Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
  • Cited by 1
Publisher:
Cambridge University Press
Online publication date:
February 2011
Print publication year:
2010
Online ISBN:
9780511763090

Book description

Plato's Republic has proven to be of astounding influence and importance. Justly celebrated as Plato's central text, it brings together all of his prior works, unifying them into a comprehensive vision that is at once theological, philosophical, political and moral. The essays in this volume provide a picture of the most interesting aspects of the Republic, and address questions that continue to puzzle and provoke, such as: Does Plato succeed in his argument that the life of justice is the most attractive one? Is his tripartite analysis of the soul coherent and plausible? Why does Plato seem to have to force his philosopher-guardians to rule when they know this is something that they ought to do? What is the point of the strange and complicated closing Myth of Er? This volume will be essential to those looking for thoughtful and detailed excursions into the problems posed by Plato's text and ideas.

Reviews

'In the past few years, the Republic's readers have already been lucky enough to see two other fine anthologies dedicated to that dialogue … This new Critical Guide is much shorter than those, but it stands well in their company … This volume, a collection of papers that were mostly presented at a 2008 conference, is pitched to specialists slightly more than the other anthologies are … its selections are shorter, so even the difficult chapters feel more inviting than longer versions of them would have been. Freshness is at a premium … rich assortment … a wide spectrum of issues has been updated in this excellent book. Every philosopher who has thought about the Republic will find something here that illuminates an aspect of the dialogue; specialists will want to spend time with many of the twelve selections.'

Nickolas Pappas Source: Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews

Refine List

Actions for selected content:

Select all | Deselect all
  • View selected items
  • Export citations
  • Download PDF (zip)
  • Save to Kindle
  • Save to Dropbox
  • Save to Google Drive

Save Search

You can save your searches here and later view and run them again in "My saved searches".

Please provide a title, maximum of 40 characters.
×

Contents

  • 1 - Socrates in the Republic
    pp 11-31
  • View abstract

    Summary

    Not only is Socrates one of the fictional characters in the Republic, he is also its fictional voice. To the modern narratologist, Socrates is the Republic's "internal narrator". This chapter begins with a description of his private thoughts. It also discusses three other Platonic dialogues, internally narrated by Socrates: the Lysis, the Charmides, and the Lovers. Unexpected interventions are plentiful in the Republic; and they are sometimes connected with a private thought of Socrates' in a way that has no parallel in the other three dialogues for which he serves as internal narrator. Socrates invites Glaucon to join him as he rousts justice from a shadowy thicket; shouts as he comes upon its tracks; berates himself for not seeing it sooner. Socrates becomes less authoritative in the sense that he is no longer concealing his moves from his interlocutors.
  • 2 - Platonic ring-composition and Republic 10
    pp 32-51
  • View abstract

    Summary

    Ring-composition makes it possible for the culminating insights and conclusions of a work to be experienced as moments of recognition. It is found in every kind of temporally extended artistic composition, on every scale, and in a bewildering variety of patterns: ABA, ABBA, ABCBA, ABCCBA, and so on indefinitely. Scholars have inferred that it is a marker of oral composition; but ring-composition of various kinds is pervasive in later Greek literature as well as well, including Pindar, Herodotus, Thucydides, and various orators and epigrammatists. It has tended to go undetected in philosophical texts-or perhaps to be ignored as philosophically insignificant. The chapter remedies this partially for the case of Plato, and the Republic in particular, after noting some other instances of ring-composition in Plato and Aristotle. It shows ring-composition in Plato and Aristotle, and explanatory regress more generally, as expressing a distinctively Platonic-Aristotelian conception of philosophical method.
  • 3 - The Atlantis story: the Republic and the Timaeus
    pp 52-64
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter focuses on the Atlantis story and its links to the main argument of the Republic and the cosmology of the Timaeus. The Atlantis story is fiction invented by Plato, which is intended to carry an ethical message. The story insists on its own truth, something which is a familiar feature of fiction. The Republic argues for the value and benefit of virtue in a person's life even in the worst conditions of the actual world. In the Timaeus Plato creates a cosmology in which the goodness of the gods, insisted on in the Republic, is seen in the good ordering and construction of the whole cosmos, in which virtue and vice get the appropriate reward despite appearances. In the Timaeus the story is presented as a narrative which supports philosophical ideas. But what has actually appealed about the story is the fantastic and exotic aspect of Atlantis.
  • 4 - Ethics and politics in Socrates' defense of justice
    pp 65-82
  • View abstract

