Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2plfb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-01T02:48:12.295Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reading Wittgenstein's Tractatus

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 June 2021

Mauro Luiz Engelmann
Affiliation:
Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais, Brazil

Summary

This Element presents a concise and accessible view of the central arguments of Wittgenstein's Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Starting from the difficulties found in historical and current debates, drawing on the background of Russell's philosophy, and grounded in the ladder structure expressed in the numbering system of the book, this Element presents the central arguments of the Tractatus in three lines of thought. The first concerns the role of the so-called 'ontology' and its relationship to the method of the Tractatus and its logical symbolism, which displays the formal essence of language and world. The second deals with the symbolic unity of language and its role in the 'ladder structure' and explains how and why the book is not self-defeating. The third elucidates Wittgenstein's claim to have solved in essentials all philosophical problems, whose very formulation, he says, rests on misunderstandings.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781108887892
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 29 July 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

References

Stern, D., Rogers, B and Citron, G., eds.Wittgenstein: Lectures, Cambridge 1930–1933; From the Notes of G. E. Moore. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2016.

A Lecture on Ethics. In Philosophical Occasions, 1912–1951. Edited by Klagge, J. C and Nordmann, A.. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993.

Letters to C. K. Ogden. Oxford:Basil Blackwell, 1983.

Notebooks, 1914–1916. 2nd edition. Translated by G. E. M. Anscombe. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1979 [1961].

Notes on Logic. In Notebooks, 1914–1916. 2nd edition. Translated by G. E. M. Anscombe. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1979 [1961], pp. 93107.

Notes Dictated to Moore in Norway. In Notebooks, 1914–1916. 2nd edition. Translated by G. E. M. Anscombe. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1979 [1961], pp. 108119.

Philosophical Investigations. 4th edition, revised. Edited by Hacker, P. M. S. and Schulte, J., translated by G. E. M. Anscombe, P. M. S. Hacker and J. Schulte. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2009 [1953].

Klagge, J. C. and Nordmann, A., eds. Ludwig Wittgenstein: Public and Private Occasions. New York: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2003.

Prototractatus. Logisch-philosophische Abhandlung. Kritische Edition. Edited by McGuinness, B. and Schulte, J. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 2001.

Some Remarks on Logical Form. Aristotelian Society, Supplement 9 (1929), pp. 162171.

Tractatus Logico-philosophicus. Translated by McGuinness, B. F. and Pears, D.. London: Routledge, 2004 [1961].

Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Translated by C. K. Ogden, with an introduction by B. Russell. New York: Dover Publications, 1999 [1922].

McGuiness, B., ed. Wittgenstein in Cambridge: Letters and Documents, 1911–1951. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2012.

McGuinness, B, ed. and P. Winslow, tr. Wittgenstein’s Family Letters. London: Bloomsbury, 2018.

McGuinness, B., ed. and tr., J. Schulte, tr. Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle. Oxford: Blackwell, 2003 [1979].

