Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-l4dxg Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-01-30T06:21:26.878Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On Believing and Being Convinced

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 January 2025

Paul Silva Jr.
Affiliation:
University of Cologne

Summary

Our doxastic states are our belief-like states, and these include outright doxastic states and degreed doxastic states. The former include believing that p, having the opinion that p, thinking that p, being sure that p, being certain that p, and doubting that p. The latter include degrees of confidence, credences, and perhaps some phenomenal states. But we also have conviction (being convinced simpliciter that p) and degrees of conviction (being more or less convinced that p). This Element shows: how and why all of the outright doxastic states mentioned above can be reduced to conviction thresholds; what degrees of conviction fundamentally are (degreed reliance-dispositions); why degrees of conviction are not credences; when suspending a belief is compatible with continuing to believe; and the surprising extent to which Kant endorsed the theory of conviction that emerges in this Element.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781009524117
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 30 January 2025

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aimar, Simona (2019). Disposition Ascriptions. Philosophical Studies 176 (7):1667–1692.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ashwell, Lauren (2010). Superficial Dispositionalism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88 (4):119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Atkins, Philip (2017). A Russellian Account of Suspended Judgment. Synthese 194:30213046.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beddor, Bob (2020). New Work For Certainty. Philosophers’ Imprint 20 (8):125.Google Scholar
Beddor, Bob & Pavese, Carlotta (2020). Modal Virtue Epistemology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 101 (1):6179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benzenberg, Christopher (forthcoming). Room for Responsibility: Kant on Direct Doxastic Voluntarism. Inquiry.Google Scholar
Borgoni, Cristina, Kindermann, Dirk, & Onofri, Andrea (2021). The Fragmented Mind. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bricker, Adam Michael (2022). I Hear You Feel Confident. Philosophical Quarterly 73 (1):2443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchak, Lara (2014). Belief, Credence, and Norms. Philosophical Studies 169 (2):127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, David (1996). The Conscious Mind. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chignell, Andrew (2007a). Belief in Kant. Philosophical Review 116 (3):323360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chignell, Andrew (2007b). Kant’s Concepts of Justification. Noûs 41 (1):3363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chignell, Andrew (2021). Kantian Fallibilism: Knowledge, Certainty, Doubt. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 45:99128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Choi, Sungho (2013). Can Opposing Dispositions Be Co-instantiated? Erkenntnis 78 (1):161182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Choi, Sungho (2017). Against Intrinsic Interferers: A Critique of Kittle. Philosophical Quarterly 67 (269):845854.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christensen, David (2007). Epistemology of Disagreement: The Good News. Philosophical Review 116:187218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke, Randolph (2010). Opposing Powers. Philosophical Studies 149 (2): 153160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke, Roger (2013). Belief Is Credence One (in Context). Philosophers’ Imprint 13 (11):118.Google Scholar
Clarke, Roger & Staffel, Julia (2023). Are Credences Different From Beliefs? In Roeber, Blake, Steup, Matthias, Turri, John, & Sosa, Ernest (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 3rd edition. Wiley Blackwell, 229252.Google Scholar
Cohen, Alix (2021). Kant on Epistemic Autonomy. In Serck-Hanssen, C. & Himmelmann, B. (eds.), The Court of Reason: Proceedings of the 13th International Kant Congress. De Gruyter, 687696.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crane, Tim (2013). Unconscious Belief and Conscious Thought. In Kriegel, Uriah (ed.), Phenomenal Intentionality. Oxford University Press, 156173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dorst, Kevin (2019). Lockeans Maximize Expected Accuracy. Mind 128 (509):175211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eriksson, Lina & Hájek, Alan (2007). What Are Degrees of Belief? Studia Logica 86 (2):185215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Everett, Anthony (2009). Intrinsic Finks, Masks, and Mimics. Erkenntnis 71 (2):191203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Field, Hartry (1978). Mental Representation. Erkenntnis 13:961.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, Jerry (1990). A Theory of Content and Other Essays. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Foley, Richard (1992). The Epistemology of Belief and the Epistemology of Degrees of Belief. American Philosophical Quarterly 29 (2):111124.Google Scholar