    Summary

    In the Republic, Socrates argues that justice ought to be valued both for its own sake and for the sake of its consequences. Scholars divide over the importance of politics in the Republic. This chapter argues that the account of the ideal city in Socrates' defense of justice plays the role of connecting justice as a structural condition of the soul and just behavior. It raises a worry that the defense is question-begging and show why it is not. The chapter discusses some methodological implications relevant to the controversy in Plato scholarship about the relative roles of ethics and politics in the argument of the Republic. In the middle books of the Republic, Socrates lays out the very intellectually demanding conditions for knowledge of what justice is, which involve knowledge of the Good itself, a knowledge he himself lacks.
  • 5 - Return to the cave
    pp 83-102
  • View abstract

    Summary

    The problem addressed in this chapter, sometimes called "the happy philosopher problem", is that one of the main arguments of the Republic was supposed to show that justice is preferable to injustice, for the agent. Based on the Republic, the chapter highlights doing what is just is not preferable to those who must return to the cave, who would be happier shirking their duties and remaining uninvolved with the dirty business of politics. In the case of the returners, Plato provides a counter example to his claim that justice is invariably preferable to injustice. When Plato discusses injustice as psychic disharmony, the account requires that each part of the soul must "do its own". The chapter concludes that how refusing to return to the cave would be psychically unbalancing, and also how the incomplete education of the returners could be used to explain their epistemic defects.
  • 6 - Degenerate regimes in Plato's Republic
    pp 103-131
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter concerns the negative end of the political argument of the Republic. According to the political philosophy presented in the Republic and the Laws, one's political standard ultimately determines the practical choices one makes about political institutions and laws. The political turmoil of the late fifth and early fourth centuries clearly lies in the background of Plato's Republic. The chapter overviews the system of degenerate regimes in Book 8 and examines what exactly goes wrong with them and why. It explains how the process of degeneration ought to be understood as the progressive decay of the rule of reason. The chapter shows how the central contrast between the rule of reason and the rule of appetite is prefigured in earlier and less systematic parts of the Republic: the Ship of State image and the argument with Thrasymachus in Book 1.
  • 7 - Virtue, luck, and choice at the end of the Republic
    pp 132-146
  • View abstract

    Summary

    The Republic famously ends with a consideration of the question of the rewards of justice by proving the soul's immortality. Plato begins by affirming Adeimantus' story that the gods reward just souls and punish the unjust during the course of their earthly lives, and then just as Cephalus feared, the gods do the same in the afterlife. Every commentator on the Myth of Er has rightly understood Plato's insertion of the initial lottery to be his way of initially absolving the gods of moral responsibility for each soul's choice of a life and the consequences that accompany that choice. Blame for one's placement in the choice-queue will then be placed on tuche, commonly translated as "luck" or "chance". The end of the Republic can be read as returning us to the stern Socrates of Book I who urges us to choose the path of justice simpliciter, and damn the consequences.
  • 8 - Plato's divided soul
    pp 147-170
  • View abstract

    Summary

    Plato's reason for introducing a tripartite soul into the Republic pertains to the overarching goals of that work: Plato wishes to establish the nature of justice and thereby to show why an individual might wish to be just rather than unjust. In saying that the soul had appeared to the interlocutors of the Republic to be composite, Plato is evidently alluding to the argument for the tripartition of the soul in Book 4 of the Republic. Plato's argument proceeds in two stages. First, he establishes that the reasoning element (to logistikon) is not the same as the appetitive element. He then turns to the slightly more vexed question of whether there is a third element, reducible to neither the appetitive nor the rational. According to Plato, internal discord arises when our motivational streams are not integrated with one another, when and only when we are suffering from psychic disarray.
  • 9 - The meaning of “saphēneia” in Plato's Divided Line
    pp 171-187
  • View abstract

    Summary

    Plato's famous comparison of the different forms of human awareness with a line divided into four parts contains many puzzling features. This chapter talks about Socrates' most puzzling claim, namely that the different line segments provide a measure of the relative degrees of sapheneia and asapheia- usually translated into English as "clarity" and "obscurity"- available to human beings. It argues that none of the usual translations of sapheneia provides us with a satisfactory understanding of this remark. The chapter reviews the use of saphes and its cognates from the time of the Homeric poems down to the fourth century BCE and argues that the relevant sense of sapheneia in this setting is "full, accurate and sure awareness of an object". Socrates concludes that justice exists in the individual when each of the elements in the soul does its own and avoids meddling in the business of the others.
  • 10 - Plato's philosophical method in the Republic: the Divided Line (510b–511d)
    pp 188-208
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter discusses Plato's image of the Divided Line which focuses on the nature of the ontological divisions associated with the four sections of the Line, especially the third. The initial division of the Line into two parts suggests an ontological focus. The top two sections of the line are distinguished in terms of a method or procedure of the soul. Divided Line passage suggests that the dianoetic and dialectical methods employs the general method as the Meno and traditionally called the method of hypothesis. The difference between dianoetic and dialectic lies in how each treats its hypotheses. The dianoetic method is in some way inferior to dialectic. The chapter examines the consequences of the hypothesis that follow directly from the nature of the Forms involved and not from contingent or artificial features of the hypothesis.
  • 11 - Blindness and reorientation: education and the acquisition of knowledge in the Republic
    pp 209-228
  • View abstract