Anscombe, G. E. M. (1996 [1959]) An Introduction to Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. Bristol: Thoemmes Press.Google Scholar
Bazzocchi, L. (2015) A Better Appraisal of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Manuscript. Philosophical Investigations 38:4, pp. 333359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Biletzki, A. (2003) (Over)Interpreting Wittgenstein. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
Black, M. (1966) A Companion to Wittgenstein’s “Tractatus. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Cahill, K. M. (2011) The Fate of Wonder: Wittgenstein’s Critique of Metaphysics and Modernity. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1959 [1934]) The Logical Syntax of Language. Translated by A. Smeathon. Paterson: Littlefield.Google Scholar
Conant, J. (1993) Kierkegaard, Wittgenstein and Nonsense. In Cohen, T., Guyer, P., and Putnam, H., eds., Pursuits or Reason: Essays in Honor of Stanley Cavell. Lubock, TX: Texas University Press, pp. 195224.Google Scholar
Conant, J. (1995) Putting Two and Two Together: Kierkegaard, Wittgenstein and the Point of View for Their Works as Authors. In Tessin, T. and von der Ruhr, M., eds., Philosophy and the Grammar of Religious Belief. New York: St. Martin’s Press, pp. 248331.Google Scholar
Conant, J. (2000) Elucidation and Nonsense in Frege and Early Wittgenstein. In Crary, A. and Read, R., eds., The New Wittgenstein. London: Routledge, pp. 174217.Google Scholar
Conant, J. (2005) What Ethics in the Tractatus is Not. In Philips, D. Z. and von der Ruhr, M., eds., Religion and Wittgenstein’s Legacy. London: Ashgate Publishing, pp. 3995.Google Scholar
Conant, J. (2007) Mild Mono-Wittgensteinianism. In Crary, A., ed., Wittgenstein and the Moral Life: Essays in Honor of Cora Diamond. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 31142.Google Scholar
Conant, J. and Bronzo, S. (2017) Resolute Readings of the Tractatus. In Glock, H.-J. and Hyman, J., eds., A Companion to Wittgenstein. Chichester: Wiley Blackwell, pp. 175194.Google Scholar
Conant, J. and Diamond, C. (2004) On Reading the Tractatus Resolutely: Reply to Meredith Williams and Peter Sullivan. In Koelbel, M. and Weiss, B., eds., Wittgenstein’s Lasting Significance. London: Routledge, pp. 4297.Google Scholar
Diamond, C. (1996) The Realistic Spirit: Wittgenstein, Philosophy and the Mind. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Diamond, C. (2000) Ethics, Imagination and the Method of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. In Crary, A. and Read, R., eds., The New Wittgenstein. London: Routledge, pp. 149173.Google Scholar
Diamond, C. (2004) Criss-Cross Philosophy. In Ammereller, E. and Fischer, E., eds., Wittgenstein at Work: Method in the “Philosophical Investigations. London: Routledge, pp. 201220.Google Scholar
Diamond, C. (2014) The Hardness of the Soft: Wittgenstein’s Early Thought about Skepticism. In Conant, J. and Kern, A., eds., Varieties of Skepticism: Essays after Kant, Wittgenstein, and Cavell. Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. 145182.Google Scholar
Diamond, C. (2019) Reading Wittgenstein with Anscombe: Going on to Ethics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Engelmann, M. L. (2011) What Wittgenstein’s ‘Grammar’ Is Not (On Garver, Baker and Hacker, and Hacker on Wittgenstein on ‘Grammar’). Wittgenstein-Studien 2, 71102.Google Scholar
Engelmann, M. L. (2013) Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Development: Phenomenology, Grammar, Method, and the Anthropological View. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Engelmann, M. L. (2016) The Faces of Necessity, Perspicuous Representation, and the Irreligious “Cult of the Useful”: The Spenglerian Background of the First Set of Remarks on Frazer. In Albinus, L. and Rothhaupt, J., eds., Wittgenstein’s Remarks on Frazer: The Text and the Matter. Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. 129174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Engelmann, M. L. (2017) What Does a Phenomenological Language Do? (Revisiting “Some Remarks on Logical Form” in Its Context). In Silva, M., ed., Colours in Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Development. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 95126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Engelmann, M. L. (2018a) What Does it Take to Climb the Ladder? (A Sideways Approach). Kriterion 59:140, pp. 591613.Google Scholar
