Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-6bf8c574d5-7jkgd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-26T00:31:26.293Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Kant's Ideas of Reason

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 February 2025

Katharina T. Kraus
Affiliation:
Johns Hopkins University

Summary

This Element introduces Kant's ideas of reason, focussing on the ideas of theoretical reason in the study of nature. It offers a novel interpretation that shows how such ideas as the soul, the world-whole, and God provide a regulative orientation for coping with human perspectival situatedness in the world. This perspectivalist interpretation reconciles two interpretive tendencies: a realist reading, according to which ideas refer to real things independent of the human mind, and a fictionalist reading, according to which ideas are heuristic fictions without reference to anything real. The perspectivalist interpretation recognizes two functions of ideas: first, ideas outline domains of possible objects, thus presenting the human mind with contexts of intelligibility in which the cognition of objects can be meaningful at all. Second, ideas project an ultimate reality as a focus imaginarius, which serves as a normative ideal for evaluating the success of human inquiries into nature.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781009024273
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 06 March 2025

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Bibliography

Primary Sources

Secondary Sources

English translations are according to The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant, edited by Guyer, Paul and Wood, Allen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992–).Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1998). Critique of Pure Reason. Guyer, Paul/Wood, Allen (trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (2000). Critique of the Power of Judgment. Guyer, Paul/Matthews, Eric (trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (2003). Theoretical Philosophy, 1755–1770. Walford, David/Meerbote, Ralf (trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (2004). Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science. Friedman, Michael (trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (2004). Lectures on Logic. Young, J. Michael (trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (2010). Theoretical Philosophy after 1781. Allison, Henry E./Heath, Peter/Hatfield, Gary/Friedman, Michael (trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Abela, Paul (2006). ‘The Demands of Systematicity: Rational Judgment and the Structure of Nature’. In Graham Bird (ed.) A Companion to Kant. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 408422.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adickes, Erich (1924). Kant und das Ding an sich. Berlin: Verlag Rolf Heise.Google Scholar
Adickes, Erich (1927). Kant und die Als-Ob-Philosophie. Stuttgart: Frommans Verlag.Google Scholar
Allais, Lucy (2015). Manifest Reality: Kant’s Idealism and his Realism. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allison, Henry E. (2004). Kant’s Transcendental Idealism: An Interpretation and Defense; Revised and Enlarged Edition. New Haven: Yale University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ameriks, Karl (2003). Interpreting Kant’s Critiques. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ameriks, Karl (2006). ‘A Common-Sense Kant?’. In Ameriks, Karl (ed.) Kant and the Historical Turn. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 108‒133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, R. Lanier (2014). The Poverty of Conceptual Truth: Kant’s Analytic/Synthetic Distinction and the Limits of Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bacon, Francis (1620/2012). New Organon, or True Directions Concerning the Interpretation of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Baumgarten, Alexander G. (1750/1758). Aesthetica. Frankfurt an der Oder: G. Olms.Google Scholar
Breitenbach, Angela (2014). ‘Biological Purposiveness and Analogical Reflection’. In Goy, Ina and Watkins, Eric (eds.) Kant’s Theory of Biology. Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. 131148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchdahl, Gerd (1967). ‘The Relation between “Understanding” and “Reason”’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 67, 209226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchdahl, Gerd (1969). Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Science. The Classical Origins: Descartes to Kant. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Buchdahl, Gerd (1971). ‘The Conception of Lawlikeness in Kant’s Philosophy of Science’. Synthese, 23(1), 2446.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Callanan, John (2021). ‘The Boundary of Pure Reason’. In Thielke, Peter (ed.) Kant’s Prolegomena. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 133153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cassirer, Ernst (1999). Das Erkenntnisproblem in der Philosophie und Wissenschaft der neueren Zeit. Zweiter Band. In Recki, Birgit (ed.) Gesammelte Werke. Hamburger Ausgabe. Band 3. Hamburg: Meiner.Google Scholar