    Summary

    Platonic education is forced to extend its purview to appetite and spirit. In the Republic, this part of education is discussed first, in Books 2 and 3. This chapter focuses on Platonic education's primary target and on the perplexing contrast Socrates draws between reorienting it and curing its blindness. Self-styled educators, who claim to be able to put knowledge into souls like sight into blind eyes stand revealed as people who think that the soul does not need an eye, a divine or god-like element, in order to acquire knowledge. Even if the soul were blind, so that it couldn't see the good itself were the two face to face, it could still, by learning everything else the philosopher learns, acquire knowledge. Countenancing the good, however, is a precondition of countenancing any forms.
  • 12 - Music all pow'rful
    pp 229-248
  • View abstract

    Summary

    In this chapter, the author argues for the centrality of music in Plato's conception of education in the Republic. It explores some of the key passages in Book 3 where Socrates explains the importance of music for fostering our capacity for philosophy and what sort of music is appropriate for training the city's guards and how musical mimesis works. The chapter considers why it is that poetry looms much larger than music in most accounts of the dialogue's teaching on art and culture. Music saturates the cultural thinking of the Laws. The whole system of choral performance is grounded in a theory about human nature to explain our attraction to art than anything Plato offers us in the Republic. The theory is first introduced in Book 1 of the dialogue, and then rearticulated in the form relevant to an education at the beginning of Book 2.
Bibliography
Adam, J. 1905. The Republic of Plato. 2 vols. Cambridge.
Adam, J. 1963. The Republic of Plato. 2 vols. 2nd edn. Cambridge.
Adkins, A. W. H. 1960. Merit and Responsibility: A Study in Greek Values. Oxford; rpt. Chicago.
Adkins, A. W. H. 1971. “Polupragmosune and ‘Minding One's Own Business’: A Study in Greek Social and Political Values.” Classical Philology 71(4): 301–27.
Albinus, L. 1998. “The Katabasis of Er.” In Essays on Plato's Republic, ed. Ostenfeld, E. N.. Aarhus.
Allan, D. J., ed. 1993. Plato: Republic I. Bristol.
Annas, J. 1981. An Introduction to Plato's Republic. Oxford.
Annas, J. 1982a. “Knowledge and Language: The Theaetetus and the Cratylus.” In Language and Logos, ed. Nussbaum, M. and Schofield, M.. Cambridge, 95–114.
Annas, J. 1982b. “Plato's Myths of Judgment.” Phronesis 27: 119–43.
Annas, J. 1999. Platonic Ethics Old and New. Cornell.
,Anonymous. 1963. Prolegomena to Platonic Philosophy, trans. Westerlink, L. G.. Amsterdam.
Archer-Hind, R. 1881. “On Some Difficulties in the Platonic Psychology.” The Journal of Philology 10: 120–31.
Aronson, S. H. 1972. “The Happy Philosopher Problem – A Counterexample to Plato's Proof.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 10: 383–98.
Bailey, D. T. J. 2006. “Plato and Aristotle on the Unhypothetical.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 30: 101–26.
Balot, R. 2001. Greed and Injustice in Classical Athens. Princeton.
Baltzly, D. 1996. “‘To an Unhypothetical First Principle’ in Plato's Republic.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 13: 149–65.
Barker, A. 1984. Greek Musical Writings, vol. 1. Cambridge.
Barker, A. 1989. Greek Musical Writings, vol. 2. Cambridge.
Barker, A. 2005. Psicomusicologia nella grecia antica. Naples.
Barker, A. 2007. The Science of Harmonics in Classical Greece. Cambridge.
Barnes, J. ed. 1984. The Complete Works of Aristotle. Princeton.
Barney, R. 2001a. Names and Nature in Plato's Cratylus. New York.
Barney, R. 2001b. “Platonism, Moral Nostalgia, and the ‘City of Pigs’.” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 17: 207–27.
