Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-fbnjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-19T11:27:21.612Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Wittgenstein on Music

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 March 2024

Eran Guter
Affiliation:
The Max Stern Yezreel Valley College

Summary

In this Element, the author set out to answer a twofold question concerning the importance of music to Wittgenstein's philosophical progression and the otherness of this sort of philosophical importance vis-à-vis philosophy of music as practiced today in the analytic tradition. The author starts with the idea of making music together and with Wittgenstein's master simile of language-as-music. The author traces these themes as they play out in Wittgenstein early, middle, and later periods. The author argues that Wittgenstein's overarching reorientation of the concept of depth pertaining to music in the aftermath of his anthropological turn, and against the backdrop of the outlook of German Romanticism, culminates in his unique view of musical profundity as 'knowledge of people.' This sets Wittgenstein's view in sharp contrast with certain convictions and debates that typify current analytically inclined philosophy of music.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781009313742
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 11 April 2024

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Primary Sources

Secondary Sources

Ahonen, H. (2005). “Wittgenstein and the Conditions of Musical Communication.” Philosophy 80 (4), 513529.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allen, R. and Turvey, R. (2001). Wittgenstein, Theory and the Arts. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Almén, B. (1996). “Prophets of the Decline: The Worldviews of Heinrich Schenker and Oswald Spengler.” Indiana Theory Review 17, 124.Google Scholar
Appelqvist, H. (2019). “Wittgenstein and Formalism: A Case Revisited.” Ápeiron: Estudios defilosofía 10, 927.Google Scholar
Appelqvist, H. (2023). Wittgenstein and Aesthetics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arbo, A. (2013). Entendre comme: Wittgenstein et l’esthétique musicale. Paris: Hermann.Google Scholar
Baz, A. (2000). “What’s the Point of Seeing Aspects?Philosophical Investigations 23 (3), 97121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baz, A. (2020). Wittgenstein on Aspect Perception. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bolton, T. L. (1894). “Rhythm.” American Journal of Psychology 6, 145238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowie, A. (2007). Music, Philosophy, and Modernity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cavell, S. (1979). The Claim of Reason: Wittgenstein, Skepticism, Morality, and Tragedy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cavell, S. (1996). “Declining Decline.” In Mulhall, S., ed., The Cavell Reader. Oxford: Blackwell, 321352.Google Scholar
Cavell, S. (2022). Here and There: Sites of Philosophy. Bauer, N., Crary, A., and Laugier, S., eds. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Cook, N. (1989). “Schenker’s Theory of Music as Ethics.” The Journal of Musicology 7, 415439.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cooke, D. (1964). The Language of Music. London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Davies, S. (2002). “Profundity in Instrumental Music.” British Journal of Aesthetics 42 (4), 343356.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, S. (2011). “Analytic Philosophy and Music.” In Gracyk, T. and Kania, A., eds., The Routledge Companion to Philosophy and Music. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 294304.Google Scholar
Dodd, J. (2014). “The Possibility of Profound Music.” British Journal of Aesthetics 54 (3), 299322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Drury, M. O’C. (2017). The Selected Writings of Maurice O’Connor Drury: On Wittgenstein, Philosophy, Religion, and Psychiatry. Hayes, J., ed. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Eggers, K. (2014). Ludwig Wittgenstein als Musikphilosoph. Freiburg im Breisgau: Karl Alber.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Engelmann, M. L. (2013). “Wittgenstein’s ‘Most Fruitful Ideas’ and Sraffa.” Philosophical Investigations 36, 155178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Floyd, J. (2010). “On Being Surprised: Wittgenstein on Aspect-Perception, Logic, and Mathematics.” In Day, W. and Krebs, V. J., eds., Seeing Wittgenstein Anew. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 314337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Floyd, J. (2016). “Chains of Life: Turing, Lebensform, and the Emergence of Wittgenstein’s Later Style.” Nordic Wittgenstein Review 5 (2), 789.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Floyd, J. (2017). “The Fluidity of Simplicity: Philosophy, Mathematics, Art.” In Kossak, R. and Ording, P., eds., Simplicity: Ideals of Practice in Mathematics and the Arts. New York: Springer, 153175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Floyd, J. (2018a). “Aspects of Aspects.” In Sluga, H. and Stern, D., eds., The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein, 2nd ed. New York: Cambridge University Press, 361388.Google Scholar
Floyd, J. (2018b). “Lebensformen: Living Logic.” In Martin, C., ed., Language, Form(s) of Life, and Logic. Berlin: De Gruyter, 5992.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goehr, L. (2016). “Improvising Impromptu or, What to Do with a Broken String.” In Lewis, G. and Piekut, B., eds., Oxford Handbook of Critical Improvisation Studies, Vol. 1. New York: Oxford University Press, 458480.Google Scholar
