Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-24T18:21:29.032Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Symmetric Spatial Games Without Majority Rule Equilibria*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 August 2014

Richard D. McKelvey
Affiliation:
Carnegie-Mellon University
Peter C. Ordeshook
Affiliation:
Carnegie-Mellon University

Abstract

The assumptions imposed in spatial models of election competition generally are restrictive in that they require either unidimensional issue spaces or symmetrically distributed electorate preferences. We attribute such assumptions to the reliance of these models on a single concept of a solution to the election game—pure strategy equilibria—and to the fact that such equilibria do not exist in general under less severe restrictions. This essay considers, then, the possibility that candidates adopt mixed minimax strategies. We show, for a general class of symmetric zero-sum two-person games, that the domain of these minimax strategies is restricted to a subset of the strategy space and that for spatial games this set not only exists, but if preferences are characterized by continuous densities, it is typically small. Thus, the hypothesis that candidates abide by mixed minimax strategies can limit considerably our expectation as to the policies candidates eventually advocate. Additionally, we examine the frequently blurred distinction between spatial conceptualizations of two-candidate elections and of committees, and we conclude that if pure strategy equilibria do not exist, this distinction is especially important since committees and elections can produce entirely different outcomes.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 1976

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Downs, Anthony, An Economic Theory of Democracy (N.Y.: Harper & Row, 1957)Google Scholar..

2 One exception to the use of this condition is Hinich, Melvin J., Ledyard, John O. and Ordeshook, Peter C., “A Theory of Electoral Equilibrium: A Spatial Analysis Based on the Theory of Games,” Journal of Politics, 35 (February, 1973), 154193CrossRefGoogle Scholar. There, however, the restrictive assumption of continuous concave-convex payoff functions is used.

3 Briefly, a two-person zero-sum game is symmetric if the strategy sets of both players are identical, if the value of the game to both players is zero and if φ1(x,y) = φ2(y,x) for all x and y—i.e., if they interchange strategies, they interchange payoffs. A constant sum game, moreover, is equivalent to a zero-sum game since for any constant sum, there exists a positive monotonic transformation of the payoffs that renders the game zero-sum (e.g., substitute the payoffs, 1, 0, −1 for 1, 1/2, 0).

4 Plott, Charles R., “A Notion of Equilibrium and its Possibility Under Majority Rule,” American Economic Review, 57 (September, 1967), 787806Google Scholar; and Sloss, Judith, “Stable Outcomes in Majority Rule Voting Games,” Public Choice, 15 (Summer, 1973), 1948CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 See Davis, Otto A., DeGroot, M., and Hinich, Melvin J., “Social Preference Orderings and Majority Rule,” Econometrica, 40 (January, 1972)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Hoyer, R. W. and Mayer, Lawrence S., “Comparing Strategies in a Spatial Model of Electoral Competition,” American Journal of Political Science (1974)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 Von Neumann, John and Morgenstern, Oskar, Theory of Games and Economic Behavior, 2nd ed. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1947)Google Scholar.

7 See, for example, Riker, William H. and Ordeshook, Peter C., An Introduction to Positive Political Theory (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1973), p. 340Google Scholar, and McKelvey, Richard D., “Policy Related Voting and Electoral Equilibrium,” Econometrica, 43 (September, 1975), 815843CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Formally, if B is a σ-algebra of sets in X, a probability measure P:B → R is a set function satisfying the usual probability axioms. I. e., for each A, BεB, O < P(A) < 1 and A ⋂ B = Φ ⇒ P(A) + P(B) = P(A∪B). We use the notation P(x) = P({x}).