Barney, R. 2004. “Callicles and Thrasymachus.” In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. (http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/callicles-thrasymachus).
Barney, R. 2006. “Socrates' Refutation of Thrasymachus.” In Santas, 2006, 44–62.
Beatty, J. 1976a. “Plato's Happy Philosophers and Politics.” The Review of Politics 38: 545–75.
Beatty, J. 1976b. “Why Should Plato's Philosopher Be Moral, and Hence, Rule?The Personalist 57: 132–44.
Bedu-Addo, J. T. 1978. “Mathematics, Dialectic and the Good in the Republic VI–VII.” Platon 30: 111–27.
Bedu-Addo, J. T. 1979. “The Role of the Hypothetical Method in the Phaedo.” Phronesis 24: 111–27.
Belfiore, E. 1983. “Plato's Greatest Accusation Against Poetry.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9: 39–56.
Benardete, S. 1989. Socrates' Second Sailing: On Plato's Republic. Chicago.
Benson, H. H. 2000. Socratic Wisdom: The Model of Knowledge in Plato's Early Dialogues. New York.
Benson, H. H. 2003. “The Method of Hypothesis in the Meno.” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 18: 95–126.
Benson, H. H. 2006. “Plato's Method of Dialectic.” In A Companion to Plato, ed. Benson, H.. Oxford, 85–100.
Benson, H. H. 2008. “Knowledge, Virtue, and Method in Republic 471c–502c.” Philosophical Inquiry 30: 1–28.
Berry, E. G. 1940. The History and Development of the Concept of THEIA MOIRA and THEIA TUCHÊ Down to and Including Plato. Chicago.
Blondell, R. 2002. The Play of Character in Plato's Dialogues. Cambridge.
Bloom, A. 1968. The Republic of Plato. New York.
Blössner, N. 1997. Dialogform und Argument: Studien zu Platons “Politeia”. Stuttgart.
Blössner, N. 2007. “The City–Soul Analogy.” In Ferrari, 2007, 345–85.
Bluck, R. S. 1955. Plato's Phaedo. London.
Bobonich, Christopher. 2001. “Akrasia and Agency in Plato's Laws and Republic.” In Essays in Plato's Psychology, ed. Wagner, E.. Lexington; originally published in Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 76 (1994): 3–36.
Bobonich, Christopher. 2002. Plato's Utopia Recast: His Later Ethics and Politics (Oxford: Clarendon Press).
Bodéüs, R. 1993. The Political Dimensions of Aristotle's Ethics. Albany.
Bostock, D. 1986. Plato Phaedo. Oxford.
Brancacci, A. 2005. “Musique et philosophie en République 2–4.” In Études sur la République de Platon, vol. 1, ed. Dixsaut, M.. Paris.
Brann, E. 1967. “The Music of the Republic.” Agon 1: 1–117.
Brann, E. 2004. The Music of the Republic: Essays on Socrates' Conversations and Plato's Writings. Philadelphia. First published as: “The Music of the Republic.” St. John's Review 39 (1989–90): 1–103.
Brickhouse, T. C. 1998. “The Paradox of the Philosophers' Rule.” In Smith 1998, vol. 2, 141–52.
Brisson, L. 1992. Platon, Timée–Critias. Paris.
Brisson, L. 1998. Plato the Myth Maker. Tr. Naddaf, G.. Chicago.
Broadie, S. 2001. “Theodicy and Pseudo-History in the Timaeus.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 21: 1–28.
Broadie, S. 2005. “Virtue and Beyond in Plato and Aristotle.” Southern Journal of Philosophy 43: 97–114.
Brown, E. 2000. “Justice and Compulsion for Plato's Philosopher-Rulers.” Ancient Philosophy 20: 1–17.
Brown, E. 2004. “Minding the Gap in Plato's Republic.” Philosophical Studies 117: 272–302.
Burkert, W. 1985. Greek Religion. Harvard.
Burnyeat, M. F. 1977. “Examples in Epistemology: Socrates, Theaetetus and G. E. Moore.” Philosophy 52: 381–98.
Burnyeat, M. F. 1987. “Platonism and Mathematics: A Prelude to Discussion.” In Mathematics and Metaphysics in Aristotle, ed. Graeser, A.. Stuttgart.
Burnyeat, M. F. 1999. “Culture and Society in Plato's Republic.” Tanner Lectures in Human Values 20: 215–334.
Burnyeat, M. F. 2000. “Plato on Why Mathematics is Good for the Soul.” In Mathematics and Necessity, ed. Smiley, T.Oxford, 1–81.
Byrd, M. 2007a. “Dialectic and Plato's Method of Hypothesis.” Apeiron 40: 141–58.