Chaplin, Rosalind (2024). ‘Kant on the Conceptual Possibility of Actually Infinite Tota Synthetica’. Kantian Review, https://doi.org/10.1017/S1369415424000220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chignell, Andrew (2007a). ‘Belief in Kant’. The Philosophical Review, 116(3), 323360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chignell, Andrew (2007b). ‘Kant’s Concepts of Justification’. Noûs, 41(1), 3363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chignell, Andrew (2014). ‘Modal Motivations for Noumenal Ignorance: Knowledge, Cognition, and Coherence’. Kant-Studien, 105(4), 573597.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caimi, Mario (1995). ‘Über eine wenig beachtete Deduktion der regulativen Ideen’. Kant-Studien, 86(3), 308320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dyck, Corey (2014). Kant and Rational Psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Falkenburg, Brigitte (2020). Kant’s Cosmology: From the Pre-Critical System to the Antinomy of Pure Reason. Berlin: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fichte, Johann G. (1796–1799). Wissenschaftslehre nova methodo. In Lauth, Reinhard, Jacobs, Hans, Gliwitzky, Hans, and Fuchts, Eric (eds.) J. G. Fichte: Gesamtausgabe der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften. Volume IV, Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann, 1964‒.Google Scholar
Friedman, Michael (2013). Kant’s Construction of Nature: A Reading of the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frierson, Patrick (2022). ‘What is the Idea of the Soul? Comments on Katharina Kraus, Kant on Self-Knowledge and Self-Formation’. Kantian Review, 27(3), 475481.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gadamer, Hans-Georg (1960). Wahrheit und Methode. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.Google Scholar
Geiger, Ido (2003) ‘Is the Assumption of a Systematic Whole of Empirical Concepts a Necessary Condition of Knowledge?Kant-Studien, 94(3), 273298.Google Scholar
Geiger, Ido (2022). Kant and the Claims of the Empirical World: A Transcendental Reading of the Critique of the Power of Judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gerson, Lloyd (2013). From Plato to Platonism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah (2006). ‘Empirical Concepts and the Content of Experience’. European Journal of Philosophy, 14(3), 349372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah (2017). ‘Why Must We Presuppose the Systematicity of Nature?’ In Massimi, Michela and Breitenbach, Angela (eds.) Kant and the Laws of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 7188.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grier, Michelle (1997). ‘Kant on the Illusion of a Systematic Unity of Knowledge’. History of Philosophy Quarterly, 14, 128.Google Scholar
Grier, Michelle (2001). Kant’s Doctrine of Transcendental Illusion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guyer, Paul (1979). Kant and the Claims of Taste. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul (1990). ‘Reason and Reflective Judgment: Kant on the Significance of Systematicity’. Noûs, 24, 1743.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guyer, Paul (2003). ‘Kant on the Systematicity of Nature: Two Puzzles’. History of Philosophy Quarterly, 20(3), 277295.Google Scholar
Hegel, Georg W. F. (1807). Phänomenologie des Geistes. Translated as Phenomenology of Spirit, by Pinkard, Terry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2017.Google Scholar
Heidegger, Martin (1927). Sein und Zeit. Translated as Being and Time, by John Macquarrie, and Robinson, Edward. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1962.Google Scholar
Hoffer, Noam (2019). ‘Kant’s Regulative Metaphysics of God and the Lawfulness of Nature’. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 57(2), 217239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffer, Noam (2023). ‘Kant’s Regulative Essentialism and the Unknowability of Real Essences’. European Journal of Philosophy, 31(4), 887901.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hogan, Desmond (2009). ‘How to Know Unknowable Things in Themselves’. Noûs, 43(1), 4963.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hogan, Desmond (2021). ‘Handedness, Idealism, and Freedom’. The Philosophical Review, 130(3), 385449.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howard, Stephen (2022a). ‘Kant on Limits, Boundaries, and the Positive Function of Ideas’. European Journal of Philosophy, 30(1), 6478.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howard, Stephen (2022b). ‘From the Boundary of the World to the Boundary of Reason: The First Antinomy and the Development of Kant’s Critical Philosophy’. HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science, 12(1), 225241.Google Scholar
