sided presentation of military careers, focusing on the benefits of joining the military (e.g., “travel and adventurous training” and working alongside “best mates”) (Ministry of Defence N.d.a). They do little to foster awareness of the physical, psychological, and moral risks involved (Louise and Sangster Reference Louise and Sangster2019). The same is true of educational resources focused on the military. For example, mention of death or killing was absent from the “British Armed Forces Learning Resource” sent by the Department for Education to all schools in 2014.Footnote 18 The resource has been accused of presenting a “sanitised” view of the experiences of armed forces personnel and of UK military history, glorifying military values and conveying a simplistic view of soldiers as heroes (ForcesWatch 2015). (At one point, the military ethos is described as “a golden thread that can be an example of what is best about our nation and helps it improve everything it touches.”)

Within our framework, these practices can be understood as varieties of epistemic moral risk exposure: they induce moral ignorance by emphasizing nonmoral factors (e.g., the purported benefits of military-related careers) while (at best) ignoring or (at worst) suppressing discussion of morally relevant factors (e.g., that the use of force presents opportunities for grave moral wrongdoing).

Cultivating Patriotism in Schools

Since 2014, schools in England have been required to promote “British values” as part of their school ethos and across the curriculum (Department for Education 2014). While the original policy motivations focused on promoting “muscular liberalism” and countering extremism, schools have often interpreted the policy as encouraging patriotism, seeking to fulfill the statutory requirement by (for example) holding events celebrating the Royal Family and eating “British foods” such as fish and chips (Easton Reference Easton, Culp, Drerup, de Groot, Schinkel and Yacek2022).

Recently, there have been renewed calls for more patriotism in schools. In June 2021, the government endorsed “One Britain One Nation Day,” encouraging schoolchildren to sing a patriotic anthem (Woolcock, Ellery, and Grylls Reference Woolcock, Ellery and Grylls2021). In 2022, the (then) Education Secretary Nadhim Zahawi suggested that “overall I would like patriotism to be promoted in our schools unashamedly. The goal should be for our young people to be proud to be British and that on the whole we are a force of good” (Davis Reference Davis2022). In celebration of the Queen’s Platinum Jubilee in 2022, the Department for Education spent £12 million delivering a book to all schools aiming to inspire patriotism and give children a shared sense of Britain’s collective history (Booth Reference Booth2021).

These activities all seek to encourage a love of one’s country among students. But love can be dangerous. In the case of love of country, a lack of “critical distance” can cloud our political and moral judgments about the state’s activities (Hand Reference Hand2011, 29). Increased patriotism thus risks making it harder for young people to subject their state to critical scrutiny and to accurately assess the justification for particular military operations. This in turn makes it harder to assess the moral risks of joining the military. Instilling patriotism therefore manifests the first form of deliberative moral risk imposition described above, whereby one’s abilities to engage in moral reasoning are inhibited.

The second form of deliberative moral risk imposition is also relevant here. Love can cause us to give the interests of our loved one disproportionate weight in our decision-making, as when a parent wrongly prioritizes their own child’s interests, even when they know they ought not to. So, even if a patriot successfully evaluates their state’s moral credentials, their patriotism might prevent them from responding appropriately to their assessment.

Encouraging patriotism via education is also morally risky in the epistemic sense. Since a good deal of British history makes Britain “distinctly unlovable to someone possessed of an effective sense of justice” (Brighouse Reference Brighouse2006, 111), the aim of increasing love of country in students requires a degree of epistemic subversion: either imparting falsehoods, twisting the truth, or (at best) ignoring certain historical facts. In recent years, there has been growing support from British politicians for a teaching emphasis on the positive elements of British history, such as (in Zahawi’s words) the “benefits of the British Empire” (Davis Reference Davis2022). But inspiring national pride by teaching, in the words of former education secretary Michael Gove “the proper narrative of British history” (Hand Reference Hand2011, 8), requires downplaying the incidence and significance of state injustice (as Gove later emphasized, “This trashing of our past has to stop” [Wozniak Reference Wozniak2010]).Footnote 19 This conflicts with equipping young citizens to avoid moral risk. As Moody-Adams (Reference Moody-Adams2022) puts it, “comprehensive historical understanding is … a central element of the information we need to be responsible moral agents.”

Push for a “Military Ethos” in Schools

In 2012, the UK government launched an initiative to promote a “military ethos” in schools, citing the values of “loyalty, resilience, courage and teamwork” that the military embodies (ForcesWatch 2012).Footnote 20 The primary focus has been on expanding the Combined Cadet Forces, especially in disadvantaged areas. Targets for 500 new units were met, and a new round of funding was announced in 2021 with a target of reaching 60,000 cadets (Department for Education 2021). Other programs introduced under the “military ethos” umbrella include “Troops to Teachers” (designed to fast-track ex-military personnel into teaching positions) (Department for Education 2013b), and schemes led by former armed forces members to tackle student underachievement, with activities ranging from one-to-one mentoring to military-style obstacle courses (Department for Education 2013a).

“Military ethos” projects in schools have been praised for instilling “discipline” and reducing “negative behaviours” (Department for Education 2013a). But while the virtues of obedience and deference to authority can be valuable in some respects, they are unconducive to producing citizens capable of subjecting authorities to critical scrutiny. A student schooled under this “military ethos” has fewer opportunities to engage in independent moral reflection, particularly regarding the military profession. Moreover, a culture of obedience and deference makes it harder for young people to act on the moral conclusions that they do draw. Promoting a “military ethos” is thus another example of the deliberative form of moral risk imposition.

Push to Celebrate and Revere the Military in Wider Society

UK recruitment takes place within a broader political culture in which celebration of, and reverence for, the military is increasingly associated with good citizenship. Despite the public generally having high regard for the armed forces (Dixon Reference Dixon2018, 25–31), the last two decades have seen significant political efforts to encourage greater support for the military (Danilova Reference Danilova2015; Dixon Reference Dixon2018).Footnote 21

National public events concerning the military have traditionally centered on Remembrance Day, but since 2009 this has been supplemented with a rebranded Armed Forces Day. Armed Forces Day is justified as providing a morale boost for the Armed Forces community, as well as promoting civil–military integration.Footnote 22 The celebrations (described by one researcher as a “de facto military recruitment fair” [Danilova Reference Danilova2015, 92]) include events such as parades, flying displays, and other “capability demonstrations” (Armed Forces Major Events Team N.d.). The focus is exclusively on the positives of the military, leading to charges of glorifying war (Danilova Reference Danilova2015, 92).