Foley, Richard (1993). Working Without a Net: A Study of Egocentric Epistemology. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Frankish, Keith (2009). Partial Belief and Flat-out Belief. In Huber, Franz & Schmidt-Petri, Christoph (eds.), Degrees of Belief. Springer, 7593.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, Jane (2017). Why Suspend Judging? Noûs 51 (2):302326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, Jane (2019). Inquiry and Belief. Noûs 53 (2):296315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friend, Toby & Kimpton-Nye, Samuel (2023). Dispositions and Powers. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gava, Gabriele (2016). The Fallibilism of Kant’s Architectonic. In Gava, G. & Stern, R. (eds.), Pragmatism, Kant, and Transcendental Philosophy. Routledge, 4666.Google Scholar
Gava, Gabriele (2019). Kant and Crucius on Belief and Practical Justification. Kantian Review 24 (1):5371.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gava, Gabriele (2024). Kant on Conviction and Persuasion. In Filieri, Luigi & Møller, Sofie (eds.), Kant on Freedom and Human Nature. Routledge, 135150.Google Scholar
Goodman, Jeremy (2023). The Myth of Full Belief. Philosophical Perspectives 37 (1):164171. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpe.12185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodman, Jeremy & Holguín, Ben (2023). Thinking and Being Sure. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 106 (3):634654.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greco, Daniel (2015). How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love Probability 1. Philosophical Perspectives 29 (1):179201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greco, Daniel (2023). Idealization in Epistemology. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greco, John (2010). Achieving Knowledge: A Virtue-Theoretic Account of Epistemic Normativity. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Handfield, Toby (2008). Unfinkable Dispositions. Synthese 160 (2):297308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hannon, Michael (2019). What’s the Point of Knowledge? A Function-First Epistemology. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, Gilbert (1986). Change in View: Principles of Reasoning. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, John, Rothschild, Daniel, & Spectre, Levi (2016). Belief is Weak. Philosophical Studies 173 (5):13931404.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hebbeler, James (2021). Reason, Reflection, and Reliabilism: Kant and the Grounds of Rational and Empirical Knowledge. In Serck-Hanssen, C. & Himmelmann, B. (eds.), The Court of Reason: Proceedings of the 13th International Kant Congress. De Gruyter, 735742.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, Roman (2021). Knowledge and Rational Action. Why What We Know Matters for the Rationality of What We Do. Unpublished Doctoral Dissertation. University of Hamburg.Google Scholar
Holguín, Ben (2022). Thinking, Guessing, and Believing. Philosophers’ Imprint 22 (1):134.Google Scholar
Hyman, John (2017). Knowledge and Belief. Aristotelian Society Supplementary 91:267288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Insole, Christopher J. (2019). Free Belief: The Medieval Heritage in Kant’s Moral Faith. Journal of the History of Philosophy 57 (3):501528.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, Elizabeth (2020a). Belief, Credence, and Evidence. Synthese 197 (11):50735092.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, Elizabeth (2020b). The Relationship Between Belief and Credence. Philosophy Compass 15 (6):113.Google Scholar
Johnston, Mark (1992). How to Speak of the Colors. Philosophical Studies 68 (3):221263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1900). Kants Gesammelte Schriften. Königlich-Preußische Akademie der Wissenschaften (ed.). De Gruyter.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1998). Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Timmermann, Jens (ed.). Felix Meiner Verlag.Google Scholar
Kelly, Thomas (2005). The Epistemic Significance of Disagreement. In Gendler, T. & Hawthorne, J. (eds.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology: Volume 1. Oxford University Press, 7196.Google Scholar