Engelmann, M. L. (2018b) Instructions for Climbing the Ladder (The Minimalism of the Tractatus). Philosophical Investigations 41:4, pp. 446470.Google Scholar
Engelmann, M. L. (2018c) Phenomenology in Grammar: Explicitation-Verificationism, Arbitrariness, and the Vienna Circle. In Kuusela, O., Ometita, M., and Ucan, T., eds., Wittgenstein and Phenomenology. London: Routledge, pp. 2246.Google Scholar
Engelmann, P. (1967) Letters from Ludwig Wittgenstein with a Memoir. Edited by McGuinness, B. and translated by L. Furtmuller. New York: Horizon Press.Google Scholar
Floyd, J. (2001) Numbers and Ascriptions of Numbers in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. In Floyd, J. and Shieh, S., eds., Future Pasts: The Analytic Tradition in Twentieth-Century Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 145192.Google Scholar
Frege, G. (1987 [1884]) Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik. Stuttgart: Reclam.Google Scholar
Frege, G. (1962 [1903]) Grundgesetze der Arithmetik (Begriffsschriftlich Abgeleitet) II. Hildesheim: Georg Olms.Google Scholar
Goldfarb, W. (1997) Metaphysics and Nonsense: On Cora Diamond’s The Realistic Spirit. Journal of Philosophical Research 22, pp. 5773.Google Scholar
Goldfarb, W. (2002) Wittgenstein’s Understanding of Frege: The Pre-Tractarian Evidence. In Reck, E., ed., From Frege to Wittgenstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 185200.Google Scholar
Grasshoff, G. (1997) Hertzian Objects in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. British Journal of the History of Philosophy 5:1, pp. 87119.Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. (1986) Insight and Illusion. 2nd edition. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. (1999) Naming, Thinking and Meaning in the Tractatus. Philosophical Investigations 22:2, pp. 119135.Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. (2000) Was He Trying to Whistle it? In Crary, A. and Read, R., eds., The New Wittgenstein. London: Routledge, pp. 353–88.Google Scholar
Hänsel, L. (2012) Begegnungen mit Wittgenstein – Ludwig Hänsels Tagebücher 1918–1919 und 1921–1922. Edited by Somavilla, I.. Wien: Haymon Verlag.Google Scholar
Hintikka, J. and Hintikka, M. (1986) Investigating Wittgenstein. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hutto, D. (2006) Wittgenstein and the End of Philosophy: Neither Theory nor Therapy. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Hylton, P. (1992) Russell, Idealism, and the Emergence of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hylton, P. (2005) Logic in Russell’s Logicism. In Propositions, Functions, and Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 4982.Google Scholar
Ishiguro, H. (1969) Use and Reference of Names. In Winch, P., ed., Studies in the Philosophy of Wittgenstein. London: Routledge, pp. 2050.Google Scholar
Janik, A. and Toulmin, S. (1973) Wittgenstein’s Vienna. New York: Touchstone.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. (1974) For Self-Examination and Judge for Yourself. Translated by W. Lowrie. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. (1987) Either/Or, Part I. Translated by Hong, H. V. and Hong, E. H.. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. (2009a) Concluding Unscientific Postscript to the Philosophical Crumbs. Translated by A. Hannay. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. (2009b) The Point of View for My Work as an Author. Translated by H. V. Hong and E. H. Hong. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kremer, M. (1997) Contextualism and Holism in Early Wittgenstein: From Prototractatus to Tractatus. Philosophical Topics 25:2, pp. 87120.Google Scholar
Kremer, M. (2001) The Purpose of Tractarian Nonsense. Nous 35:1, pp. 3973.Google Scholar
Kuusela, O. (2011) The Dialectic of Interpretations: Reading the Tractatus. In Read, R. and Lavery, M. A., eds., Beyond the “Tractatus” War: The New Wittgenstein Debate. New York: Routledge, pp. 121148.Google Scholar
Kuusela, O. (2019) Wittgenstein on Logic and the Method of Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Landini, G. (2007) Wittgenstein’s Apprenticeship with Russell. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lugg, A. (2013) Wittgenstein’s True Thoughts. Nordic Wittgenstein Review 2:1, pp. 3356.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malcolm, N. (1986) Nothing is Hidden. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Marion, M. (1998) Wittgenstein, Finitism, and the Foundations of Mathematics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