Remembrance Day has also undergone notable changes. What began as a day for solemn reflection on lives lost in the First World War and the importance of peace has expanded toward showing support for soldiers involved in all British operations. Remembrance Day activities and associated paraphernalia (most notably, the famous Red Poppy) are dominated by the Royal British Legion, according to whom remembrance “honours those who serve” (Royal British Legion N.d.).Footnote 23 The implicit message is that this honor is given unconditionally, regardless of whether the wars fought in were justified or fought justly.

In line with our earlier discussion, our view is that increasing public focus on the military’s successes and virtues—while ignoring its moral failings and vices—results in an epistemically morally risky picture of the military, which radically underestimates the moral risks associated with military service.Footnote 24

In addition, we contend that the push to celebrate and revere the military has created another source of moral risk, by discouraging and delegitimizing moral criticism of the military. For example, failing to join in with Remembrance celebrations (or participating in alternative ways, such as by wearing a white poppy) is increasingly cast as ungrateful and unpatriotic (Shiner Reference Shiner2018). The vilification of those who do not wear a red poppy (especially public figures) has become common (spawning the term “poppy fascism” to describe the phenomenon) (English Reference English2017; Hall Reference Hall2017).Footnote 25

A similar phenomenon can be detected in the political and public discourse surrounding the creation of the Armed Forces Covenant in 2010. This legislation affirms a moral obligation to support the armed forces and (since 2021) imposes statutory obligations on certain public bodies to pay “due regard” to the interests of members of the armed forces and their families. A key part of the political rhetoric surrounding the introduction, and continuation, of the Covenant is that the military is, in some sense, under threat from a hostile and unsupportive public, that requires moral correction.Footnote 26

A more extreme variant of these sentiments was present in the political debate surrounding the Overseas Operations (Service Personnel and Veterans) Act 2021. The Act imposes new limits on bringing legal claims against members of the military for actions overseas. The original Bill proposed a five-year time limit on prosecuting members of the armed forces for international crimes committed abroad, but was subsequently watered down (as critics pointed out, the Bill came close to proposing a de facto amnesty for war crimes). But a key rallying point for defenders of the Bill was that allegations against British troops (including unlawful killings and torture) were largely vexatious claims brought by those with a political axe to grind. As then Prime Minister Teresa May MP proclaimed, “We will never again in any future conflict let those activist left-wing human rights lawyers harangue and harass the bravest of the brave, the men and women of our armed forces” (The Independent 2016). On this telling, soldiers require protection from the weaponization of moral and legal norms by bad actors.

This combination of vilification and credibility denial has a chilling effect on moral debate and deliberation about decisions to go to war and conduct in war. When dissent and criticism are recast as disrespectful and bad faith, it becomes harder for persons to think clearly about the rights and wrongs of military actions and hence about the moral riskiness of the military profession.Footnote 27

Pervasiveness of “Just War Myths”

Finally, we contend that commonly accepted ethical norms regarding war are themselves a source of moral risk—in particular, the pervasiveness of the view that conduct in war is subject to radically different moral norms to those that apply in other domains. The most common manifestation of this view is the idea—reflected in orthodox just war theory—that killing (or helping to kill) in an unjust war does not involve personal moral wrongdoing. As we noted earlier, there are good reasons to doubt that this is true, and this doubtfulness accounts for a significant portion of the moral riskiness of the military profession. Hence, the fact that the orthodox view is accepted as the default or “common-sense” view of the morality of participation in war is itself a significant source of epistemic moral risk. As James Christensen puts it:

By promulgating the view that it is permissible to fight regardless of a war’s moral status, we facilitate injustice. When we tell the young, impressionable individuals who comprise our armed forces that they can do no wrong, we invite them to forgo moral reflection (Christensen Reference Christensen2020, 190, drawing on McMahan Reference McMahan2009, 6–7).Footnote 28

Interim Conclusion

Individually and collectively, the practices discussed above increase young people’s exposure to moral risk. Since there is a general duty to avoid exposing others to moral risk, we conclude that the British state presumptively wrongs its young people by subjecting them to these practices. Furthermore, since the state has a special duty of care that requires protecting and supporting its children and young people, it follows that the state’s duty to avoid exposing these citizens to additional moral risk is more stringent. It is typically a graver wrong to fail to fulfill one’s general duties to those to whom one owes special duties of care (Gardner Reference Gardner, Duff, Farmer, Marshall, Renzo and Tadros2013).

Though our conclusion is specific to the UK context, our aim in discussing this case is to demonstrate a general approach to evaluating military recruitment in light of a concern for the creation and distribution of moral risk within a community, that can be applied to other contexts.

ARE THE RISKS COMPENSATED?

We now consider an important defense against our criticism. This response accepts that UK-style recruitment practices involve moral risk exposure, but argues that these practices are nonetheless justified by virtue of the overall benefits young people can expect from a military career. If recruitment practices are in young people’s interests, then they need not be wronged by being exposed to the associated moral risk. We will consider two versions of this “Compensation Defense.”

The Prudential Compensation Defense

The first defense, common in popular and political discourse, claims that exposing young people to the military profession is prudentially beneficial. Indeed, such benefits are often invoked to resist calls for reform (such as raising the minimum age of enlistment) on the grounds that this would deprive young people of a valuable opportunity.Footnote 29 The most common arguments focus on social mobility: The military offers opportunities for acquiring education and training for underprivileged young people. Recent recruitment advertising emphasizes the benefits of “seeing the world” (or “getting out”) and making friends. The military also claims to improve recruits’ health and to instill self-discipline (and other valuable traits). It is also sometimes claimed that a military career provides prudential moral benefits too. For example, that the military “gets kids off the streets” who would otherwise be going down a path of crime and vice. There is thus a case to be made that recruits are compensated for the moral risks they are exposed to.

We offer three arguments against this version of the Compensation Defense.

Unclear Benefits

Our first response questions whether serving in the military is unambiguously beneficial for recruits. Although the military is often praised for offering people a “leg up,”Footnote 30 there is little evidence to support claims that military service contributes to social mobility (the military does not collect socioeconomic data on recruits) (ForcesWatch 2017). Veterans are no more likely than nonveterans to be in work, and their jobs are more likely to be unskilled (Child Soldiers International 2019, 2). Reemployment rates are particularly low among those who have served in the infantry, with one study suggesting that 30% of infantry veterans who had left the army within four years of starting their training were not in work or education (Fossey and Hughes Reference Fossey and Hughes2013, 9).