Howard, Stephen (2024). ‘The Cosmological Ideas in Kant’s Critical Philosophy: Their Unique Status and Twofold Regulative Use’. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, https://doi.org/10.1111/sjp.12529.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, David (1748/2007). An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Husserl, Edmund (1900). Logische Untersuchungen. Erster Band: Prolegomena zur reinen Logik. In Holenstein, Edmund (ed.) Husserliana XVIII. The Hague: Nijhoff, 1975.Google Scholar
Kaplan, David (1989). ‘Demonstratives’. In Almog, Joseph, Perry, John, and Wettstein, Howard (eds.) Themes from Kaplan. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 481563.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (1986). ‘Projecting the Order of Nature’. In Butts, Robert (ed.) Kant’s Philosophy of Physical Science. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 201235.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraus, Katharina (2018). ‘The Soul as the “Guiding Idea” of Psychology: Kant on Scientific Psychology, Systematicity, and the Idea of the Soul’. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 71, 7788.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraus, Katharina (2020). Kant on Self-Knowledge and Self-Formation. The Nature of Inner Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraus, Katharina (2022). ‘Précis of Kant on Self-Knowledge and Self-Formation and Replies to Critics’. Kantian Review, 27(3), 491508.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraus, Katharina (2023). ‘Contemporary Kantian Philosophy of Science’. In Baiasu, Sorin and Timmons, Mark (eds.) The Kantian Mind. London: Routledge, pp. 568580.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kreines, James (2009). ‘Kant on the Laws of Nature and the Limitations of our Knowledge’. European Journal of Philosophy, 17(4), 527558.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kreines, James (2017). ‘Kant on the Laws of Nature: Restrictive Inflationism and Its Philosophical Advantages’. The Monist, 100(3), 326341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leibniz, Gottfried W. (1693). De L’Horizon de la Doctrine Humaine. La Restitution Universelle (Bibliotheque Des Textes Philosophiques). Paris: Vrin (1991).Google Scholar
Lewis, David (1980). ‘Index, Context, and Content’. In Kanger, Stig and Öhman, Sven (eds.) Philosophy and Grammar. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 79100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longuenesse, Béatrice (1998). Kant and the Capacity to Judge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longuenesse, Béatrice (2005). Kant on the Human Standpoint. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Makkreel, Rudolf (1990). Imagination and Interpretation in Kant: The Hermeneutical Import of the Critique of Judgment. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Maly, Sebastian (2011). Kant über die symbolische Erkenntnis Gottes. Berlin: De Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Massimi, Michela (2017). ‘What Is This Thing Ccalled “Scientific Knowledge”? Kant on Imaginary Standpoints and the Regulative Role of Reason’. Kant Yearbook, 9, 6383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Massimi, Michela (2021). ‘Points of View. Kant on Perspectival Knowledge’. Synthese (Supplement 13), 198, 3279–3296.Google Scholar
Massimi, Michela and Breitenbach, Angela (eds.) (2017). Kant and the Laws of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, John (1994). Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McLaughlin, Peter (2014). ‘Transcendental Presuppositions and Ideas of Reason’. Kant-Studien, 105(4), 554572.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McNulty, Michael B. (2015). ‘Rehabilitating the Regulative Use of Reason: Kant on Empirical and Chemical Laws’. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science (Part A), 54, 110.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Meier, Georg F. (1752). Vernunftlehre. Halle: J. J. Gebauer.Google Scholar
Melamedoff-Vosters, Damian (2022). ‘Truthmaker Noumenalism’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 100(1), 4055.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Thomas (1986). The View from Nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nassar, Dalia (2016). ‘Analogical Reflection As a Source for the Science of Life: Kant and the Possibility of the Biological Sciences’. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 58, 5766.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
O’Shea, James (1997). ‘The needs of the Understanding: Kant on Empirical Laws and Regulative Ideals’. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 5, 216254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pickering, Marc (2016). ‘Kant’s Theoretical Reasons for Belief in Things in Themselves’. Kant-Studien, 107(4), 589616.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Proops, Ian (2021). The Fiery Test of Critique: A Reading of Kant’s Dialectic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Posy, Carl (1981). ‘The Language of Appearances and Things in Themselves’. Synthese, 47(2), 313352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Posy, Carl (1983). ‘Dancing to the Antinomy: A Proposal for Transcendental Idealism’. American Philosophical Quarterly, 20(1), 8194.Google Scholar