McGinn, M. (1999) Between Metaphysics and Nonsense: Elucidation in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. Philosophical Quarterly 49:147, pp. 491513.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGinn, M. (2006) Elucidating the Tractatus.” Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
McGuinness, B. (1988) Wittgenstein: A Life; Young Ludwig (1889–1921). Duckworth.Google Scholar
McGuinness, B. (2002) Approaches to Wittgenstein (Collected Papers). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
McManus, D. (2010) The Enchantment of Words: Wittgenstein’s “Tractatus Logico-philosophicus. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. (2000 [1903]) Principia Ethica. Edited by Baldwin, T.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1922) The Conception of Intrinsic Value. In Philosophical Studies. New York: Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Mounce, H. O. (1989) Wittgenstein’s “Tractatus”: An Introduction. Chicago:The University of Chicago Press, Midway Reprint Edition.Google Scholar
Moyal-Sharrock, D. (2007) The Good Sense of Nonsense. Philosophy 82, pp. 147177.Google Scholar
Neurath, O. (1983 [1931a]) Physicalism. In Philosophical Papers 1913–1946. Dordrecht: D Reidel Publishing Company, pp. 5257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neurath, O. (1983 [1931b]) Sociology in the Framework of Physicalism. In Philosophical Papers 1913–1946. Dordrecht: D Reidel Publishing Company, pp. 5890.Google Scholar
Pears, D. (1987) The False Prison, vol. 1. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Potter, M. (2011) Wittgenstein’s Notes on Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (2001) Justice as Fairness: A Restatement. Edited by Kelly, E.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reid, L. (1998) Wittgenstein’s Ladder: The Tractatus and Nonsense. Philosophical Investigations 21 2, pp. 97151.Google Scholar
Rhees, R. (1996 [1970]) Discussions of Wittgenstein. Bristol: Toemmes Press.Google Scholar
Ricketts, T. (1996) Pictures, Logic, and the Limits of Sense in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. In Stern, D. and Sluga, H., eds., The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 5999.Google Scholar
Ricketts, T. (2014) Analysis, Independence, Simplicity, and the General Propositional-Form. Philosophical Topics 42:2, pp. 263288.Google Scholar
Russell, B., (1992 [1905]) On Denoting. In Logic and Knowledge. London: Routledge, pp. 3956.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1910) Philosophical Essays. London: Longmans, Green, and Co.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1997 [1912]) The Problems of Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1999 [1913]) Theory of Knowledge (The 1913 Manuscript). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1995 [1914a]) Our Knowledge of the External World. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (2004 [1914b]) On Scientific Method in Philosophy. In Mysticism and Logic. New York: Dover Publications.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1998a [1918]) The Philosophy of Logical Atomism. Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1998b [1919]) Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1968) The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell 1874–1914. New York: Bantan Books.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (2002) The Selected Letters of Bertrand Russell: The Public Years, 1914–1970. Edited by Griffin, N.. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Russell, B. and Whitehead, A. N. (1973 [1910]) Principia Mathematica (to *56). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Stern, D. (2004) Wittgenstein’s “Philosophical Investigations”: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sullivan, P. (2004) What is the Tractatus About? In Koelbel, M. and Weiss, B., eds., Wittgenstein’s Lasting Significance. London: Routledge, pp. 2841.Google Scholar
Tejedor, C. (2015) The Early Wittgenstein on Metaphysics, Natural Science, Language, and Value. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Von Wright, G. H. (1980) Wittgenstein. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
White, R. (2006) Wittgenstein’s “Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. London: Continuum.Google Scholar
Winch, P. (1987) Trying to Make Sense. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1996 [1959]) An Introduction to Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. Bristol: Thoemmes Press.Google Scholar