Rather than “rescuing” young people from unemployment, for most recruits joining the military amounts to the end of their full-time education. The level of education provided for youth recruits is significantly below high school standards (inspection standards for military education providers—unlike schools—exclude quality of education) (Child Soldiers International 2019, 2). Unlike in the United States, there is no supported pipeline into higher education for ex-service personnel, and veterans are 10% less likely to have a degree than nonveteran members of the UK population (Hatfield Reference Hatfield2020).

It is plausible that the health of recruits is better than that of the general population during their term of service. However, long-term health can be impacted by injuries sustained during service, and overall health is often negatively impacted by poor mental health (Oster et al. Reference Oster, Morello, Venning, Redpath and Lawn2017). Veterans are more likely to experience common mental health problems, such as depression and anxiety, than those in the general population, and are almost twice as likely to experience alcohol problems (Community Innovations Enterprise 2015).

Lastly, it is unclear whether a military career benefits recruits by removing them from criminogenic environments.Footnote 31 Military personnel are more likely than their civilian peers to commit violent, sexual, and drug-related offenses (MacManus et al. Reference MacManus, Dean, Jones, Rona, Greenberg, Hull, Fahy, Wessely and Fear2013). Although only approximately 3% of those in British prisons are ex-service personnel (Ministry of Justice 2021),Footnote 32 veterans are overrepresented in the prison population for violent and sexual crimes (Howard League for Penal Reform 2011).

However, it is admittedly difficult to assess the extent to which negative outcomes for veterans can be attributed to having served in the military, since military recruitment selects for those who are already at higher risk of negative life outcomes.Footnote 33 But, at the very least, the case for the prudential benefits of a military career remains to be shown. Moreover, as we argue below, the Compensation Defense fails even if the prudential benefits obtain.

Gratuitous Risk

Our second response targets a key assumption behind the Compensation Defense. The assumption is that exposing a person to (a risk of) harm is justified simply if the (expected) benefit to that person is greater than the (expected) harm. But this is not true. To justify a harmful action by appealing to the benefits to the person harmed, the harm must also be necessary to provide the benefit (i.e., there must be no feasible way of providing the benefit without the harm). To illustrate, consider a simple example:

Smoothie: Angie is deficient in Vitamin C and drinking orange juice will give her 10 units of benefit. However, she is allergic to apples and drinking apple juice will give her 2 units of harm. Billy makes Angie an orange and apple smoothie, which Angie drinks.

Here Billy gives Angie a net benefit. Does this justify providing the smoothie? This crucially depends on whether Billy had the option of providing the benefit without the harm. If Billy could have given Angie a glass of orange juice sans apple, the fact that the benefits of the orange juice outweigh the harm of the apple is insufficient to justify the harm. Billy cannot defend giving Angie the smoothie by saying “What are you complaining about? You are amply compensated for your allergic reaction!” Billy wrongs Angie because the harm is gratuitous, even if it is outweighed.

Let us apply this point to the Compensation Defense. The upshot is that even if the empirical claims made on behalf of military recruitment are true (that the opportunity for military service is overall beneficial to young people), it does not follow that the exposure to moral risk is justified. It also needs to be shown that the risk is necessary for providing the benefits: that there is no feasible way of supplying the benefit at lower risk. But it is implausible that there are no feasible reforms to recruitment practices that would reduce moral risk without jeopardizing the benefits.

Irrelevant Baselines

Our third response focuses on the source of the putative prudential benefits of a military career. The Compensation Defense typically focuses on the advantages of military service relative to a baseline of social deprivation and lack of opportunity (such as poverty, poor education, and lack of social mobility). The military is billed as a good option for young people because it provides a “way out” of these circumstances.

However, two further factors pose a problem for the Compensation Defense. The first is that the background social deprivation obtains (at least partly) as a result of distributive and social injustice. The second is that the state bears some responsibility for this unjust deprivation, either by contributing to it or failing to remedy it. This should not be particularly controversial. It is hard to deny that the social deprivation present in areas targeted for military recruitment is (at least partly) attributable to policy failures.

Crucially, the fact that the state bears responsibility for the unjust deprivation that (purportedly) renders military recruitment beneficial for young people (despite the moral risk) undermines the state’s ability to invoke the Compensation Defense. The state cannot claim to have discharged its duty of care to young people by appealing to the benefits of giving young people a risk-imposing opportunity if it is culpably sustaining the background conditions that make that opportunity beneficial. To discharge its duty of care, the state must first fulfill its obligations to address background deprivation. Justifications cannot be derived from one’s own ongoing moral failures.Footnote 34 The relevant baseline for judging whether a state-provided option counts as overall beneficial to a person is how well off that person would be if the state fulfilled its obligations to combat distributive and social injustice. Once we make the morally appropriate comparison, a significant proportion of the “benefits” of military service are rendered ineligible for the Compensation Defense.

The Moral Compensation Defense

We now consider a second version of the Compensation Defense. It points out that alongside the moral risk of committing serious wrongs, military personnel also have a chance of contributing to significant moral goods (such as justified humanitarian interventions, peacekeeping operations, aid delivery, rescues, and maintaining valuable deterrence). This expectation of doing good outweighs the moral risk that recruits are exposed to via recruitment practices, and so recruits are not wronged by being subjected to those practices.

One way to defend this moral version of the Compensation Defense is via an argument for the permissibility of individuals joining the military. One might argue that if a state is justified in having its current military, relative to having no military, then its military institutions must be expected to overall do more good than bad. If having a military is justified in this “minimal” sense, then it plausibly follows that would-be recruits can expect to do more good than bad by participating in that military. So, as long as a state is not morally required to abolish its military, individuals are morally justified in enlisting.Footnote 35 The Moral Compensation Defense can be derived by adding one further step to this argument: the same expectation of doing overall good that renders it permissible for individuals to join a military also renders it unobjectionable to induce individuals to join that military via morally risky military recruitment practices.

We offer three responses, which mirror our responses to the prudential version of the Compensation Defense.

First, it is not obvious that military institutions typically satisfy the minimal justification test. Dobos (Reference Dobos2020) has recently argued at length that we tend to radically underestimate the moral costs of having standing militaries and that the majority of states’ military institutions are likely to do more bad than good. So, if one wants to employ the Moral Compensation Defense to justify specific state recruitment practices—like those of the UK—one will need to make a compelling case that the UK military is minimally justified.

Second, even if we grant that a state’s military is minimally justified, the Moral Compensation Defense runs into the same gratuitous risk problem discussed earlier. The mere fact that the overall moral benefits of joining the military outweigh the moral risk does not make it permissible to expose a person to that risk, if the risk imposer could feasibly have mitigated the risk. As we pointed out, it seems implausible that states like the UK could not maintain an effective military via a less morally risky suite of recruitment practices.