Byrd, M. 2007. “The Summoner Approach: A New Method of Plato Interpretation.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 45: 365–81.
Calvo, T. and Brisson, L., eds. 1997. Interpreting the Timaeus–Critias. Sankt Augustin.
Chantraine, P. 1968, 1970, 1975, 1977, 1980. Dictionnaire étymologique de la langue grecque. Paris.
Cherniss, H. 1971. “The Sources of Evil According to Plato.” In Plato: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. Vlastos, G.. Garden City, 244–58.
Chisholm, Roderick. 1991. “On the Simplicity of the Soul.” Philosophical Perspectives 5: 167–81.
Clay, D. 1994. “The Origins of the Socratic Dialogue.” In The Socratic Movement, ed. Vander Waerdt, P. A.. Ithaca, 23–47.
Clay, D. 1997. “The Plan of Plato's Critias.” In Interpreting the Timaeus–Critias, ed. Calvo, T.. Sankt Augustin, 49–54.
Clay, D. 1999. “Plato's Atlantis: the Anatomy of a Fiction.” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 15: 1–21.
Clay, D. and Purvis, A.. 1999. Four Island Utopias. Newburyport.
Cole, T. 1983. “Archaic Truth.” Quaderni Urbinati di Cultura Classica 64: 7–28.
Collard, C., Cropp, M. J., and Lee, K. H. 1995. Euripides: Selected Fragmentary Plays, 1. Warminster.
Collard, C., Cropp, M. J., and Gilbert, J. 2004. Euripides: Selected Fragmentary Plays, 2. Warminster.
Cooper, J. 1984. “Plato's Theory of Human Motivation.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 1: 3–21.
Cooper, J. 1997a. “The Psychology of Justice in Plato.” Rpt. In Reason and Emotion. Princeton. First published in American Philosophical Quarterly 14 (1977): 151–57.
Cooper, J. ed. 1997b. Plato: Complete Works. Indianapolis.
Cooper, J. forthcoming. “Political Community and the Highest Good.” In Being, Nature, and Life: Essays in Honor of Allan Gotthelf, ed. Bolton, R. and Lennox, J.. Cambridge.
Cooper, N. 1966. “The Importance of Dianoia in Plato's Theory of Forms.” Classical Quarterly 16: 65–69.
Cornford, F. M. 1945. The Republic of Plato. London and New York.
Cornford, F. M. 1965. “Mathematics and Dialectic in Republic VI–VII.” In Studies in Plato's Metaphysics, ed. Allen, R. E.. London.
Cross, R. C., and Woozley, A. D.. 1964. Plato's Republic: A Philosophical Commentary. London.
Dahl, N. O. 1991. “Plato's Defense of Justice.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51: 809–34.
Davies, J. 1968. “A Note on the Philosopher's Descent into the Cave.” Philologus 112: 121–26.
Jong, I. 2004. “Narratological Theory on Narrators, Narratees, and Narrative.” In Jong, et al. 2004.
Jong, I., Nünlist, R., and Bowie, A., eds. 2004. Narrators, Narratees, and Narratives in Ancient Greek Literature. Leiden.
Demos, R. 1964. “A Fallacy in Plato's Republic?Philosophical Review 73: 395–98.
Denyer, N. 2007. “Sun and Line: The Role of the Good.” In Ferrari, 2007, 284–309.
Diels, H., and Kranz, W.. 1951. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. 6th edn. Berlin.
Dobbs, D. 1985. “The Justice of Socrates' Philosopher Kings.” American Journal of Political Science 29: 809–26.
Dodds, E. R. 1951. The Greeks and the Irrational. Berkeley.
Dorion, L.-A., trans., comm. 1995. Aristote: Les Réfutations Sophistiques. Paris.
Dorter, K. 2003. “Free Will, Luck, and Happiness in the Myth of Er.” Journal of Philosophical Research 28: 129–42.
Dorter, K. 2006. The Transformation of Plato's Republic. Lanham.
Douglas, M. 2007. Thinking in Circles: An Essay on Ring-Composition. New Haven.
Eliot, T. S. 1944. “Little Gidding.” In Four Quartets. London.
Ellis, R. 1998. Imagining Atlantis. New York.
Else, G. 1972. “The Structure and Date of Book 10 of Plato's Republic.” Abhandlungen der Heidelberger Akademie der Wissenschaften. Heidelberg.
Feeney, D. C. 1993. “Towards an Account of the Ancient World's Concept of Fictive Belief.” In Gill, and Wiseman, 1993.
Ferrari, G. R. F. 2003. City and Soul in Plato's Republic. Sankt Augustin.