Guter, E. (2011). “A Surrogate for the Soul: Wittgenstein and Schoenberg.” In Pellegrin, E. De, ed., Interactive Wittgenstein: Essays in Memory of Georg Henrik von Wright. Synthese Library, Vol. 349. Dordrecht: Springer, 109152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guter, E. (2015). “The Good, the Bad, and the Vacuous: Wittgenstein on Modern and Future Musics.” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 73 (4), 425439.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guter, E. (2017). “Wittgenstein on Musical Depth and Our Knowledge of the Humankind.” In Hagberg, G., ed., Wittgenstein on Aesthetic Understanding. Cham: Palgrave Macmillan, 217247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guter, E. (2019a). “‘A Small, Shabby Crystal, yet a Crystal’: A Life of Music in Wittgenstein’s Denkbewegungen.” In Somavilla, I., Hamphries, C., and Sieradzka-Baziur, B., eds., Wittgenstein’s Denkbewegungen. Diaries 1930–1932/1936–1937: Interdisciplinary Perspectives. Innsbruck: StudienVerlag, 83112.Google Scholar
Guter, E. (2019b). “Measure for Measure: Wittgenstein’s Critique of the Augustinian Picture of Music.” In Appelqvist, H., ed., Wittgenstein and the Limits of Language. London: Routledge, 245269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guter, E. (2019c). “Musical Profundity: Wittgenstein’s Paradigm Shift.” Ápeiron: Estudios de filosofía 10, 4158.Google Scholar
Guter, E. (2020). “The Philosophical Significance of Wittgenstein’s Experiments on Rhythm, Cambridge 1912–13.” Estetika: The European Journal of Aesthetics 57 (1), 2843.Google Scholar
Guter, E. (2023a). “Musicking as Knowing Human Beings.” In Carmona, C., Perez-Chico, D., and Tejedor, C., eds., Intercultural Understanding after Wittgenstein. London: Anthem, 7791.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guter, E. (2023b). “Wittgenstein in the Laboratory: Pre-Tractatus Seeds of Wittgenstein’s Post-Tractatus Aesthetics.” In A. Pichler, E. Heinrich-Ramharter, and F. Stadler, eds., 100 Years of Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus – 70 Years after Wittgenstein’s Death: A Critical Assessment, Papers of the 44th International Wittgenstein Symposium. Kirchberg am Wechsel: Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society. https://symposium.alws.at/#/article/511c6b7a-b66f-4793-9e46-88e35735905d.Google Scholar
Guter, E. (2024). “Carl Stumpf and the Curious Incident of Music in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie. https://doi.org/10.1515/agph-2021-0141CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guter, E. (Forthcoming). “Cavell’s Odd Couple: Wittgenstein and Schoenberg.” In LaRocca, D., ed., Music with Stanley Cavell in Mind. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Guter, E. and Guter, I. (2023). “Thinking through Music: Wittgenstein’s Use of Musical Notation.” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 81 (3), 348362. https://doi.org/10.1093/jaac/kpad033.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hagberg, G. (2011). “Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations, Linguistic Meaning and Music.” Paragraph 34 (3), 388405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hagberg, G. (2014). “Wittgenstein’s Aesthetics.” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2014 ed.), E. N. Zalta, ed. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/wittgenstein-aesthetics.Google Scholar
Hagberg, G. (2017). “Wittgenstein, Music, and the Philosophy of Culture.” In Hagberg, G., ed., Wittgenstein on Aesthetic Understanding. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 6198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanslick, E. (2018). On the Musically Beautiful. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hark, M. ter (1990). Beyond the Inner and the Outer: Wittgenstein’s Philosophy of Psychology. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hintikka, M. B. and Hintikka, J. (1986). Investigating Wittgenstein. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hintikka, M. B. and Hintikka, J. (1996). “Different Language Games in Wittgenstein.” In Hintikka, J., Wittgenstein: Half-Truths and One-and-a-Half-Truths. Selected Papers 1. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 335343.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hui, A. (2013). The Psychophysical Ear: Musical Experiments, Experimental Sounds, 1840-1910. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hulatt, O. (2017). “‘Pure Showing’ and Anti-humanist Musical Profundity.” British Journal of Aesthetics 57 (2), 195210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Husserl, E. (1964). The Phenomenology of Internal Time-Consciousness. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Hutto, D. D. (2013). “Enactivism from a Wittgensteinian Point of View.” American Philosophical Quarterly 50 (3), 281302.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. (2000). Ulysses. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Kittler, F. A. (1999). Gramophone, Film, Typewriter. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Kivy, P. (1990). Music Alone: Philosophical Reflections on the Purely Musical Experience. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Kivy, P. (1997). Philosophies of Arts: An Essay in Differences. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kivy, P. (2003). “Another Go at Musical Profundity: Stephen Davies and the Game of Chess.” British Journal of Aesthetics 43 (4), 401411.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kramer, L. (2012). Expression and Truth: On the Music of Knowledge. Berkley: The University of California Press.Google Scholar
Kursell, J. (2018). “Carl Stumpf and the Beginnings of Research in Musicality.” In Honing, H., ed., The Origins of Musicality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 323346.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kursell, J. (2019). “From Tone to Tune – Carl Stumpf and the Violin.” 19th Century Music 43 (2), 121139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakoff, G. and Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors We Live by. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Langer, S. K. (1953). Feeling and Form. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Lerdahl, F. and Jackendoff, R. (1983). A Generative Theory of Tonal Music. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Levinson, J. (1992). “Musical Profundity Misplaced.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 50 (1), 5860.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levinson, J. (1997). Music in the Moment. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, P. B. (2004). Wittgenstein, Aesthetics and Philosophy. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
