Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-29T11:35:31.130Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Evidential Decision Theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 September 2021

Arif Ahmed
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge

Summary

Evidential Decision Theory is a radical theory of rational decision-making. It recommends that instead of thinking about what your decisions *cause*, you should think about what they *reveal*. This Element explains in simple terms why thinking in this way makes a big difference, and argues that doing so makes for *better* decisions. An appendix gives an intuitive explanation of the measure-theoretic foundations of Evidential Decision Theory.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781108581462
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 21 October 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ahmed, A. 2014a. Evidence, Decision and Causality. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ahmed, A. 2014b. Dicing with death. Analysis 74 (4): 587–92.Google Scholar
Ahmed, A. 2016. Review of Lara Buchak, Risk and Rationality. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science Review of Books. Available online at: https://bjpsbooks.wordpress.com/2016/08/22/lara-buchak-risk-and-rationality.Google Scholar
Ahmed, A. 2018. Self-control and hyperbolic discounting. In Bermúdez, J.-L. (ed.), Self-Control, Decision Theory and Rationality. Cambridge University Press: 96120.Google Scholar
Ahmed, A. 2020. Equal opportunities in Newcomb’s Problem and elsewhere. Mind 129 (515): 867–86.Google Scholar
Ahmed, A. and Price, H.. 2012. Arntzenius on ‘Why ain’cha rich?’ Erkenntnis 77 (1): 1530.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ahmed, A. and Price, H. and Spencer, J.. 2020. Objective value is always Newcombizable. Mind 129 (516): 1157–92.Google Scholar
Ainslie, G. 1991. Derivation of ‘rational’ economic behaviour from hyperbolic discount curves. American Economic Review 81 (2): 334–40.Google Scholar
Allais, M. 1953. Le comportement de l’homme rationnel devant le risque: critique des postulats et axiomes de l’école Américaine. Econometrica 21 (4): 503–46.Google Scholar
Bales, A. (unpublished). Decision and Dependence: A Defence of Causal Decision Theory. Doctoral dissertation, University of Cambridge.Google Scholar
Bales, A. 2018. Richness and rationality: Causal Decision Theory and the WAR argument. Synthese 195 (1): 259–67.Google Scholar
Bénabou, R. and Tirole., J. 2011. Identity, morals and taboos: beliefs as assets. Quarterly Journal of Economics 126 (2): 805–55.Google Scholar
Bermúdez, J. L. 2018. Does Newcomb’s Problem actually exist? In Ahmed, A. (ed.), Newcomb’s Problem. Cambridge University Press: 1941.Google Scholar
Bernoulli, D. 1738. Specimen Theoriae Novae de Mensura Sortis. Commentarii Academiae Scientiarum Imperialis Petropolitanae V: 175–92. Reprinted as ‘Exposition of a new theory on the measurement of risk’, tr. L. Sommer. Econometrica 22 (1) (1954): 2336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bodner, R. and Prelec, D.. 2003. Self-signalling and diagnostic utility in everyday decision making. In Brocas, I. and Carrillo, J. D. (eds), The Psychology of Economic Decisions, vol. I: Rationality and Well-Being. Oxford University Press: 105–23.Google Scholar
Bolker, E. 1966. Functions resembling quotients of measures. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 124 (2): 292312.Google Scholar
Bolker, E. 1967. A simultaneous axiomatization of utility and subjective probability. Philosophy of Science 34 (4): 333–40.Google Scholar
Bradley, R. 2017. Decision Theory with a Human Face. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bradley, R. and Stefánsson, H. O. 2016. Desire, expectation, and invariance. Mind 125 (499): 691725.Google Scholar
Brier, G. W. 1950. Verification of forecasts expressed in terms of probabilities. Monthly Weather Review 78 (1): 13.Google Scholar
Broome, J. 1991. Weighing Goods. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Buchak, L. 2013. Risk and Rationality. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Capinski, M. and Copp, E.. 2004. Measure, Integral and Probability. 2nd ed. London: Springer.Google Scholar