Ferrari, G. R. F. 2008a. “Glaucon's Reward, Philosophy's Debt: The Myth of Er.” In Plato's Myths, ed. Partenie, C.Oxford.
Ferrari, G. R. F. 2008b. “Socratic Irony as Pretence.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 34: 1–33.
Ferrari, G. R. F., ed. 2007. The Cambridge Companion to Plato's Republic. Cambridge.
Ferrari, G. R. F., ed., and Griffith, T., trans. 2000. Plato: the Republic. Cambridge.
Fine, G. 1990. “Knowledge and Belief in Republic V–VII.” In Epistemology, ed. Everson, S.. Cambridge, 85–115.
Fine, G. 1999. “Knowledge and Belief in Republic 5–7.” In Plato 1: Metaphysics and Epistemology, ed. Fine, G.. Oxford, 215–46.
Fogelin, R. J. 1971. “Three Platonic Analogies.” Philosophical Review 80: 371–82.
Foley, R. 2008. “Plato's Undividable Line: Contradiction and Method in Republic VI.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 46: 1–23.
Ford, A. 2004. “Catharsis: The Power of Music in Aristotle's Politics.” In Music and Muses, ed. Murray, P. and Wilson, P.. Oxford.
Forster, M. 2007. “Socrates' Profession of Ignorance.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 32: 1–35.
Foster, M. B. 1936. “Some Implications of a Passage in Plato's Republic.” Philosophy 11: 301–08.
Foster, M. B. 1937. “A Mistake in Plato's Republic.” Mind 46: 386–93.
Frede, D. 1996. “Plato, Popper, and Historicism.” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 12: 247–76.
Frede, M. 1992. “Plato's Arguments and the Dialogue Form.” In Klagge, and Smith, 1992, 201–19.
Gallop, D. 1965. “Image and Reality in Plato's Republic.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 47: 113–31.
Gentzler, J. 1991. “Sumphonein in Plato's Phaedo.” Phronesis 36: 265–77.
Gifford, E. H. 1905. The Euthydemus of Plato. Oxford.
Gill, C. 1977. “The Genre of the Atlantis Story.” Classical Philology 72: 287–304.
Gill, C. 1979. “Plato's Atlantis Story and the Birth of Fiction.” Philosophy and Literature 3: 64–78.
Gill, C. 1980. Plato, the Atlantis Story (Timaeus 17–27, Critias). Bristol.
Gill, C. 1993. “Plato on Falsehood – not Fiction.” In Gill, and Wiseman, 1983, 38–87.
Gill, C. and Wiseman, T. 1996. Personality in Greek Epic, Tragedy, and Philosophy. Oxford.
Gill, C. and Wiseman, T., eds. 1993. Lies and Fiction in the Ancient World. Exeter and Austin.
Gonzalez, F. J. 1998. Dialectic and Dialogue: Plato's Practice of Philosophical Inquiry. Evanston.
Gosling, J. C. B. 1973. Plato. London.
Griswold, C. L. 1986. Self-Knowledge in Plato's Phaedrus. New Haven.
Grube, G. M. A. 1992. Plato's Republic. Indianapolis.
Guthrie, W. K. C. 1950. The Greeks and Their Gods. London.
Guthrie, W. K. C. 1971. Socrates. Cambridge.
Guthrie, W. K. C. 1975. A History of Greek Philosophy, vol. 4: Plato, The Man and His Dialogues: Earlier Period. Cambridge.
Hall, D. 1977. “The Republic and the Limits of Politics.” Political Theory 5: 293–313.
Halliwell, S. 1988. Republic 10. Warminster.
Halliwell, S. 2002. The Aesthetics of Mimesis. Princeton.
Halliwell, S. 2007. “The Life and Death Journey of the Soul: Interpreting the Myth of Er.” In Ferrari, 2007, 445–73.
Halperin, D. M. 1992. “Plato and the Erotics of Narrativity.” In Klagge, and Smith, 1992, 93–129.
Harte, V. 2006. “Beware of Imitations: Image Recognition in Plato.” In Herrmann, 2006, 21–42.
Hatzistavrou, A. 2006. “Happiness and the Nature of the Philosopher-Kings.” In Herrmann, 2006, 95–124.
Hatzistavrou, A. Forthcoming. “‘Correctness’ and Poetic Knowledge: Choric Poetry in the Laws.” In Plato and the Poets, ed. Destrée, P. and Herrmann, F. G.. Leiden.
Herrmann, F.-G. 2006. New Essays on Plato. Swansea.
Hitz, Z. 2005. Review of K. Raaflaub's The Discovery of Freedom in Ancient Greece. Journal of Philosophy 102: 594–601.
Hornblower, S. 2004. Thucydides and Pindar. Oxford.
Höschele, R. 2007. “Garlands in the Garland: Meleager's Poetics of Entanglement.” University of Toronto, 2007. University of Virginia, 2007.