To give one example, research indicates that the practice of recruiting minors may in fact be detrimental to maintaining capable military personnel.Footnote 36 Analysis by Gee and Taylor (Reference Gee and Taylor2016) suggests that a transition to a “Straight 18” recruitment model is economically feasible, and the Ministry of Defence has not provided evidence to the contrary (despite requests from the House of Commons Defence Committee to investigate the feasibility of raising the recruitment age) (House of Commons Defence Committee 2005, 42–3). Since other countries manage to fill their ranks without recruiting minors, we find it implausible that alternative means of recruitment could not achieve the desired results. In any case, it is very implausible that every morally risky element of UK recruitment we have identified could not feasibly be reformed.

Third, there is an additional form of gratuitous moral risk in play. Just as states typically have the option of reforming their recruitment policies to reduce their moral riskiness, states are also typically able to reform their military institutions and policies in ways that will lower the risk of military wrongdoing. Even if a state’s current military institutions are minimally justified, compared to having no military at all, it is very unlikely that those institutions are as good as they could feasibly be, in terms of avoiding wrongdoing. When states fail to take reasonable steps to reduce the risk of military wrongdoing, they impose gratuitous moral risk on their military personnel. Military personnel are thereby wronged, even if they can expect to do more overall moral good than bad by joining the military.

These problems of gratuitous risk highlight that even if individuals are justified in joining the military (in virtue of their expectation of doing more good than bad), it does not follow that those recruits are not wronged by recruitment. Recruits and recruiters have different option sets. Recruits do not have the option of reducing the moral risks associated with their state’s recruitment practices and military institutions. Since they lack this option, their decision to enlist may be morally optimal for them, despite the moral risk. But states typically do have these additional, risk-reducing options. So, recruitment can be morally suboptimal for the recruiter, even if enlistment is morally optimal for the recruit.

CONCLUSION

Our central contention is that a theory of just recruitment should incorporate a concern for moral risk. Alongside the duty to avoid exposing others to risks of prosaic harms, such as death, injury, and psychological trauma, we also have presumptive duties to avoid exposing others to increased risks of committing serious wrongs. Recruitment practices should therefore be evaluated in terms of how they create and distribute moral risk within a community.

To illustrate this idea, we have argued that UK-style practices are deficient at the bar of just recruitment. These practices expose young people to excessive moral risk via a variety of mechanisms. Because this exposure is not justified by compensating benefits, the state wrongs its young people by subjecting them to these practices. Since the general mechanisms of moral risk exposure are not unique to the UK, our mode of evaluation is applicable to other contexts, and the implied avenues of reform will be relevant to other countries too.

Our framework adds further weight to the case—already pressed by activists, NGOs, and human rights organizations—against recruiting minors and targeting recruitment at disadvantaged individuals. But our argument also suggests some new areas that ought to be targeted for reform. We should be concerned not only with the demographic of those targeted for recruitment, but also with the wider context in which recruitment takes place. This speaks against militarization in wider society and against the promotion of uncritical patriotism. In particular, it allows us to see that the stifling of critical discussion—especially about the moral assessment of military personnel and military operations—contributes to the moral riskiness of military recruitment. Looking beyond recruitment, our approach calls for broader reforms of military institutions that would make the military profession less morally risky, ranging from government decision-making about the use of force to military training.Footnote 37

Finally, though we have argued that compensation alone cannot justify morally risky recruitment practices, our framework supports calls for providing military personnel with improved benefits. These might, for example, include funded schemes to encourage veterans’ access to further education and better pay and leaving packages.Footnote 38 Even if compensation does not eliminate or even lessen the injustice, it does at least provide some acknowledgment of the wrong that is being done. It is morally important that the state recognizes the price being paid by its current recruitment practices.

Acknowledgements

This research was presented at a University of Warwick Just War workshop; the University of Birmingham Global Ethics seminar; the University of Birmingham Philosophy of Education seminar; a workshop co-organized with ForcesWatch; a Newcastle University Philosophy and Public Policy workshop; and departmental seminars at the University of Nottingham, the University of Toronto (online), and the London School of Economics and Political Science. The authors are grateful to the audiences for their feedback. For written comments, the authors are especially grateful to Jane Gatley, Thomas Bostock, Lewis Ross, David Gee, Jan Kandiyali, Nicola Mulkeen, and Emma Sangster. The authors specially thank Ziming Xia for his excellent research assistance at an early stage of the project and three anonymous reviewers at APSR for their helpful suggestions.

FUNDING STATEMENT

Jonathan Parry’s work on this article was supported by funding from UK Research and Innovation (UKRI) under the UK government’s Horizon Europe funding guarantee scheme [Grant Number: EP/X01598X/1]. UKRI Data Statement: This work contains no data. Christina Easton’s work on this article was supported by a British Academy Post-Doctoral Fellowship [Grant Number: PF21\210082].

CONFLICT OF INTEREST

The authors declare no ethical issues or conflicts of interest in this research.

ETHICAL STANDARDS

The authors affirm this research did not involve human subjects.

Footnotes

1 As Cheyney Ryan pithily puts it, “In the field of philosophy, there are more articles on what it is like to be a bat than what it’s like to be a soldier” (Ryan Reference Ryan, Robillard and Strawser2022, 188).

2 For exceptions, see, for example, Dobos (Reference Dobos2020), Robillard and Strawser (Reference Robillard and Strawser2022), Ryan (Reference Ryan2009), and Surber (Reference Surber2023). There is a small literature on the “macro” ethics of military recruitment: the question of whether to recruit a volunteer force or use a system of conscription (see, e.g., Galston Reference Galston2003; Pattison Reference Pattison2011; Sagdahl Reference Sagdahl2018). Little work evaluates the different means of creating a volunteer military.

3 However, the trend does seem to be shifting (see, e.g., Gheaus and Herzog Reference Gheaus and Herzog2016; Kandiyali Reference Kandiyali2023; Parr Reference Parr2022; Schouten Reference Schouten, Sobel, Vallentyne and Wall2016).

4 Medact (2016) documents young recruits’ increased risk of PTSD, suicide, self-harm, and alcohol misuse. Gee and Goodman (Reference Gee and Goodman2013) found that 16-year-old British recruits were twice as likely to be killed or injured in operations in Afghanistan, compared with those who enlisted post-18. Other studies indicate that youth and childhood adversity (a factor associated with socioeconomic disadvantage) increases vulnerability to mental health problems among recruits (Campbell Reference Campbell2022).