Christensen, D. 1992. Confirmational holism and Bayesian epistemology. Philosophy of Science 59 (4): 540–57.Google Scholar
Chu, F. and Halpern, J. Y.. 2004. Great expectations. Part II: generalized expected utility as a universal decision rule. Artificial Intelligence 159 (1–2): 207–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Finetti, B. 1937. La prévision: ses lois logiques, ses sources subjectives. Annales de l’Institut Henri Poincaré 7: 168.Google Scholar
Diamond, P. 1967. Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics and interpersonal comparison of utility: comment. Journal of Political Economy 75 (5): 765–6.Google Scholar
Dove, M. R. 1993. Uncertainty, humility and adaptation in the tropical forest: the agricultural augury of the Kantu’. Ethnology 32 (2): 145–67.Google Scholar
Dummett, M. A. E. 1964. Bringing about the past. Philosophical Review 73 (3): 338–59.Google Scholar
Eells, E. 1982. Rational Decision and Causality. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Elga, A. 2020. Newcomb University: A play in one act. Analysis 80 (2): 212–21.Google Scholar
Ellsberg, D. 1961. Risk, ambiguity and the Savage axioms. Quarterly Journal of Economics 75 (4): 643–69.Google Scholar
Fernandes, A. 2017. A deliberative approach to causation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 95 (3): 686708.Google Scholar
Fisher, R. A. 1935. The Design of Experiments. Edinburgh: Oliver and Boyd.Google Scholar
Flew, A. G. N. 1954. Can an effect precede its cause? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 28: 4762.Google Scholar
Gallow, D. 2021. Riches and rationality. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 99 (1): 114-129.Google Scholar
Garber, D. 1983. Old evidence and logical omniscience in Bayesian confirmation theory. In Earman, J. (ed.), Testing Scientific Theories (Midwest Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. X). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 99131.Google Scholar
Gibbard, A. and Harper., W. L. 1978. Counterfactuals and two kinds of expected utility. In Hooker, C., Leach, J., and McClennen, E. (eds), Foundations and Applications of Decision Theory. Dordrecht: Riedel: 125–62. Reprinted in P. Gärdenfors and N.-E. Sahlin (eds), Decision, Probability and Utility. Cambridge University Press 1988: 341–76.Google Scholar
Gneiting, T. and Raftery., A. E. 2007. Strictly proper scoring rules, prediction, and estimation. Journal of the American Statistical Association 102 (477): 359–78.Google Scholar
Grafstein, R. 1991. An evidential decision theory of turnout. American Journal of Political Science 35 (4): 9891010.Google Scholar
Grafstein, R. 1999. Choice-Free Rationality: A Positive Theory of Political Behaviour. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Grafstein, R. 2018. Newcomb’s problem is everyone’s problem: making political and economic decisions when behaviour is interdependent. In Ahmed, A. (ed.), Newcomb’s Problem. Cambridge University Press: 96114.Google Scholar
Greene, P. 2018. Success-first decision theories. In Ahmed, A. (ed.), Newcomb’s Problem. Cambridge University Press: 115–37.Google Scholar
Holton, R. J. 2016. Addiction, self-signalling and the deep self. Mind and Language 31 (3): 300–13.Google Scholar
Holton, R. J. Unpublished. Self-deception and the moral self.Google Scholar
Hume, D. 1738 [1949]. Treatise of Human Nature. London: J. M. Dent.Google Scholar
Huttegger, S. M. 2017. The Probabilistic Foundations of Rational Learning. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Icard, T. 2021. Why be random? Mind 130 (517): 111-39Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1985. (Tr.) Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, R. C. 1977. A note on the kinematics of preference. Erkenntnis 11 (1): 135–41.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, R. C. 1983. The Logic of Decision. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. M. 1999. Foundations of Causal Decision Theory. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. M. 2011. The development of subjective Bayesianism. In Gabbay, D. M., Hartmann, S., and Woods, J. (eds), Handbook of the History of Logic, vol. 10. Oxford: Elsevier, 415–75.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. M. 2012. Regret and instability in Causal Decision Theory. Synthese 187 (1): 123–45.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. M. 2018. Deliberation and stability in Newcomb problems and pseudo-Newcomb problems. In Ahmed, A. (ed.), Newcomb’s Problem. Cambridge University Press: 138–59.Google Scholar