Bazzocchi, L. (2015) A Better Appraisal of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Manuscript. Philosophical Investigations 38:4, pp. 333359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Biletzki, A. (2003) (Over)Interpreting Wittgenstein. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
Black, M. (1966) A Companion to Wittgenstein’s “Tractatus. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Cahill, K. M. (2011) The Fate of Wonder: Wittgenstein’s Critique of Metaphysics and Modernity. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1959 [1934]) The Logical Syntax of Language. Translated by A. Smeathon. Paterson: Littlefield.Google Scholar
Conant, J. (1993) Kierkegaard, Wittgenstein and Nonsense. In Cohen, T., Guyer, P., and Putnam, H., eds., Pursuits or Reason: Essays in Honor of Stanley Cavell. Lubock, TX: Texas University Press, pp. 195224.Google Scholar
Conant, J. (1995) Putting Two and Two Together: Kierkegaard, Wittgenstein and the Point of View for Their Works as Authors. In Tessin, T. and von der Ruhr, M., eds., Philosophy and the Grammar of Religious Belief. New York: St. Martin’s Press, pp. 248331.Google Scholar
Conant, J. (2000) Elucidation and Nonsense in Frege and Early Wittgenstein. In Crary, A. and Read, R., eds., The New Wittgenstein. London: Routledge, pp. 174217.Google Scholar
Conant, J. (2005) What Ethics in the Tractatus is Not. In Philips, D. Z. and von der Ruhr, M., eds., Religion and Wittgenstein’s Legacy. London: Ashgate Publishing, pp. 3995.Google Scholar
Conant, J. (2007) Mild Mono-Wittgensteinianism. In Crary, A., ed., Wittgenstein and the Moral Life: Essays in Honor of Cora Diamond. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 31142.Google Scholar
Conant, J. and Bronzo, S. (2017) Resolute Readings of the Tractatus. In Glock, H.-J. and Hyman, J., eds., A Companion to Wittgenstein. Chichester: Wiley Blackwell, pp. 175194.Google Scholar
Conant, J. and Diamond, C. (2004) On Reading the Tractatus Resolutely: Reply to Meredith Williams and Peter Sullivan. In Koelbel, M. and Weiss, B., eds., Wittgenstein’s Lasting Significance. London: Routledge, pp. 4297.Google Scholar
Diamond, C. (1996) The Realistic Spirit: Wittgenstein, Philosophy and the Mind. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Diamond, C. (2000) Ethics, Imagination and the Method of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. In Crary, A. and Read, R., eds., The New Wittgenstein. London: Routledge, pp. 149173.Google Scholar
Diamond, C. (2004) Criss-Cross Philosophy. In Ammereller, E. and Fischer, E., eds., Wittgenstein at Work: Method in the “Philosophical Investigations. London: Routledge, pp. 201220.Google Scholar
Diamond, C. (2014) The Hardness of the Soft: Wittgenstein’s Early Thought about Skepticism. In Conant, J. and Kern, A., eds., Varieties of Skepticism: Essays after Kant, Wittgenstein, and Cavell. Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. 145182.Google Scholar
Diamond, C. (2019) Reading Wittgenstein with Anscombe: Going on to Ethics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Engelmann, M. L. (2011) What Wittgenstein’s ‘Grammar’ Is Not (On Garver, Baker and Hacker, and Hacker on Wittgenstein on ‘Grammar’). Wittgenstein-Studien 2, 71102.Google Scholar
Engelmann, M. L. (2013) Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Development: Phenomenology, Grammar, Method, and the Anthropological View. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Engelmann, M. L. (2016) The Faces of Necessity, Perspicuous Representation, and the Irreligious “Cult of the Useful”: The Spenglerian Background of the First Set of Remarks on Frazer. In Albinus, L. and Rothhaupt, J., eds., Wittgenstein’s Remarks on Frazer: The Text and the Matter. Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. 129174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Engelmann, M. L. (2017) What Does a Phenomenological Language Do? (Revisiting “Some Remarks on Logical Form” in Its Context). In Silva, M., ed., Colours in Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Development. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 95126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Engelmann, M. L. (2018a) What Does it Take to Climb the Ladder? (A Sideways Approach). Kriterion 59:140, pp. 591613.Google Scholar
Engelmann, M. L. (2018b) Instructions for Climbing the Ladder (The Minimalism of the Tractatus). Philosophical Investigations 41:4, pp. 446470.Google Scholar