5 On the pharmacological possibilities, see Dobos (Reference Dobos2023).

6 Of course, we are not claiming that other professions are not morally risky. For one example, see Rosenthal (Reference RosenthalForthcoming).

7 For complications, see, for example, Bazargan (Reference Bazargan2011) and Tadros (Reference Tadros2016a). These complications do not undermine our general claim that the military is a morally risky profession.

8 For further arguments, see McMahan (Reference McMahan2013) and Strawser (Reference Strawser, Welsh, Akande and RodinForthcoming). For additional sources of moral risk within the military profession, see Robillard (Reference Robillard2017) and Wolfendale and Portis (Reference Wolfendale and Portis2021).

9 Strawser (Reference Strawser, Welsh, Akande and RodinForthcoming) offers a more detailed version of this argument. For analogous arguments in a different context, see Moller (Reference Moller2011).

10 Howard takes these capacities to be similar to what Rawls describes as persons’ “first moral power” (Rawls Reference Rawls2005, 19).

11 This example drives Tadros’ (Reference Tadros2020) argument that the distribution of responsibility for wrongdoing is a matter of distributive justice, as well as Howard’s (Reference Howard2016) argument that criminogenic policies inflict the wrong of entrapment on citizens.

12 The proportion of child recruits is even higher for infantry sections of the army.

13 Our article takes its title from a 2017 government report by Mark Francois MP (Francois Reference Francois2017). The report makes a number of recommendations aimed at increasing recruitment, including making the Armed Forces a topic on the National Curriculum (9), increasing cadet forces nationwide so that more young people experience a military ethos (10), and stepping up recruitment efforts within cadet forces (“within the legal constraints”) (10).

14 One study of enlisted minors found that recruitment was 57% higher in the poorest fifth of constituencies compared with the wealthiest fifth (Child Rights International Network 2019).

15 See also Medact (2016). For summaries of the evidence, see, for example, Hackman and Farah (Reference Hackman and Farah2009), Kishiyama et al. (Reference Kishiyama, Boyce, Jimenez, Perry and Knight2009), and Moriguchi and Shinohara (Reference Moriguchi and Shinohara2019).

16 A study by Veterans for Peace (Gee Reference Gee2017) estimates that British infantry recruits (who are younger and from more disadvantaged backgrounds) were 50% more likely to have experienced high levels of childhood adversity.

17 In addition, low-income citizens tend to have access to fewer, and poorer quality, news sources (Hamilton and Morgan Reference Hamilton and Morgan2018). For a philosophical discussion of the issue, see Kurtulmuş and Kandiyali (Reference Kurtulmuş, Kandiyali, Fox and SaundersForthcoming).

18 Promoted by the Department for Education under the curriculum category of “Spiritual, moral, social and cultural development.” The Department website no longer hosts this resource, but an archived copy can be found at https://studylib.net/doc/18618617.

19 On the recent “history wars” in the UK, see Watson (Reference Watson2020).

20 References to “loyalty” have since been removed from the Department for Education webpage (Department for Education 2013a).

21 Many of these initiatives can be traced to recommendations in the Report of Inquiry into National Recognition of our Armed Forces (Davies, Clark, and Sharp Reference Davies, Clark and Sharp2008) and the Report of the Task Force on the Military Covenant (Strachan et al. Reference Strachan, Armour, Healey and Smith2010).

22 For illustrative statements of these aims, see, for example, the Armed Forces Day website (Ministry of Defence N.d.b) and the website of the Armed Forces Major Events Team North East Lincolnshire (Armed Forces Major Events Team N.d.)

23 This supports the common criticism that Remembrance Day has become less about remembrance and more about showing support for the current military (see, e.g., ForcesWatch 2015, 9).

24 For a general discussion of the ethics of states’ use of symbolism and nonrational persuasion, see Tsai (Reference Tsai2016).

25 For a philosophical account, see Archer and Matheson (Reference Archer and Matheson2022).

26 On political efforts to construct this perception of threat, see Dixon (Reference Dixon2018).

27 As Quakers in Britain (2021, 3) put it in response to the Armed Forces Bill, “society needs the freedom to question British military policy without fear of censure.”

28 We are reminded here of Bernard Williams’s worry that moral philosophy risks “misleading people about matters of great importance” (Williams Reference Williams1972, xvii).

29 See, for example, Penny Mordaunt’s (then Minister of State for the Armed Forces) letter to Child Soldiers International (Mordaunt Reference Mordaunt2016).

30 For example, the military is described as a “vehicle for social mobility” (Ministry of Defence 2017).

31 A Home Office-commissioned review of interventions to prevent gang involvement, youth violence, and crime is skeptical about the efficacy of military-style intervention programs (O’Connor and Waddell Reference O’Connor and Waddell2015).

32 Other estimates are higher (Gee Reference Gee2007, 131; Howard League for Penal Reform 2011).

33 The problem of selection effects is widely acknowledged in the literature on veteran outcomes (e.g., MacLean and Elder Reference MacLean and Elder2007). However, McManus et al. (Reference MacManus, Dean, Al Bakir, Iversen, Hull, Fahy, Wessely and Fear2012) report that rates of violence among veterans remain strongly associated with combat and trauma, controlling for pre-enlistment antisocial behavior and other sociodemographic factors.

34 Our objection here is similar to Cohen’s (Reference Cohen and Petersen1992) well-known “interpersonal test” for the validity of moral justifications.

35 This argument is drawn from Lazar (Reference Lazar and Edmonds2016).

36 One reason is that younger recruits are more likely to drop out before completing their training. Among some youth cohorts, nearly half drop out within four years (National Institute of Adult Continuing Education 2012). Moreover, it is very expensive to recruit under 18s. One analysis of the 2013–2014 recruitment intake estimates that it costs an additional £50 million to recruit junior soldiers rather than an all-adult intake (ForcesWatch 2014). See also Child Soldiers International (2019).

37 On the ethics of military training, see Dobos (Reference Dobos2020) and Surber (Reference Surber2023).

38 However, one might worry that material goods are incommensurable with the cost of taking on moral risk (Robillard and Strawser Reference Robillard and Strawser2022, 200).

