Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-6bf8c574d5-b4m5d Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-20T08:18:32.395Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Kant on the History and Development of Practical Reason

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 January 2025

Olga Lenczewska
Affiliation:
Florida State University

Summary

This Element's focus is Kant's history of human reason: his teleological vision of the past development of our rational capacities from their very emergence until Kant's own 'age of Enlightenment.' One of the goals is to connect Kant's speculative account of the very beginning of rationality – a topic that has thus far been largely neglected in Kantian scholarship – to his well-known theory of humankind's progress. The Element elucidates Kant's hopes with regard to reason's future progress and his guidelines for how to achieve this progress by unifying them with his vision of reason's past. Another goal is to bring more attention to Kant's essay 'Conjectural Beginning of Human History,' where this account is presented, and to show that this unusual text does not stand in conflict with Kant's philosophy and is not merely tangentially related to it, but illuminates and complements certain aspects of his critical philosophy.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781009216760
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 30 January 2025

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allison, Henry (2009). “Teleology and History in Kant: The Critical Foundations of Kant’s Philosophy of History.Kant’s “Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Aim”: A Critical Guide, ed. Rorty, Amélie O & Schmidt, James. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Basedow, Johann B. (1752). Inusitata et optima honestioris iuverntutis erudiendae methodus, Magister thesis, University of Kiel.Google Scholar
Basedow, Johann B. (1774). Das in Dessau errichtete Philanthropinum, eine Schule der Menschenfreundschaf. Leipzig: Crusius.Google Scholar
Batterman, Robert W. & Rice, Collin C. (2014). “Minimal Model Explanations.Philosophy of Science 81(3), 349–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beiser, Frederick C. (1987). The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berry, Christopher J. (1974). “Adam Smith’s Considerations on Language.Journal of the History of Ideas 35(1), 130–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Booth, W. (2009). “Reason and History: Kant’s Other Copernican Revolution.Kant-Studien 74(1), 5671.Google Scholar
Brandt, Reinhard (2007). Die Bestimmung des Menschen bei Kant. Hamburg: Meiner.Google Scholar
Brown, Garrett W. (2009). Grounding Cosmopolitanism: From Kant to the Idea of a Cosmopolitan Constitution. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caswell, Matthew (2006). “The Value of Humanity and Kant’s Conception of Evil.Journal of the History of Philosophy 44(4), 635–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cavallar, Georg (2012). “Cosmopolitanisms in Kant’s Philosophy.Ethics and Global Politics 5(2), 95118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cavallar, Georg (2014). “Sources of Kant’s Cosmopolitanism: Basedow, Rousseau, and Cosmopolitan Education.Studies in Philosophy and Education 33(4), 369–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chakrabarty, Dipesh (2016). “Humanities in the Anthropocene: The Crisis of an Enduring Kantian Fable.New Literary History 47(2–3), 377–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, Alix (2012). “Enabling the Realization of Humanity: The Anthropological Dimension of Education.” Kant and Education: Interpretations and Commentary, ed. Roth, Klas & Supernant, Chris. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Deligiorgi, Katerina (2002). “Universalizability, Publicity, and Communication: Kant’s Conception of Reason.European Journal of Philosophy 10(2), 143–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deligiorgi, Katerina (2005). Kant and the Culture of Enlightenment. New York: SUNY Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deligiorgi, Katerina (2017). “The Philosopher as Legislator: Kant on History.The Palgrave Kant Handbook, ed. Altman, M.. London: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Evnine, Simon (1993). “Hume, Conjectural History, and the Uniformity of Human Nature.Journal of the History of Philosophy, 31(4), 589606.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Formosa, Paul (2012). “From Discipline to Autonomy: Kant’s Theory of Moral Development.Kant and Education: Interpretations and Commentary, ed. Roth, Klas & Supernant, Chris. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Forst, Rainer (2017). “Political Liberalism: A Kantian View.” Ethics 128(1), 123–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frierson, Patrick R. (2013). What Is the Human Being? Oxford: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaus, Gerald (1995). “The Rational, the Reasonable and Justification.The Journal of Political Philosophy, 3, 234–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gerald., Gaus (1999). “Reasonable Pluralism and the Domain of the Political: How the Weaknesses of John Rawls’s Political Liberalism can be Overcome by a Justificatory Liberalism.Inquiry, 4, 229–58.Google Scholar