Kennedy, Christopher (2007). Vagueness and Grammar: The Semantics of Relative and Absolute Gradable Adjectives. Linguistics and Philosophy 30 (1):145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kern, Andrea (2021). Kant on Doubt and Error. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 45:129154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kittle, Simon (2015). Powers Opposed and Intrinsic Finks. Philosophical Quarterly 65 (260):372380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krifka, Manfred (2002). Be Brief and Vague! And How Bidirectional Optimality Theory Allows for Verbosity and Precision. In Restle, D. & Zaefferer, D. (eds.), Sounds and Systems, Studies in Structure and Change: A Festschrift for Theo Vennemann. Mouton de Gruyter, 439458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krifka, Manfred (2007). Approximate Interpretations of Number Words: A Case of Strategic Communication. In Bouma, G., Kramer, I., & Zwarts, J. (eds.), Cognitive Foundations of Interpretation. Koninklijke Nederlandse Akademie van Wetenschapen, 111126.Google Scholar
Lakoff, George (1973). Hedges: A Study in Meaning Criteria and the Logic of Fuzzy Concepts. Journal of Philosophical Logic 2:458508.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leitgeb, Hannes (2017). The Stability of Belief. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David (1979). Scorekeeping in a Language Game. Journal of Philosophical Logic 8 (3):339359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, John (1975). An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Nidditch, Peter H. (ed.). Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Lord, Errol (2020). Suspension of Judgment, Rationality’s Competition, and the Reach of the Epistemic. In Schmidt, S. & Ernst, G. (eds.), The Ethics of Belief and Beyond. Routledge, 126145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lyons, Jack C. (2009). Perception and Basic Beliefs: Zombies, Modules and the Problem of the External World. Lyons, Jack (ed.). Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manley, David & Wasserman, Ryan (2007). A Gradable Approach to Dispositions. Philosophical Quarterly 57 (226):6875.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manley, David & Wasserman, Ryan (2008). On Linking Dispositions and Conditionals. Mind 117 (465):5984.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manley, David & Wasserman, Ryan (2011). Dispositions, Conditionals, and Counterexamples. Mind 120 (480):11911227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGrath, Matthew (2021a). Being Neutral: Agnosticism, Inquiry and the Suspension of Judgment. Noûs 55 (2):463484.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGrath, Matthew (2021b). Epistemic Norms for Waiting. Philosophical Topics 49 (2):173201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meier, Georg F. (1752). Auszug aus der Vernunftlehre. Johann Justinus Gebauer.Google Scholar
Miller, Christian (2014). Character and Moral Psychology. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miracchi, Lisa (2019). When Evidence Isn’t Enough: Suspension, Evidentialism, and Knowledge-First Virtue Epistemology. Episteme 16 (4):413437.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moon, Andrew (2018). The Nature of Doubt and a New Puzzle about Belief, Doubt, and Confidence. Synthese 195 (4):18271848.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moon, Andrew & Jackson, Elizabeth (2020). Credence: A Belief-First Approach. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 50 (5):652669.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pasternack, Lawrence (2011). The Development and Scope of Kantian Belief: The Highest-Good, The Practical Postulates, and the Fact of Reason. Kant-Studien 102 (3):290315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pasternack, Lawrence (2014). Kant on Opinion: Assent, Hypothesis, and the Norms of General Applied Logic. Kant-Studien 105 (1):4182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pinkal, Manfred (1995). Logic and Lexicon. Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raleigh, Thomas (2021). Suspending is Believing. Synthese 198:24492474CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, Jacob & Schroeder, Mark (2014). Belief, Credence, and Pragmatic Encroachment. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 88 (2):259288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rothschild, Daniel (2020). What It Takes to Believe. Philosophical Studies 177 (5):13451362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rotstein, Carmen & Winter, Yoad (2004). Total Adjectives vs. Partial Adjectives: Scale Structure and Higher-Order Modifiers. Natural Language Semantics 12 (3):259288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sadock, Jerrold (1977). Truth and Approximations. In Whistler, K. Jr., Van Valin, R.D., Chiarello, C., et al. (eds.), Proceedings of the Third Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society. Berkeley Linguistics Society.Google Scholar
Sauerland, Uli & Stateva, Penka (2007). Scalar vs. Epistemic Vagueness: Evidence from Approximators. In Friedman, T. and Gibson, M. (eds.), Proceedings of the 17th Semantics and Linguistic Theory Conference. CLC Publishing, 228245.Google Scholar
Schroeder, Mark (2015). Knowledge Is Belief for Sufficient (Objective and Subjective) Reason. Oxford Studies in Epistemology 5, 226251.Google Scholar