References

REFERENCES

Arain, Mariam, Haque, Maliha, Johal, Lina, Mathur, Puja, Nel, Wynand, Rais, Afsha, Sandhu, Ranbir, et al. 2013. “Maturation of the Adolescent Brain.” Neuropsychiatric Disease and Treatment 9: 449–61.Google ScholarPubMed
Archer, Alfred, and Matheson, Benjamin. 2022. “Commemoration and Emotional Imperialism.” Journal of Applied Philosophy 39 (5): 761–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armed Forces Major Events Team. N.d. “Armed Forces Day Details.” https://armedforcesnortheastlincolnshire.co.uk/armed-forces-day/.Google Scholar
Bazargan, Saba. 2011. “The Permissibility of Aiding and Abetting Unjust Wars.” Journal of Moral Philosophy 8 (4): 513–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Booth, Samantha. 2021. “Queen’s Jubilee Book for Schools to Cost £12m.” Schools Week, September 28. https://schoolsweek.co.uk/queens-jubilee-book-for-schools-to-cost-12m/.Google Scholar
Brighouse, Harry. 2006. On Education. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brownlee, Kimberley. 2019. “Acting Defensively for the Sake of Our Attacker.” Journal of Moral Philosophy 16 (2): 105–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, Katherine Ann. 2022. “Childhood Trauma: A Major Risk Factor in the Military Recruitment of Young People.” BMJ Military Health. doi:10.1136/bmjmilitary-2022-002149Google Scholar
Child Soldiers International. 2019. “The British Armed Forces: Why Raising the Recruitment Age Would Benefit Everyone.” https://www.forceswatch.net/resources/the-british-armed-forces-why-raising-the-recruitment-age-would-benefit-everyone/.Google Scholar
Child Rights International Network. 2019. “Conscription by Poverty? Deprivation and Army Recruitment in the UK.” https://static1.squarespace.com/static/5afadb22e17ba3eddf90c02f/t/5d5bbf83278b3100018306a4/1566293898095/UK_recruitment_report_final.pdf.Google Scholar
Christensen, James. 2020. Global Justice. London: Red Globe Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, Gerald Allan. 1992. “Incentives, Inequality, and Community.” In The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, Vol. 13, ed. Petersen, G. B., 261329. Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press.Google Scholar
Community Innovations Enterprise and Forces in Mind Trust. 2015. “Call to Mind: A Framework for Action. Findings from the Review of Veterans and Family Members Mental and Related Health Needs Assessments.” Final Report. https://www.fim-trust.org/wp-content/uploads/jhna-england-call-to-mind.pdf.Google Scholar
Danilova, Natalia. 2015. The Politics of War Commemoration in the UK and Russia. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dannenbaum, Tom. 2018. The Crime of Aggression, Humanity, and the Soldier. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, Anna. 2022. “Children Should be Taught Patriotism and Not Be Ashamed to be British, MP says.” The Standard, April 20. https://www.standard.co.uk/news/education/patriotism-british-children-conservative-mp-b995300.html.Google Scholar
Davies, Quentin, Clark, Bill, and Sharp, Martin. 2008. “Report of Inquiry into National Recognition of our Armed Forces.” https://data.parliament.uk/DepositedPapers/Files/DEP2008-1296/DEP2008-1296.pdf.Google Scholar
Department for Education. 2013a. “New Funding for Military Ethos Projects.” https://www.gov.uk/government/news/new-funding-for-military-ethos-projects.Google Scholar
Department for Education. 2013b. “New Routes for Talented Ex-Armed Forces Personnel to become Teachers.” https://www.gov.uk/government/news/new-routes-for-talented-ex-armed-forces-personnel-to-become-teachers.Google Scholar
Department for Education. 2021. “Thousands More Pupils to Benefit.” https://www.gov.uk/government/news/thousands-more-pupils-to-benefit-from-cadet-programme.Google Scholar
Dixon, Paul. 2018. “Warrior Nation: War, Militarisation and British Democracy.” Report. https://www.forceswatch.net/wp-content/uploads/Warrior_Nation_web-1.pdf.Google Scholar
Dobos, Ned. 2020. Ethics, Security, and the War Machine: The True Cost of the Military. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dobos, Ned. 2023. “Pharmacological Prophylaxes against Moral Injury.” Monash Bioethics Review 41 (1): 3748.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Doward, Jamie. 2018. “Arms Industry Spends Millions to Promote Brands in Schools.” The Guardian, September 1. https://www.theguardian.com/world/2018/sep/01/arms-industry-spending-millions-normalise-weapons-in-schools.Google Scholar
Easton, Christina. 2022. “Teaching Liberal Values: The Case of Promoting ’British Values’ in Schools.” In Liberal Democratic Education: A Paradigm in Crisis, eds. Culp, Julian, Drerup, Johannes, de Groot, Isolde, Schinkel, Anders and Yacek, Douglas, 4766. Paderborn, Germany: Brill Mentis.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
English, Otto. 2017. “The Poppy Has Lost Its Original Meaning – Time to Ditch It.” Independent, November 1. https://www.independent.co.uk/voices/poppy-wear-why-not-remembrance-wars-soldiers-veterans-poppies-moeen-ali-a8031746.html?r=63745.Google Scholar
ForcesWatch. 2012. “We Shall Reach Them in the Classrooms: Promoting a ‘Military Ethos’ in Schools.” https://www.forceswatch.net/comment/we-shall-reach-them-in-the-classrooms-promoting-a-military-ethos-in-schools/.Google Scholar
ForcesWatch. 2014. “Army Recruitment: Comparative Cost-Effectiveness of Recruiting from Age 16 Versus Age 18.” https://www.forceswatch.net/wp-content/uploads/2014/09/army-recruitment-costs-2014.pdf.Google Scholar
ForcesWatch. 2015. “A Critical Response to ‘The British Armed Forces: Learning Resource 2014’.” https://www.forceswatch.net/wp-content/uploads/ForcesWatch_response_British_Armed_Forces_Learning_Resource.pdf.Google Scholar
ForcesWatch. 2017. “Does the Military Give Young People a ‘Leg Up’? The Armed Forces and Social Mobility.” https://www.forceswatch.net/wp-content/uploads/2017/07/armed_forces_and_social_mobility.pdf.Google Scholar
Fossey, Matt, and Hughes, Jamie Hacker. 2013. “Future Horizons Programme: Final Report.” Future Horizons Programme. https://www.fim-trust.org/wp-content/uploads/future-horizons-full-report.pdf.Google Scholar
Galston, William A. 2003. “A Sketch of Some Arguments for Conscription.” Philosophy and Public Policy Quarterly 23 (3): 27.Google Scholar
Gardner, John. 2013. “Criminals in Uniform.” In The Constitution of the Criminal Law, eds Duff, R. A., Farmer, Lindsay, Marshall, S. E., Renzo, Massimo and Tadros, Victor, 97118. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gee, David. 2007. “Informed Choice? Armed Forces Recruitment Practice in the United Kingdom.” https://antimili-youth.net/sites/default/files/informedchoiceweb.pdf.Google Scholar