9 Note that Theorems 1 and 2 do not imply that there cannot exist mixed minimax strategies that give positive weight to positions not in admissible or weakly admissible sets (recall that minimax strategies need not be unique). With respect to Theorem 3, however, it is straightforward to show that such strategies cannot exist outside of the Pareto optimals, Q. Briefly, from the definition of Pareto optimality we see that the weak inequality in expression (1) holds for all zεX, while strict inequality holds for at least one zεX, namely x. Thus, any strategy, P, that gives positive weight to some position not in Q, can be strictly dominated by a strategy P′. In the case of a finite strategy space, for example, if P(y) ≠ 0 for some yεQ, we can define P′ thus,

P′(z) = P(z), zεQ, z ≠ x

P′(y) = 0

P′(x) = P(y) + P(x), xεQ, x ≻ y

By successively applying this transformation for all y Q to which P gives positive weight, we arrive at a strategy that dominates P but which gives weight only to Q. This result is established elsewhere by Ordeshook, Peter C., “Pareto Optimality in Electoral Competition,” American Political Science Review, 6 (December, 1971), 11411145CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10 An important issue that Theorem 4 and its corollary fail to address is whether minimax strategy solutions exist in simple multidimensional elections. We know from the minimax theorem that if X is finite such strategies necessarily exist. From a practical perspective, moreover, this is perhaps the most reasonable context of election competition in the sense that the real constraints on candidate strategies and their perceptions of alternatives may render the game finite. For an infinite strategy space, however, establishing existence is more problematical. This is especially true in our analysis since φ is not continuous (for a proof that continuous zero-sum games over closed convex strategy spaces possess minimax solutions see Owen, Guillermo, Game Theory [Philadelphia: W. B. Saunders, 1968], pp. 7678)Google Scholar. We conjecture, nevertheless, that the class of spatial games being considered here always possess minimax solutions.

11 If the number of voters is finite and even, this assertion is not strictly true, given our definition of a median in terms of hyperplanes. Thus, if C is odd or infinite, there exists a unique median in every direction, whereas for C even, median hyperplanes are not necessarily unique. That is, for C even, a median in a particular direction can be a bounded region (e.g., for two voters on a line, the median is the set of all positions between the two ideal points). If we extend our notion of a median to bounded regions, the assertion follows. The definition of medians in terms of hyperplanes is simply a convenience for reducing notational complexity.

12 The identification of I * in theory is simple in two-dimensions: identify all median lines and hence their intersections, and take the convex hull of these intersections. To generate Figure 8, however, a computer is essential to calculate and plot these median lines for the several values of λ. Identification of the weakly admissible set in Figure 5, on the other hand, is accomplished by trial and error. We note simply that a point at the center of the triangle dominates all of the excluded points within the triangle.

13 We note also that if we decrease the distance between the means of the two bivariate normals used to construct Figure 8 (or, equivalents, increase their variances), the site of I * decreases. A distance of 5σ, moreover, seems the extreme of opinion polarization.

14 The theorem is outlined in Owen, , Game Theory, p. 31, 3637Google Scholar, and proved in Karlin, Samuel, Mathematical Methods and Theory in Games, Programming and Economics, Vol. 1 (Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1959), pp. 179189Google Scholar. As proved, the theorem applies, of course, only to finite games. Thus, we can only conjecture that it applies to infinite solvable games as well.

15 For a discussion of n-person majority games without side payments (the context of a spatial conceptualization of preferences) see Wilson, Robert, “A Game-Theoretic Analysis of Social Choice,” in Lieberman, B., ed., Social Choice (N.Y.: Gordon and Breach, 1971), pp. 393408Google Scholar; and Wilson, , “Stable Coalition Proposals in Majority Rule Voting,” Journal of Economic Theory, 3 (September, 1971), 254271CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

16 Usually, a bargaining set is defined in terms of a payoff configuration and a particular coalition structure. Here, however, exposition is eased if we consider only the payoff configuration x. Note also that payoffs are defined in game theory in terms of utility, whereas here x is a policy position. This transformation of terminology is of no consequence to our analysis owing to the 1 to 1 correspondence (given our assumptions about utility) between payoff configurations and spatial position.

Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.