Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T18:11:59.423Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Politics of Political Science: “Value-free” Theory and the Wolin–Strauss Dust-Up of 1963

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 November 2006

BENJAMIN R. BARBER
Affiliation:
University of Maryland

Abstract

Political theory's relationship with political science over the last 60 years has been fraught with ambiguity and weighed down by epistemological tensions in a manner that suggests an old and extremely prickly marriage. To some, political theory has been nothing less than the theoretical foundation of political science as a discipline—the conceptual and epistemological ground for each and every subfield, cherished and nurtured by tolerant, even ecumenical political science departments. To others, it has been merely a distraction, a needless normative diversion from the empirical responsibilities of hard social science by those who do not understand its rigors. As was perhaps more common in the first half of the twentieth century, some have continued to see in political science and political theory complementary perspectives that need and entail one another, two sides of how we establish and balance the human sciences, doing empirical science even as we assess its epistemological standards and methods. But others have regarded the two as preternaturally antagonistic. At the height of the behavioral revolution in the 1960s, a few self-styled “hardboiled” scientists dismissed theory altogether as little more than mythology: moralizing fairy tales dressed up as a kind of prescriptive philosophy that confounded facts and values. But the real crux of the debate between political theory and political science has been the relationship of political science to politics, as exemplified in historian Alfred A. Cobban's scathing comment excoriating political science as mostly a device for avoiding politics without achieving science“The political scientist, in so far as he wishes to remain a scientist, is limited to the study of techniques. A good deal of what is called political science, I must confess, seems, to me a device, invented by academic persons, avoiding that dangerous subject politics, without achieving science” (Cobban 1960, 240).. Cobban's challenge was taken up by many theorists, including Leo Strauss, whose blunt rebuke to the “new” political science suggesting that it was doing little more than fiddling while Rome was burning inaugurated a debate that in 1962 set this mostly fire-proof journal aflame“One may say (of the new political science),” wrote Strauss, “that it fiddles while Rome burns. It is excused by two facts: it does not know that it fiddles, and it does not know that Rome burns”(Strauss 1962, 327)..

Type
“THE EVOLUTION OF POLITICAL SCIENCE” ESSAYS
Copyright
© 2006 by the American Political Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adorno Theodore W., and Max Horkheimer. 1972. Dialectic of Enlightenment. New York: Herder and Herder.
Barber Benjamin. 2003. Fear's Empire: War, Terrorism and Democracy. New York: Norton.
Becker Carl L. 1932. The Heavenly City of the Eighteenth Century Philosophers. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Berman Paul. 2003. Terror and Liberalism. New York: Norton.
Berns Walter. 1962. “Voting Studies.” In Essays on the Scientific Study of Politics, ed. Herbert J. Storing. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.
Bloom Allan. 1988. The Closing of the American Mind. New York: Simon & Shuster.
Brickhouse T.C., and Nicholas D. Smith. 2001. The Trial and Execution of Socrates: Sources and Controversies. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Brzezinski Zbigniew. 1967. Ideology and Power in Soviet Politics. New York: Praeger.
Cobban Alfred A. 1960. In Search of Humanity: The Role of the Enlightenment in Modern History. New York: George Braziller.
Halper Stefan. 2004. America Alone: American Conservatives and the Global Order. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hartz Louis. 1955. The Liberal Tradition in America. New York: Harcourt, Brace and World.
Kuhn Thomas. 1962. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press.
Marcuse Herbert. 1964. One Dimensional Man. Boston: Beacon Press.
Norton Anne. 2004. Leo Strauss and the Politics of the American Empire. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Popper Karl R. 1944. The Poverty of Historicism. London: Routledge.
Popper Karl R. The Open Society and Its Enemies. Two volumes, London: Routledge.
Schaar John H., and Sheldon S. Wolin. 1963. “Essays on the Scientific Study of Politics: A Critique.” American Political Science Review 57 (March): 12550.Google Scholar
Smith Steven B. 2006. Reading Leo Strauss: Politics, Philosophy, Judaism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Stone I.F. 1989. The Trial of Socrates. New York: Anchor Reprint Edition.
Storing Herbert J. 1963. “Replies to Schaar and Wolin: I.” American Political Science Review 57 (March): 15152.Google Scholar
Strauss Leo. 1962. “An Epilogue.” In Essays on the Scientific Study of Politics, ed. Herbert J. Storing. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.
Strauss Leo. 1963. “Replies to Schaar and Wolin: II.” American Political Science Review 57 (March): 15255.Google Scholar
Weinsten Leo. 1962. “Scientific Propaganda.” In Essays on the Scientific Study of Politics, ed. Herbert J. Storing. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.
Weldon T. D. 1953. The Vocabulary of Politics. London: Penguin.
Wolin Sheldon S. 2004. Politics and Vision: Continuity and Innovation in Western Political Thought. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.