Gode, Alexander (1986). “Introduction.On the Origin of Language: Jean Jacques Rousseau’s Essay on the Origin of Languages & Johann Gottfried Herder’s Essay On the Origin of Language, trans. John H. Moran. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Grenberg, Jeanine M. (2009). “Social Dimensions of Kant’s Conception of Radical Evil.Kant’s Anatomy of Evil, ed. Anderson-Gold, Sharon & Muchnik, Pablo. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul (2009). “The Crooked Timber of Mankind”: Kant’s “Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Aim” – A Critical Guide, ed. Rorty, Amélie O. & Schmidt, James. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Herder, Johann Gottfried (1986). On the Origin of Language, trans. John H. Moran. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Herder, Johann Gottfried (2015). On World History: An Anthology, ed. Adler, Hans & Menze, Ernest A.. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Herman, Barbara (2009). “A Habitat for Humanity.Kant’s “Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Aim”: A Critical Guide, ed. Rorty, Amélie O. & Schmidt, James. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Höpfl, Harro M. (1987). “From Savage to Scotsman: Conjectural History in the Scottish Enlightenment.Journal of British Studies 17(2), 1940.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, David (2018). The Natural History of Religion. Dallas: Veritatis Splendor Publications.Google Scholar
Kain, Philip J. (1989). “Kant’s Political Theory and Philosophy of History.Clio 18: 325–45.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1996a). “An Answer to the Question: What Is Enlightenment?Practical Philosophy, trans. Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1996b). What Does It Mean to Orient Oneself in Thinking? In Religion and Rational Theology, trans. Allen W. Wood & George di Giovanni. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1998). Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason, trans. Allen W. Wood & George di Giovanni. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1999a). “On the Common Saying: That May be Correct in Theory, but It Is of No Use in Practice.” Practical Philosophy, trans. Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1999b). The Metaphysics of Morals. Practical Philosophy, trans. Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1999c). Toward Perpetual Peace. Practical Philosophy, trans. Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (2000). Critique of the Power of Judgment. trans. Paul Guyer & Matthews, Eric. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (2005). Notes and Fragments, trans. Curtis Bowman, Guyer, Paul & Rauscher, Frederick. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (2006). Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View, trans. Robert B. Louden. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (2007a). “Conjectural Beginning of Human History.” Anthropology, History, and Education, trans. Allen. W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (2007b). Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Aim. Anthropology, History, and Education, trans. Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (2009). Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Paul Guyer & Wood, Allen W.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (2012). Lectures on Anthropology, trans. Robert B. Louden & Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (2015). Critique of Practical Reason, trans. Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kleingeld, Pauline (1999). “Kant, History, and the Idea of Moral Development.History of Philosophy Quarterly 16(1).Google Scholar
Kleingeld, Pauline (2009). “Kant’s Changing Cosmopolitanism.Kant’s “Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Aim”: A Critical Guide, ed. Rorty, Amélie O & Kleingeld, Pauline (2012). Kant and Cosmopolitanism: The Philosophical Ideal of World Citizenship. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kuehn, Manfred (2012). “Kant on Education, Anthropology, and Ethics.Kant and Education: Interpretations and Commentary, ed. Roth, Klas & Supernant, Chris. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lindstedt, D. (2009). “Kant: Progress in Universal History as a Postulate of Practical Reason.Kant-Studien 90(2), 129–47.Google Scholar
Louden, Robert B. (2011). Kant’s Human Being: Essays on His Theory of Human Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Louden, Robert B. (2016). “Applying Kant’s Ethics: The Role of Anthropology.A Companion to Kant, ed. Bird, Graham. London: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Louden, Robert B. (2017). “Becoming Human: Kant’s Philosophy of Education and Human Nature.The Palgrave Kant Handbook, ed. Altman, Matthew. London: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Louden, Robert B. (2020). Johann Bernhard Basedow and the Transformation of Modern Education: Educational Reform in the German Enlightenment. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Lu-Adler, Huaping (2023a). Kant, Race, and Racism: Views from Somewhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lu-Adler, Huaping (2023b). “Know Your Place, Know Your Calling: Geography, Race, and Kant’s ‘World-Citizen.’” Studia Kantiana 21(2), 8196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moran, Kate A. (2009). “Can Kant Have an Account of Moral Education?Journal of Philosophy of Education 43(4), 471–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moran, Kate A. (2011). “The Ethical Community as Ground of Moral Action: An Interpretation of the Highest Good.Rethinking Kant, vol. 3, ed. Thorndike, Oliver. Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.Google Scholar
Moran, Kate A. (2012). Community and Progress in Kant’s Moral Philosophy. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Munzel, G. Felicitas (1999). Kant’s Conception of Moral Character: The “Critical” Link of Morality, Anthropology, and Reflective Judgment. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Munzel, G. Felicitas (2003). “Kant on Moral Education, or ‘Enlightenment’ and the Liberal Arts.The Review of Metaphysics 57(1), 4373.Google Scholar
Neiman, Susan (1994). The Unity of Reason: Rereading Kant. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Neill, Onora (1989). Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant’s Practical Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