Gee, David, and Goodman, Anna. 2013. “Young Age at Army Enlistment is Associated with Greater War Zone Risk: An Analysis of British Army Fatalities in Afghanistan.” Report, ForcesWatch and Child Soldiers International. https://www.forceswatch.net/wp-content/uploads/2013/08/Young_age_at_army_enlistment_greater_risks%28FINAL%29.pdf.Google Scholar
Gee, David, and Taylor, Rachel. 2016. “Is it Counterproductive to Enlist Minors into the Army?The RUSI Journal 161 (6): 3648.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gee, David. 2017. The First Ambush? Effects of Army Training and Employment. London: Veterans for Peace UK.Google Scholar
Gheaus, Anca, and Herzog, Lisa. 2016. “The Good of Work (Other Than Money!).” Journal of Social Philosophy 47 (1): 7089.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hackman, Daniel A., and Farah, Martha J.. 2009. “Socioeconomic Status and the Developing Brain.” Trends in Cognitive Sciences 13 (2): 6573.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hall, Leanna. 2017. “Poppy Fascism: What Is It?” Voice of London November 12. https://thevoiceoflondon.co.uk/poppy-fascism-what-is-it/Google Scholar
Hamilton, James T., and Morgan, Fiona. 2018. “Poor Information: How Economics Affects the Information Lives of Low Income Individuals.” International Journal of Communication 12: 2832–50.Google Scholar
Hand, Michael. 2011. “Patriotism in Schools.” Impact: Philosophical Perspectives on Education Policy 19: 140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harris, Diane, and Williams, Julian. 2012. “The Association of Classroom Interactions, Year Group and Social Class.” British Educational Research Journal 38 (3): 373–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hatfield, Chrissy. 2020. “Ministers Encourage Universities to Support Further Education for Veterans.” FE News, March 23. https://www.fenews.co.uk/skills/ministers-beg-universities-to-support-further-education-for-veterans/.Google Scholar
Howard, Jeffrey W. 2016. “Moral Subversion and Structural Entrapment.” The Journal of Political Philosophy 24 (1): 2446.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howard League for Penal Reform. 2011. “Report of the Inquiry into Former Armed Service Personnel in Prison.” https://howardleague.org/wp-content/uploads/2016/05/Military-inquiry-final-report.pdf.Google Scholar
House of Commons Defence Committee. 2005. “Duty of Care.” Third Report of Session 2004-05. https://publications.parliament.uk/pa/cm200405/cmselect/cmdfence/63/63.pdfGoogle Scholar
The Independent. 2016. “Theresa May’s Keynote Speech at Tory Conference in Full.” The Independent, October 5. https://www.independent.co.uk/news/uk/politics/theresa-may-speech-tory-conference-2016-in-full-transcript-a7346171.html.Google Scholar
Iverson, Amy C., Fear, Nicola T., Simonoff, Emily, Hull, Lisa, Horn, Oded, Greenberg, Neil, Hotopf, Matthew, et al. 2007. “Influence of Childhood Adversity on Health Among Male UK Military Personnel.” British Journal of Psychiatry 191 (6): 506–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, Sara B., Blum, Robert W., and Giedd, Jay N.. 2009. “Adolescent Maturity and the Brain: The Promise and Pitfalls of Neuroscience Research in Adolescent Health Policy.” Journal of Adolescent Health 45 (3):216–21.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kandiyali, Jan. 2023. “Sharing Burdensome Work.” The Philosophical Quarterly 73 (1): 143–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kishiyama, Mark M., Boyce, W. Thomas, Jimenez, Amy M., Perry, Lee M., and Knight, Robert T.. 2009. “Socioeconomic Disparities Affect Prefrontal Function in Children.” Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 21 (6): 1106–15.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kurtulmuş, Faik, and Kandiyali, Jan. Forthcoming. “Class and Inequality: Why the Media Fails the Poor.” In Routledge Handbook of Philosophy and Media Ethics, eds. Fox, Carl and Saunders, Joe. Abingdon, UK: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lazar, Seth. 2016. “Friends, Travel, Killing.” In Philosophers Take on the World, ed. Edmonds, David, 25–7. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Louise, Rhianna, and Sangster, Emma. 2019. “Selling the Military: A Critical Analysis of Contemporary Recruitment Marketing in the UK.” Report, Forceswatch and Medact. https://www.medact.org/2019/resources/reports/selling-the-military-a-critical-analysis-of-contemporary-recruitment-marketing/.Google Scholar
MacLean, Alair, and Elder, Glen. 2007. “Military Service in the Life Course.” Annual Review of Sociology 33: 175–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, Jeff. 2009. Killing in War. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, Jeff. 2013. “The Moral Responsibility of Volunteer Soldiers.” https://www.bostonreview.net/forum/moral-wounds-ethics-volunteer-military-service/.Google Scholar
MacManus, Deirdre, Dean, K., Al Bakir, M., Iversen, A. C., Hull, L., Fahy, T., Wessely, S., and Fear, N. T.. 2012. “Violent Behaviour in UK Military Personnel Returning Home After Deployment.” Psychological Medicine 42 (8): 1663–73.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
MacManus, Deirdre, Dean, Kimberley, Jones, Margaret, Rona, Roberto J., Greenberg, Neil, Hull, Lisa, Fahy, Tom, Wessely, Simon, and Fear, Nicola T.. 2013. “Violent Offending by UK Military Personnel Deployed to Iraq and Afghanistan: A Data Linkage Cohort Study.” The Lancet 381 (9870): 907–17.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Medact. 2016. “The Recruitment of Children by the UK Armed Forces: A Critique from Health Professionals.” https://www.medact.org/2016/resources/reports/recruitment-children-uk-armed-forces/.Google Scholar
Ministry of Defence. 2017. “30% of Officers Progress from the Ranks.” https://www.gov.uk/government/news/30-of-officers-progress-from-the-ranks.Google Scholar
Ministry of Defence. N.d.a. “Army Life.” https://jobs.army.mod.uk/regular-army/army-life/.Google Scholar
Ministry of Defence. N.d.b. “Armed Forces Day.” https://www.armedforcesday.org.uk/about/.Google Scholar
Ministry of Defence. 2022. “UK Armed Forces Biannual Diversity Statistics: April 2022.” https://www.gov.uk/government/statistics/uk-armed-forces-biannual-diversity-statistics-april-2022.Google Scholar
Moller, Dan. 2011. “Abortion and Moral Risk.” Philosophy 86 (337): 425–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moody-Adams, Michelle. 2022. “Coming to Terms With History.” The Raven. Spring Issue. https://ravenmagazine.org/magazine/coming-to-terms-with-history/.Google Scholar