Höschele, R. 2010. Die blütenlesende Muse: Poetik und Textualität antiker Epigrammsammlungen. Tübingen.
Howland, J. 1993. The Republic: the Odyssey of Philosophy. New York; rpt., Philadelphia. 2004.
Huffman, C. A. 2005. Archytas of Tarentum: Pythagorean, Philosopher and Mathematician King. Cambridge.
Irwin, T. H. 1977. Plato's Moral Theory. Oxford.
Irwin, T. H. 1995. Plato's Ethics. Oxford.
Johansen, T. 2004. Plato's Natural Philosophy: A Study of the Timaeus-Critias. Cambridge.
Johnson, R. R. 1999. “Does Plato's Myth of Er Contribute to the Argument of the Republic?Philosophy and Rhetoric 32(1): 1–13.
Kahn, C. 1972. “The Meaning of Justice and the Theory of Forms.” Journal of Philosophy 69: 567–579.
Kahn, C. 1987. “Plato's Theory of Desire.” Review of Metaphysics 41: 77–103.
Kahn, C. 1996. Plato and the Socratic Dialogue: The Philosophical Use of a Literary Form. Cambridge.
Kahn, C. 2003. The Verb “Be” in Ancient Greek. Indianapolis and Cambridge.
Kamtekar, R. 2001. “Social Justice and Happiness in the Republic: Plato's Two Principles.” History of Political Thought 22: 189–220.
Kamtekar, R. 2006. “Speaking with the Same Voice as Reason: Personification in Plato's Psychology.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 31: 167–202.
Karasmanis, V. 2002. “Dialectic and the Good in Plato's Republic.”Cahiers de Philosophie Ancienne. Ousia.
Kayser, J. R. 1970. “Prologue to the Study of Justice: Republic 327a–328b.” The Western Political Quarterly 23: 256–265.
Keyt, D. 2006. “Plato and the Ship of State.” In Santas, 2006, 189–213.
King, D. 2005. Finding Atlantis: A True Story of Genius, Madness and an Extraordinary Quest for a Lost World. New York.
Kirkwood, G. 1982. Selections from Pindar. Chico.
Klagge, J. C., and Smith, N. D., eds. 1992. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, suppl. vol.: Methods of Interpreting Plato and His Dialogues. Oxford.
Klosko, G. 1981. “Implementing the Ideal State.” Journal of Politics 43: 365–89.
Kock, T. 1880. Comicorum Atticorum Fragmenta, vol. 1. Leipzig.
Kraut, R. 1973. “Egoism, Love, and Political Office in Plato.” Philosophical Review 82: 330–44.
Kraut, R. 1991. “Return to the Cave: Republic 519–521.” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 7: 43–62.
Kraut, R. 1992. “The Defense of Justice in the Republic.” In The Cambridge Companion to Plato, ed. Kraut, R.. Cambridge, 311–37.
Laks, A. 2000. “The Laws.” In The Cambridge History of Greek and Roman Political Thought, ed. Rowe, C. and Schofield, M.. Cambridge.
Lear, E. 1862. A Book of Nonsense. London.
Lear, G. R. 2006. “Plato on Learning to Love Beauty.” In The Blackwell Guide to Plato's Republic, ed. Santas, G.. Oxford, 104–24.
Lear, J. 1992. “Inside and Outside the Republic.” Phronesis 37: 184–215.
Lear, J. 2006. “Allegory and Myth in Plato's Republic.” In Santas, 2006, 25–43.
Lee, H. D. P. 2001. The Republic. London.
Leroux, G. 2002. Platon, La République. Paris.
Lesher, J. 1994. “The Emergence of Philosophical Interest in Cognition.”Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 12: 1–34.
Liddell, H. and Scott, R.. 1848. A Greek-English Lexicon. 9th ed. rev. Jones, H. and McKenzie, R., with 1968 suppl. Oxford.
Long, A. A. 1977. “Chance and Natural Law in Epicureanism.” Phronesis 22: 63–88.
Lorenz, H. 2006. The Brute Within. Oxford.
Lyons, J. 1963. Structural Semantics: An Analysis of Part of the Vocabulary of Plato. Oxford.
Mahoney, T. A. 1992. “Do Plato's Philosopher-Rulers Sacrifice Self-Interest to Justice?Phronesis 37: 265–82.
Mara, G. M. 1983. “Politics and Action in Plato's Republic.” The Western Political Quarterly 36: 596–618.
McCabe, M. M. 2006. “Is Dialectic as Dialectic Does? The Virtue of Philosophical Conversation.” In The Virtuous Life in Greek Ethics, ed. Reis, B.. Cambridge.