Kadane, J. and Seidenfeld, T.. 1990. Randomization in a Bayesian perspective. Journal of Statistical Planning and Inference 25 (3): 329–45.Google Scholar
Kahnemann, D. and Tversky., A. 1984. Choices, values and frames. APA award address. American Psychologist 39 (4): 341–50.Google Scholar
Kreps, D. 1988. Notes on the Theory of Choice. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Levinstein, B. and Soares, N.. 2020. Cheating Death in Damascus. Journal of Philosophy 117 (5): 237–66.Google Scholar
Lewis, C. S. 1943. The Screwtape Letters. New York: MacMillan.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1976. The paradoxes of time travel. American Philosophical Quarterly 13 (2): 145–52. Reprinted in his Philosophical Papers, vol. 2. Oxford University Press 1986: 67–80.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1979. Prisoners’ dilemma is a Newcomb problem. Philosophy and Public Affairs 8 (3): 235–4.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1981a. Causal Decision Theory. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 59 (1): 530. Reprinted with a postscript in his Philosophical Papers vol. 2. Oxford University Press 1986: 305–39.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1981b. Why ain’cha rich? Noûs 15 (3): 377–80.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1986. On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1988. Desire as belief. Mind 97 (387): 323–32.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1996. Desire as belief II. Mind 105 (418): 303–13.Google Scholar
Lindley, D. V. 1956. On a measure of the information provided by an experiment. Annals of Mathematical Statistics 27 (4): 9861005.Google Scholar
List, C. 2014. Free will, determinism, and the possibility of doing otherwise. Noûs 48 (1): 156–78.Google Scholar
Loewer, B. 2007. Counterfactuals and the second law. In Corry, R. and Price, H. (eds), Causation, Physics, and the Constitution of Reality. Oxford University Press: 293326.Google Scholar
Luce, R. D. and Suppes, P.. 2004. Representational measurement theory. In Wixted, J. and Pashler, H. (eds), Stevens’ Handbook of Experimental Psychology, vol. 4. 3rd ed. New York: Wiley, 141.Google Scholar
Meek, C. and Glymour., C. 1994. Conditioning and intervening. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (4): 1000–21.Google Scholar
Milne, P. and Oddie., G. 1991. Act and value: expectation and the representation of moral theories. Theoria 57 (1–2): 4276.Google Scholar
Moore, O. K. 1957. Divination – a new perspective. American Anthropologist 59 (1): 6974.Google Scholar
Moscati, I. 2019. Measuring Utility: From the Marginal Revolution to Behavioural Economics. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1970. Newcomb’s problem and two principles of choice. In Rescher, N. (ed.), Essays in Honor of Carl G. Hempel. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 114–46. Reprinted in P. Moser (ed.), Rationality in Action: Contemporary Approaches. Cambridge University Press 1990: 207–34.Google Scholar
Pasnau, R. 2020. Medieval modal spaces. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 94: 225–54.Google Scholar
Pearl, J. 2000. Causality: Models, Reasoning, and Inference. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pearl, J. Forthcoming. Causal and counterfactual inference. In Knauff, M. and Spohn, W. (eds), Handbook of Rationality. Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.Google Scholar
Peterson, M. 2017. An Introduction to Decision Theory. 2nd ed. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pettigrew, R. 2019. Choosing for Changing Selves. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Poundstone, W. 2014. How to Predict the Unpredictable: The Art of Outsmarting Almost Everyone. London: Oneworld.Google Scholar