Moriguchi, Yusuke, and Shinohara, Ikuko. 2019. “Socioeconomic Disparity in Prefrontal Development During Early Childhood.” Nature Scientific Reports 9: 2585. doi:10.1038/s41598-019-39255-6CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mullainathan, Sendhil, and Shafir, Eldar. 2013. Scarcity: Why Having Too Little Means So Much. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Munch, Luaritz Aastrup. 2022. “Digital Self-Defence: Why You Ought to Preserve Your Privacy for the Sake of Wrongdoers.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 25 (2): 233–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
National Institute of Adult Continuing Education. 2012. “Armed Forces Basic Skills. Longitudinal Study.” https://learningandwork.org.uk/wp-content/uploads/2020/02/Armed-Forces-Basic-Skills-Longitudinal-Study.pdf.Google Scholar
O’Connor, Robyn M., and Waddell, Stephanie. 2015. “What Works to Prevent Gang Involvement, Youth Violence and Crime. A Rapid Review of Interventions Delivered in The UK and Abroad.” Early Intervention Foundation. https://www.eif.org.uk/report/what-works-to-prevent-gang-involvement-youth-violence-and-crime-a-rapid-review-of-interventions-delivered-in-the-uk-and-abroad.Google Scholar
Oster, Candice, Morello, Andrea, Venning, Anthony, Redpath, Paula, and Lawn, Sharon. 2017. “The Health and Wellbeing Needs of Veterans: A Rapid Review.” BMC Psychiatry 17 (1): 414.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Oxford Economics. 2021. “The Wider Value of the British Army.” https://www.oxfordeconomics.com/resource/the-wider-value-of-the-british-army/.Google Scholar
Parr, Tom. 2022. “In Cash We Trust?Journal of Applied Philosophy. doi:10.1111/japp.12583.Google Scholar
Pattison, James. 2011. “The Legitimacy of the Military, Private Military and Security Companies, and Just War Theory.” European Journal of Political Theory 11 (2): 131–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quakers in Britain. 2021. “Written Evidence Submitted by Quakers in Britain to the Select Committee on the Armed Forces Bill.” https://committees.parliament.uk/writtenevidence/23947/pdf/.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 2005. Political Liberalism. Expanded edition. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Robillard, Michael J. 2017. “Risk, War, and the Dangers of Solider Identity.” Journal of Military Ethics 16 (3-4): 205–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robillard, Michael J., and Strawser, Bradley. 2022. Outsourcing Duty: The Moral Exploitation of the American Soldier. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenthal, Chelsea. Forthcoming. “An Ethically Risky Profession?Washington University Jurisprudence Review.Google Scholar
Ryan, Cheyney. 2022. “Epilogue.” In Outsourcing Duty: The Moral Exploitation of the American Soldier, eds. Robillard, Michael J. and Strawser, Bradley, 185–93. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ryan, Cheyney. 2009. The Chickenhawk Syndrome. Washington, DC: Rowan and Littlefield.Google ScholarPubMed
Sagdahl, Mathias S. 2018. “Conscription as a Morally Preferable Form of Military Recruitment.” Journal of Military Ethics 17 (4): 224–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schouten, Gina. 2016. “Is the Gendered Division of Labor a Problem of Distribution?” In Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy, Vol. 2, eds. Sobel, David, Vallentyne, Peter and Wall, Steven, 185208. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Scott, Sophie. 2015. “Cadet Units in State Schools: George Osborne Announces 50m Boost.” Schools Week, July 8. https://schoolsweek.co.uk/cadet-units-in-state-schools-george-osborne-announces-50m-boost/.Google Scholar
Shiner, Fionn. 2018. “What Is the White Poppy a Symbol Of? Why It’s So Controversial.” Mirror, October 15. https://www.mirror.co.uk/news/uk-news/what-white-poppy-symbol-of-13419756.Google Scholar
Strachan, Hew, Armour, Tanya, Healey, Pamela, and Smith, Melissa. 2010. “Report of the Task Force on the Military Covenant.” https://assets.publishing.service.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/27393/militarycovenanttaskforcerpt.pdf.Google Scholar
Strawser, Bradley J. Forthcoming. “The Supererogatory Moral Risks of Military Service.” In The Individualization of War: Rights, Liability, and Accountability in Contemporary Armed Conflict, eds. Welsh, Jennifer, Akande, Dapo, and Rodin, David, 89114. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Steinberg, Laurence. 2008. “A Social Neuroscience Perspective on Adolescent Risk-Taking.” Developmental Review 28 (1): 78106.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Surber, Regina S. 2023. “Military Training and Revisionist Just War Theory’s Practicability Problem.” The Journal of Ethics. doi:10.1007/s10892-023-09439-4.Google Scholar
Tadros, Victor. 2016a. “Unjust Wars Worth Fighting For.” Journal of Practical Ethics 4 (1): 52–78.Google Scholar
Tadros, Victor. 2016b. Wrongs and Crimes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tadros, Victor. 2020. “Distributing Responsibility.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 48 (3): 223–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tsai, George. 2016. “The Morality of State Symbolic Power.” Social Theory and Practice 42 (2): 318–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
UK Government. 2014. “News Story: Armed Forces Learning.” https://www.gov.uk/government/news/armed-forces-learning.Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael. 2006. Just and Unjust Wars, 4th edition. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Watson, Matthew. 2020. “Michael Gove’s War on Professional Historical Expertise: Conservative Curriculum Reform, Extreme Whig History and the Place of Imperial Heroes in Modern Multicultural Britain.” British Politics 16 (3): 271–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard. 1972. Morality: An Introduction to Ethics. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wolfendale, Jessica, and Portis, Stoney. 2021. “Toxic Warrior Identity, Accountability, and Moral Risk.” Journal of Military Ethics 20 (3-4): 163–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woolcock, Nicola, Ellery, Ben, and Grylls, George. 2021. “One Nation Song in Discord But Boris Johnson Sings its Praise.” The Times, June 24. https://www.thetimes.co.uk/article/one-britain-one-nation-dischord-boris-johnson-brexit-union-song-2pd5m33r7.Google Scholar
Wozniak, Peter. 2010. “Gove: Schools Will “Stop Trashing Our Past.” Politics.co.uk, October 5. https://www.politics.co.uk/news/2010/10/05/gove-schools-will-stop-trashing-our-past/.Google Scholar
Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.