McGuinness, B. (1988). Wittgenstein, a Life: Young Ludwig, 1889–1921. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Monk, R. (1990). Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Moyal-Sharrock, D. (2013). “Wittgenstein’s Razor: The Cutting Edge of Enactivism.” American Philosophical Quarterly 50 (3), 263279.Google Scholar
Mulhall, S. (1990). On Being in the World: Wittgenstein and Heidegger on Seeing Aspects. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Myers, C. S. (2013). A Text-Book of Experimental Psychology, with Laboratory Exercises, 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Noë, A. (2023). The Entanglement: How Art and Philosophy Make Us What We Are. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Pinsent, D. (1990). A Portrait of Wittgenstein as a Young Man: From the Diary of David Hume Pinsent 1912–1914. von Wright, G. H., ed. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Potter, M. (2008). Wittgenstein’s Notes on Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ridley, A. (1995). “Profundity in Music.” In Neill, A. and Ridley, A., eds., Arguing about Art: Contemporary Philosophical Debates. New York: McGraw-Hill, 260272.Google Scholar
Rilke, R. M. (1961). “Primal Sound.” In Selected Works, Vol. 1. Prose. Houston, G. C., tr. New York: New Directions, 5156.Google Scholar
Robinson, J. (2000). “Review of Philosophy of Arts: An Essay in Differences, by Peter Kivy.” Philosophical Review 109, 138141.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schoenberg, A. (1999). Fundamentals of Music Composition. London: Faber & Faber.Google Scholar
Schopenhauer, A. (1969). The World as Will and Representation, Vols. I and II. Payne, E. F. J., tr. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Schorske, C. E. (1999). Thinking with History: Explorations in the Passage to Modernism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schütz, A. (1951). “Making Music Together: A Study in Social Relationship.” Social Research 18 (1), 7697.Google Scholar
Scruton, R. (1999). The Aesthetics of Music. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scruton, R. (2004). “Wittgenstein and the Understanding of Music.” British Journal of Aesthetics 44 (1), 19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sloboda, J. (1986). The Musical Mind: The Cognitive Psychology of Music. Oxford: Clarendon.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Small, C. (1998). Musicking: The Meanings of Performing and Listening. Middlebury: Wesleyan University Press.Google Scholar
Snarrenberg, R. (1997). Schenker’s Interpretative Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Soulez, A. (2006). “Time, Music and Grammar: When Understanding and Performing What is Understood Are Two Facets of the Same Action.” In Stadler, F. and Stöltzner, M., eds., Time and History: Zeit und Geschichte. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag, 585599.Google Scholar
Soulez, A. (2012). Au fil du motif – autour de Wittgenstein et la musique. Paris: Delatour.Google Scholar
Spengler, O. (1939). The Decline of the West. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.Google Scholar
Stern, D. (1991). “The ‘Middle Wittgenstein’: From Logical Atomism to Practical Holism.” Synthese 87, 203226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterrett, S. G. (2005). “Pictures of Sounds: Wittgenstein on Gramophone Records and the Logic of Depiction.” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 36, 351362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stumpf, C. (1883). Tonpsychologie, Vol. 2. Leipzig: Hirzel.Google Scholar
Stumpf, C. (2012). The Origins of Music. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sully, J. (1886). “Review of Musikpsychologie in England.” Mind 11 (44), 580585.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Szabados, B. (2006). “Wittgenstein and Musical Formalism.” Philosophy 81, 649658.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Szabados, B. (2014). Wittgenstein as Philosophical Tone-Poet: Philosophy and Music in Dialogue. Amsterdam: Rodopi.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, C. (1996). Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Tejedor, C. (2015). “Tractarian Form as the Precursor to Forms of Life.Nordic Wittgenstein Review, Special Issue: Wittgenstein and Forms of Life, 83110.Google Scholar
Valentine, C. W. (1962). The Experimental Psychology of Beauty. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Wackenroder, W. H. (1971). Confessions and Fantasies. University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
White, D. A. (1992). “Toward a Theory of Profundity in Music.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 50 (1), 2334.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodrow, H. (1909). “A Quantitative Study of Rhythm.” Archives of Psychology 14, 166.Google Scholar
Wright, G. H. von (1982). “Ludwig Wittgenstein in Relation to His Times.” In McGuinness, B., ed., Wittgenstein and His Times. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Wright, J. K. (2007). Schoenberg, Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle, 2nd ed. Bern: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Wundt, W. (1903). Grundzüge der physiologischer Psychologie, Vol. 3. Leipzig: Engelmann.Google Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Wittgenstein on Music
  • Eran Guter, The Max Stern Yezreel Valley College
  • Online ISBN: 9781009313742
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Wittgenstein on Music
  • Eran Guter, The Max Stern Yezreel Valley College
  • Online ISBN: 9781009313742
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Wittgenstein on Music
  • Eran Guter, The Max Stern Yezreel Valley College
  • Online ISBN: 9781009313742
Available formats
×