O’Neill, Onora (1992). “Vindicating Reason.” In Guyer, Paul (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Kant. New York: Cambridge University Press, 280308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Palmeri, Frank (2016). State of Nature, Stages of Society. Enlightenment Conjectural History and Modern Social Discourse. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parry, Geraint (2006). “Education.The Cambridge History of Eighteenth-Century Philosophy, ed. Haakonssen, K.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Patrone, Tatiana (2008). How Kant’s Conception of Reason Implies a Liberal Politics: An Interpretation of the “Doctrine of Right”. Lewiston: Edwin Mellen Press.Google Scholar
Phillips, Mark S. (2000). Society and Sentiment Genres of Historical Writing in Britain, 1740–1820. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John (1993). Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Reisert, Joseph R. (2012). “Kant and Rousseau on Moral Education.Kant and Education: Interpretations and Commentary, ed. Roth, Klas & Supernant, Chris. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques (1984). Discourse on the Origins and Basis of Inequality among Men, trans. M. Cranston. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques (1979). Emile: Or On Education, trans. A. Bloom. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques (1986). On the Origin of Languages, trans. John H. Moran. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Castro, Santos, Juan, S. (2017). “Hume and Conjectural History.Journal of Scottish Philosophy, 15(2), 157–74.Google Scholar
Schneewind, Jerome B. (2009). “Good out of Evil: Kant and the Idea of Unsocial Sociability.Kant’s “Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Aim”: A Critical Guide, ed. Rorty, Amelie O. & Schmidt, James. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Shell, Susan (2015a). “Kant’s Lectures on Pedagogy.Reading Kant’s Lectures, ed. Robert Clewis, . Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Shell, Susan (2015b). “‘More [Than] Human’: Kant on Liberal Education and the Public Use of Reason.In Search of Humanity: Essays in Honor of Cifford Orwin, ed. Andrea Radasanu, . Boston: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Marušić, Smalligan, Jennifer, (2017). “Dugald Stewart on Conjectural History and Human Nature.Journal of Scottish Philosophy, 15(3), 261–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Adam (1853). The Theory of Moral Sentiments; or an Essay Towards an Analysis of the Principles by Which Men Naturally Judge Concerning the Conduct and Character, First of Their Neighbours, and Afterwards of Themselves: To Which Is Added, A Dissertation on the Origin of Languages. London: Bohn’s Standard Library.Google Scholar
Stewart, Dugald (1854a). Dissertation Exhibiting the Progress of Metaphysical, Ethical, and Political Philosophy: The Collected Works of Dugald Stewart, ed. Hamilton, William, 11 vols. Edinburgh: Thomas Constable and Co., vol. 1.Google Scholar
Stewart, Dugald (1854b). Elements of the Philosophy of the Human Mind: The Collected Works of Dugald Stewart, vols. 24.Google Scholar
Stewart, Dugald (1858). “Account of the Life and Writings of Adam Smith”: The Collected Works of Dugald Stewart, vol. 10, 598.Google Scholar
Stewart, Dugald (2017). The Collected Works of Dugald Stewart: Biographical Memoirs of Adam Smith, William Robertson, Thomas Reid: To Which Is Prefixed a Memoir of Dugald Stewart – From His Correspondence – By J. Veitch – 1858. Andesite Press.Google Scholar
Stroud, Scott R. (2005). “Rhetoric and Moral Progress in Kant’s Ethical Community.Philosophy & Rhetoric, 38(4), 328–54.Google Scholar
Velkley, Richard L (1989). Freedom and the End of Reason: On the Moral Foundation of Kant’s Critical Philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weinstock, Daniel (1996). “Natural Law and Public Reason in Kant’s Political Philosophy.Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 26(3), 389411.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beck, White, Lewis, (1963). “Editor’s Introduction.Kant: On History, ed. Beck, L. White. Indianapolis: The Bobbs-Merrill Company.Google Scholar
Wokler, Robert (1995). “Anthropology and Conjectural History in the Enlightenment.Inventing Human Science: Eighteenth Century Domains, ed. Fox, C., Porter, R. & Wokler, R.. Oakland: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Wood, Allen W. (1991). “Unsociable Sociability: The Anthropological Basis for Kantian Ethics.Philosophical Topics, 19(1), 325–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wood, Allen W. (1995). “Kant’s Project for Perpetual Peace.Proceedings of the Eighth International Kant Congress, vol. 1. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
Wood, Allen W. (1999). Kant’s Ethical Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wood, Allen W. (2003). “Kant and the Problem of Human Nature.Essays on Kant’s Anthropology, ed. Jacobs, B. & Kain, P.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Allen., Wood (2007). “Translator’s Introduction.” In Kant, Immanuel, Anthropology, History, and Education, ed. Louden, Robert and Günter, Zöller. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wood, Allen W. (2009). “Kant’s Fourth Proposition: The Unsociable Sociability of Human Nature.Kant’s “Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Aim”: A Critical Guide, ed. A. O. Rorty, & Schmidt, J.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Yovel, Yirmiyahu (1978). “Kant and the History of Reason.Philosophy of History and Action. Philosophical Studies Series in Philosophy, ed. Yovel, Y.. Springer: Dordrecht, vol. 11.Google Scholar
Yovel, Yirmiyahu (1989). Kant and the Philosophy of History. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Yovel, Yirmiyahu (2009). “The Highest Good and History in Kant’s Thought.Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 54(3), 238–83.Google Scholar
Zimmer, Aime Leigh (2022). “Kant’s Conjectures: The Genesis of the Feminine.The Journal of Speculative Philosophy, 36(2), 183–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Kant on the History and Development of Practical Reason
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Kant on the History and Development of Practical Reason
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Kant on the History and Development of Practical Reason
Available formats
×