Ritter, Joachim, Hinske, Norbert, Engfer, Hans Jurgen, Janssen, Paul, and Scherner, Maximilian (1974). ‘Horizont’. In Ritter, Joachim (ed.) Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie Vol. 3. Stuttgart: Schwabe Verlag, pp. 11881206.Google Scholar
Rohlf, Michael (2010). ‘The Ideas of Pure Reason’. In Guyer, Paul (ed.) Cambridge Companion to Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 190209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosefeldt, Tobias (2021). ‘Kant on Decomposing Synthesis and the Intuition of Infinite Space’. Philosophers’ Imprint, 22(1), 123.Google Scholar
Rush, Fred (2000) ‘Reason and Regulation in Kant’. Review of Metaphysics, 53(4), 837862.Google Scholar
Schafer, Karl (2023). Kant’s Reason: The Unity of Reason and the Limits of Comprehension in Kant. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spagnesi, Lorenzo (2022). ‘The Idea of God and the Investigation of Nature in Kant’s Transcendental Dialectic’. Kantian Review, 27(2), 279297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spagnesi, Lorenzo (2023a). ‘A Rule-Based Account of the Regulative Use of Reason in Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason’. European Journal of Philosophy, 31(3), 673688.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spagnesi, Lorenzo (2023b). ‘The Systematic Unity of Reason and Empirical Truth in Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason’. Kant-Studien, 114(3), 435462.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spohn, Wolfgang (2016). ‘Three Kinds of Worlds and Two Kinds of Truth’. Philosophical Studies, 173(5), 13351359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stang, Nicholas (2016). Kant’s Modal Metaphysics. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stang, Nicholas (forthcoming). ‘Why Should Metaphysics be Systematic? Contemporary Answers and Kant’s’. In Segal, Aaron and Stang, Nicholas (eds.) Systematic Metaphysics: Historical and Contemporary Perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stevenson, Leslie (2003). ‘Opinion, Belief or Faith, and Knowledge’. Kantian Review, 7, 72101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sturm, Thomas (2009). Kant und die Wissenschaften vom Menschen. Paderborn: Mentis.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vaihinger, Hans (1911). Die Philosophie des Als Ob. System der theoretischen, praktischen und religiösen Fiktionen der Menschheit auf Grund eines idealistischen Positivismus: Mit einem Anhang über Kant und Nietzsche. Berlin: Reuther & Reichard.Google Scholar
Van Inwagen, Peter (2008). Metaphysics: An Introduction. 3rd ed. Philadelphia: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Watkins, Eric (2013). ‘Kant on Infima Species’. In Ferrarin, Alfredo, Rocca, Claudio La, and Ruffing, Margit (eds.) Kant und die Philosophie in weltbürgerlicher Absicht: Akten des XI. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. 283296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watkins, Eric (2016). ‘The Unconditioned and the Absolute in Kant and Early German Romanticism’. Kant Yearbook, 8(1), 117–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watkins, Eric (2019a). Kant on Laws. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watkins, Eric (2019b). ‘Kant on Real Conditions’. In Waibel, Violette L. and Ruffing, Margit (eds.) Proceedings of the XII. International Kant Congress Nature and Freedom. Berlin: De Gruyte, pp. 11331140.Google Scholar
Watkins, Eric and Willaschek, Marcus (2017). ‘Kant’s Account of Cognition’. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 55(1), 83112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watkins, Eric and Willaschek, Marcus (2020). ‘Kant on Cognition and Knowledge’. Synthese, 197, 31953213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Willaschek, Marcus (2018). Kant on the Sources of Metaphysics: The Dialectic of Pure Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wuerth, Julian (2014). Kant on Mind, Action, and Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ypi, Lea (2021). The Architectonic of Reason: Purposiveness and Systematic Unity in Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zuckert, Rachel (2007). Kant on Beauty and Biology: An Interpretation of the Critique of Judgement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zuckert, Rachel (2017). ‘Empirical Scientific Investigation and the Ideas of Reason’ In Massimi, Michela and Breitenbach, Angela (eds.) Kant and the Laws of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 89107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zuckert, Rachel (2020). ‘Attempting to Exit the Human Perspective: A Priori Experimentation in Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason’. In Crețu, Ana-Maria and Massimi, Michela (eds.) Knowledge from a Human Point of View. Berlin: Springer, pp. 118.Google Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Kant's Ideas of Reason
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Kant's Ideas of Reason
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Kant's Ideas of Reason
Available formats
×