Engelmann, M. L. (2018c) Phenomenology in Grammar: Explicitation-Verificationism, Arbitrariness, and the Vienna Circle. In Kuusela, O., Ometita, M., and Ucan, T., eds., Wittgenstein and Phenomenology. London: Routledge, pp. 2246.Google Scholar
Engelmann, P. (1967) Letters from Ludwig Wittgenstein with a Memoir. Edited by McGuinness, B. and translated by L. Furtmuller. New York: Horizon Press.Google Scholar
Floyd, J. (2001) Numbers and Ascriptions of Numbers in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. In Floyd, J. and Shieh, S., eds., Future Pasts: The Analytic Tradition in Twentieth-Century Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 145192.Google Scholar
Frege, G. (1987 [1884]) Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik. Stuttgart: Reclam.Google Scholar
Frege, G. (1962 [1903]) Grundgesetze der Arithmetik (Begriffsschriftlich Abgeleitet) II. Hildesheim: Georg Olms.Google Scholar
Goldfarb, W. (1997) Metaphysics and Nonsense: On Cora Diamond’s The Realistic Spirit. Journal of Philosophical Research 22, pp. 5773.Google Scholar
Goldfarb, W. (2002) Wittgenstein’s Understanding of Frege: The Pre-Tractarian Evidence. In Reck, E., ed., From Frege to Wittgenstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 185200.Google Scholar
Grasshoff, G. (1997) Hertzian Objects in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. British Journal of the History of Philosophy 5:1, pp. 87119.Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. (1986) Insight and Illusion. 2nd edition. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. (1999) Naming, Thinking and Meaning in the Tractatus. Philosophical Investigations 22:2, pp. 119135.Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. (2000) Was He Trying to Whistle it? In Crary, A. and Read, R., eds., The New Wittgenstein. London: Routledge, pp. 353–88.Google Scholar
Hänsel, L. (2012) Begegnungen mit Wittgenstein – Ludwig Hänsels Tagebücher 1918–1919 und 1921–1922. Edited by Somavilla, I.. Wien: Haymon Verlag.Google Scholar
Hintikka, J. and Hintikka, M. (1986) Investigating Wittgenstein. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hutto, D. (2006) Wittgenstein and the End of Philosophy: Neither Theory nor Therapy. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Hylton, P. (1992) Russell, Idealism, and the Emergence of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hylton, P. (2005) Logic in Russell’s Logicism. In Propositions, Functions, and Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 4982.Google Scholar
Ishiguro, H. (1969) Use and Reference of Names. In Winch, P., ed., Studies in the Philosophy of Wittgenstein. London: Routledge, pp. 2050.Google Scholar
Janik, A. and Toulmin, S. (1973) Wittgenstein’s Vienna. New York: Touchstone.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. (1974) For Self-Examination and Judge for Yourself. Translated by W. Lowrie. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. (1987) Either/Or, Part I. Translated by Hong, H. V. and Hong, E. H.. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. (2009a) Concluding Unscientific Postscript to the Philosophical Crumbs. Translated by A. Hannay. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. (2009b) The Point of View for My Work as an Author. Translated by H. V. Hong and E. H. Hong. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kremer, M. (1997) Contextualism and Holism in Early Wittgenstein: From Prototractatus to Tractatus. Philosophical Topics 25:2, pp. 87120.Google Scholar
Kremer, M. (2001) The Purpose of Tractarian Nonsense. Nous 35:1, pp. 3973.Google Scholar
Kuusela, O. (2011) The Dialectic of Interpretations: Reading the Tractatus. In Read, R. and Lavery, M. A., eds., Beyond the “Tractatus” War: The New Wittgenstein Debate. New York: Routledge, pp. 121148.Google Scholar
Kuusela, O. (2019) Wittgenstein on Logic and the Method of Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Landini, G. (2007) Wittgenstein’s Apprenticeship with Russell. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lugg, A. (2013) Wittgenstein’s True Thoughts. Nordic Wittgenstein Review 2:1, pp. 3356.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malcolm, N. (1986) Nothing is Hidden. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Marion, M. (1998) Wittgenstein, Finitism, and the Foundations of Mathematics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