Schulz, Moritz (2021a). Strong Knowledge, Weak Belief? Synthese 199 (3–4):87418753.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schulz, Moritz (2021b). Practical Reasoning and Degrees of Outright Belief. Synthese 199 (3–4):80698090.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwitzgebel, Eric (2002). A Phenomenal, Dispositional Account of Belief. Noûs 36 (2):249275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwitzgebel, Eric (2023). Belief. In Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2023 Edition), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2023/entries/belief/.Google Scholar
Silva, Paul (2016). How Doxastic Justification Helps Us Solve the Puzzle of Misleading Higher-Order Evidence. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 98 (S1):308328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silva, Paul (2023a). Merely Statistical Evidence: When and Why It Justifies Belief. Philosophical Studies 180 (9):26392664.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silva, Paul (2023b). Awareness and the Substructure of Knowledge. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skyrms, Brian (2011). Resiliency, Propensities, and Causal Necessity. In Eagle, Antony (ed.), Philosophy of Probability: Contemporary Readings. Routledge.Google Scholar
Smith, Martin (2016). Between Probability and Certainty: What Justifies Belief. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smithies, Declan (2023). Belief as a Feeling of Conviction. In Schwitzgebel, Eric & Jong, Jonathan (eds.), The Nature of Belief. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sosa, Ernest (2015). Judgment and Agency. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sosa, Ernest (2019). Suspension as Spandrel. Episteme 16(4):357368.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Staffel, Julia (2016). Beliefs, Buses and Lotteries: Why Rational Belief Can’t Be Stably High Credence. Philosophical Studies 173 (7):17211734.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Staffel, Julia (2019). Credences and Suspended Judgments as Transitional Attitudes. Philosophical Issues 29(1):281294.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stalnaker, Robert C. (1984). Inquiry. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Stevenson, Leslie (2003). Opinion, Belief or Faith, and Knowledge. Kantian Review 7:72101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sturgeon, Scott (2010). Confidence and Coarse-Grained Attitudes. In Gendler, T. & Hawthorne, J. (eds.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology: Volume 3. Oxford University Press, 3126.Google Scholar
Sylvan, Kurt (2015). What Apparent Reasons Appear to Be. Philosophical Studies 172 (3):587606.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Titelbaum, Michael (2015). Rationality’s Fixed Point (Or: In Defense of Right Reason). In Hawthorne, J. & Gendler, T. (eds.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology: Volume 5. Oxford University Press, 253294.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turri, John (2015). Unreliable Knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 90 (3):529545.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turri, John (2016). A New Paradigm for Epistemology From Reliabilism to Abilism. Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 3:189231.Google Scholar
Unger, Peter K. (1975). Ignorance. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Vetter, Barbara (2015). Potentiality: From Dispositions to Modality. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wagner, Verena (2022). Agnosticism As Settled Indecision. Philosophical Studies 179 (2):671697.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wedgwood, Ralph (2002). The Aim of Belief. Philosophical Perspectives 16:267297.Google Scholar
Wedgwood, Ralph (2023). Rationality and Belief. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weisberg, Jonathan (2020). Belief in Psyontology. Philosophers’ Imprint 20 (11):127.Google Scholar
White, Roger (2005). Epistemic Permissiveness. Philosophical Perspectives 19 (1):445459.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Willaschek, Marcus (2010): The Primacy of Practical Reason and the Idea of a Practical Postulate. In Reath, Andrews & Timmermann, Jens (eds.), Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason, A Critical Guide. Cambridge University Press, 168196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Willaschek, Marcus & Watkins, Eric (2020). Kant on Cognition and Knowledge. Synthese 197 (8):31953213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, Timothy (2000). Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Zimmerman, Aaron (2018). Belief: A Pragmatic Picture. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zinke, Alexandra (2021). Rational Suspension. Theoria 87 (5):10501066.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

On Believing and Being Convinced
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

On Believing and Being Convinced
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

On Believing and Being Convinced
Available formats
×