Price, H. 1989. Defending desire-as-belief. Mind 98 (389): 119–27.Google Scholar
Price, H. 1991. Agency and probabilistic causality. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 42 (2): 157–76.Google Scholar
Price, H. and Liu., Y. 2018. ‘Click!’ bait for causalists. In Ahmed, A. (ed.), Newcomb’s Problem. Cambridge University Press: 160–79.Google Scholar
Quattrone, G. A. and Tversky, A.. 1986. Self-deception and the voter’s illusion. In Elster, J. (ed.), The Multiple Self. Cambridge University Press: 3558.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. 1981. Things and their place in theories. In his Theories and Things. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press: 123.Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. P. 1926. Truth and probability. In his Philosophical Papers, ed. Mellor, D. H.. Cambridge University Press 1990: 5294.Google Scholar
Rothfus, G. J. 2020. Dynamic consistency in the logic of decision. Philosophical Studies 177: 3923–34.Google Scholar
Roulston, M. S. 2007. Performance targets and the Brier score. Meteorological Applications 14 (2): 185–94.Google Scholar
Savage, L. J. 1972. The Foundations of Statistics. 2nd ed. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Seaman, B. T. 2002. What if Nancy Reagan’s astrologer had sued? An essay. Nova Law Review 27 (2): 277–88.Google Scholar
Sen, A. K. 1971. Choice functions and revealed preference. Review of Economic Studies 38 (3): 307–17.Google Scholar
Simpson, E. H. 1951. The interpretation of interaction in contingency tables.Journal of the Royal Statistical Society (Series B) 13 (2): 238–41.Google Scholar
Skyrms, B. 1984. Pragmatics and Empiricism. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Soares, N. and Fallenstein, B.. 2015. Toward idealized decision theory. arXiv: 1507.01986 [cs.AI].Google Scholar
Soares, N. and Yudkowsky, E.. 2018. Functional Decision Theory: a new theory of instrumental rationality. arXiv: 1710.05060.Google Scholar
Speck, F. G. 1935. Naskapi. Norman: University of Oklahoma Press.Google Scholar
Spencer, J. and Wells, I.. 2019. Why take both boxes? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 99 (1): 2748.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stalnaker, R. 1972. Letter to David Lewis. In Harper, W. L., Stalnaker, R., and Pearce, G. (eds), Ifs: Conditionals, Belief, Decision, Chance, and Time. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1980: 151–2.Google Scholar
Swijtink, Z. G. 1982. A Bayesian argument for randomization. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 1 (1982): 159–68.Google Scholar
Von Neumann, J. and Morgenstern, R.. 1953. Theory of Games and Economic Behaviour. 3d ed. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Wang, Z., Xu, B., and Zhou, H.-J.. 2014. Social cycling and conditional responses in the rock-paper-scissors game. Scientific Reports 4 (article no. 5830): 17.Google ScholarPubMed
Weirich, P. 2001. Decision Space: Multidimensional Utility Analysis. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wells, I. 2019. Equal opportunity and Newcomb’s Problem. Mind 128 (510): 429–57.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1953 [2009]. Philosophical Investigations. 4th ed. Tr. Anscombe, G. E. M., Hacker, P. M. S., and Schulte, J.. Malden: Wiley.Google Scholar
Worrall, J. 2007. Why there’s no cause to randomize. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58 (3): 451–88.Google Scholar
Yudkowsky, E. 2010. Timeless Decision Theory. San Francisco: The Singularity Institute.Google Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Evidential Decision Theory
  • Arif Ahmed, University of Cambridge
  • Online ISBN: 9781108581462
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Evidential Decision Theory
  • Arif Ahmed, University of Cambridge
  • Online ISBN: 9781108581462
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Evidential Decision Theory
  • Arif Ahmed, University of Cambridge
  • Online ISBN: 9781108581462
Available formats
×