McGinn, M. (1999) Between Metaphysics and Nonsense: Elucidation in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. Philosophical Quarterly 49:147, pp. 491513.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGinn, M. (2006) Elucidating the Tractatus.” Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
McGuinness, B. (1988) Wittgenstein: A Life; Young Ludwig (1889–1921). Duckworth.Google Scholar
McGuinness, B. (2002) Approaches to Wittgenstein (Collected Papers). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
McManus, D. (2010) The Enchantment of Words: Wittgenstein’s “Tractatus Logico-philosophicus. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. (2000 [1903]) Principia Ethica. Edited by Baldwin, T.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1922) The Conception of Intrinsic Value. In Philosophical Studies. New York: Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Mounce, H. O. (1989) Wittgenstein’s “Tractatus”: An Introduction. Chicago:The University of Chicago Press, Midway Reprint Edition.Google Scholar
Moyal-Sharrock, D. (2007) The Good Sense of Nonsense. Philosophy 82, pp. 147177.Google Scholar
Neurath, O. (1983 [1931a]) Physicalism. In Philosophical Papers 1913–1946. Dordrecht: D Reidel Publishing Company, pp. 5257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neurath, O. (1983 [1931b]) Sociology in the Framework of Physicalism. In Philosophical Papers 1913–1946. Dordrecht: D Reidel Publishing Company, pp. 5890.Google Scholar
Pears, D. (1987) The False Prison, vol. 1. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Potter, M. (2011) Wittgenstein’s Notes on Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (2001) Justice as Fairness: A Restatement. Edited by Kelly, E.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reid, L. (1998) Wittgenstein’s Ladder: The Tractatus and Nonsense. Philosophical Investigations 21 2, pp. 97151.Google Scholar
Rhees, R. (1996 [1970]) Discussions of Wittgenstein. Bristol: Toemmes Press.Google Scholar
Ricketts, T. (1996) Pictures, Logic, and the Limits of Sense in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. In Stern, D. and Sluga, H., eds., The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 5999.Google Scholar
Ricketts, T. (2014) Analysis, Independence, Simplicity, and the General Propositional-Form. Philosophical Topics 42:2, pp. 263288.Google Scholar
Russell, B., (1992 [1905]) On Denoting. In Logic and Knowledge. London: Routledge, pp. 3956.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1910) Philosophical Essays. London: Longmans, Green, and Co.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1997 [1912]) The Problems of Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1999 [1913]) Theory of Knowledge (The 1913 Manuscript). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1995 [1914a]) Our Knowledge of the External World. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (2004 [1914b]) On Scientific Method in Philosophy. In Mysticism and Logic. New York: Dover Publications.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1998a [1918]) The Philosophy of Logical Atomism. Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1998b [1919]) Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1968) The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell 1874–1914. New York: Bantan Books.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (2002) The Selected Letters of Bertrand Russell: The Public Years, 1914–1970. Edited by Griffin, N.. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Russell, B. and Whitehead, A. N. (1973 [1910]) Principia Mathematica (to *56). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Stern, D. (2004) Wittgenstein’s “Philosophical Investigations”: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sullivan, P. (2004) What is the Tractatus About? In Koelbel, M. and Weiss, B., eds., Wittgenstein’s Lasting Significance. London: Routledge, pp. 2841.Google Scholar
Tejedor, C. (2015) The Early Wittgenstein on Metaphysics, Natural Science, Language, and Value. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Von Wright, G. H. (1980) Wittgenstein. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
White, R. (2006) Wittgenstein’s “Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. London: Continuum.Google Scholar
Winch, P. (1987) Trying to Make Sense. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Reading Wittgenstein's Tractatus
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Reading Wittgenstein's Tractatus
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Reading Wittgenstein's Tractatus
Available formats
×