McPherran, M. 2003. “Socrates, Crito, and Their Debt to Asclepius.” Ancient Philosophy 23: 71–92.
Menn, S. 2002. “Plato and the Method of Analysis.” Phronesis 47: 193–223.
Menn, S. 2006. “On Plato's Politeia.” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 21: 1–55.
Merriman, F. V. 1915. “The Rise and Fall of the Platonic Kallipolis.”Mind 24: 1–15.
Miller, M. 1985. “Platonic Provocations: Reflections on the Soul and the Good in the Republic.” In O'Meara, 1985, 163–93.
Moors, K. 1988. “Named Life Selections in Plato's Myth of Er.”Classica et Medievalia 39: 55–61.
Moraux, P. 1968. “La joute dialectique d'après le huitième livre des Topiques.” In Aristotle on Dialectic:the Topics, ed. Owen, G. E. L.. Oxford.
Moravcsik, J. M. E. 1973. “Plato's Method of Division.” In Patterns in Plato's Thought, ed. Moravcsik, J. M. E.. Boston.
Morgan, K. 1998. “Designer History: Plato's Atlantis Story and Fourth Century Ideology.” Journal of Hellenic Studies 118: 101–18.
Morgan, K. 2000. Myth and Philosophy from the Presocratics to Plato. Cambridge.
Morgan, K. 2004. “Plato.” In Jong, et al. 2004.
Morgan, M. L. 1990. Platonic Piety. New Haven.
Morgan, M. L. 1992. “Plato and Greek Religion.” In The Cambridge Companion to Plato, ed. Kraut, R.. Cambridge.
Morrison, Donald. 2001. “The Happiness of the City and the Happiness of the Individual in Plato's Republic.”Ancient Philosophy 21.1: 1–24.
Morrison, Donald. 2007. “The Utopian Character of Plato's Ideal City.” In Ferrari, 2007, 232–55.
Morrison, J. S. 1955. “Parmenides and Er.” The Journal of Hellenic Studies 75: 59–68.
Moss, J. 2007. “What is Imitative Poetry and Why is it Bad?” In Ferrari, 2007, 415–44.
Moss, J. 2008. “Appearances and Calculations: Plato's Division of the Soul.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 34: 35–68.
Mueller, I. 1992. “Mathematical Method and Philosophical Truth.” In The Cambridge Companion to Plato, ed. Kraut, R.. Cambridge, 170–99.
Murphy, N. R. 1951. The Interpretation of Plato'sRepublic. Oxford.
Murray, P. 2004. “The Muses and Their Arts.” In Music and the Muses, ed. Murray, P. and Wilson, P.. Oxford, 365–89.
Myres, J. L. 1932. “The Last Book of the Iliad.” Journal of Hellenic Studies 52: 264–96.
Nehamas, A. 1982/1999. “Plato on Imitation and Poetry in Republic X.” In Virtues of Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates. Princeton; originally published in Plato on Beauty, Wisdom and the Arts, ed. Moravcsik, J. and Temko, P.. Totowa, 47–78.
Nettleship, R. L. 1897. Philosophical Lectures and Remains of Richard Lewis Nettleship, ed., with a biographical sketch, by Bradley, A. C. and Benson, G. R.. London and New York.
Nettleship, R. L. 1901. Lectures on the Republic of Plato. 2nd edn. Oxford.
Netz, R. 2003. “How Propositions Begin.” Hyperboreus 9(2): 295–317.
Notomi, N. 1999. The Unity of Plato's Sophist. Cambridge.
Notopoulos, J. A. 1951. “Continuity and Interconnection in Homeric Oral Composition.” Transactions of the American Philological Association 82: 81–101.
Ober, J. 1989. Mass and Elite in Democratic Athens. Princeton.
Ober, J. 1996. Political Dissent in Democratic Athens. Princeton.
O'Connor, D. K. 2007. “Rewriting the Poets in Plato's Characters.” In Ferrari, 2007, 55–89.
Ostenfeld, E. 1996. “Socratic Argumentation Strategies and Aristotle's Topics and Sophistical Refutations.” Methexis 9: 43–57.
Ott, W. 2006. “Aristotle and Plato on Character.” Ancient Philosophy 26: 65–79.
Otterlo, W. A. A.. 1944. Untersuchungen über Begriff, Anwendung und Entstehung der griechischen Ringkomposition. Amsterdam.
Otterlo, W. A. A.. 1948. De Ringcompositie als Opbouwprincipe in de Epische Gedichten van Homerus. Amsterdam.
Pangle, T., ed. 1987. The Roots of Political Philosophy: Ten Forgotten Socratic Dialogues. Ithaca.
Pappas, N. 1995. Plato and the Republic. New York.
Parry, R. 1996. Plato's Craft of Justice. Albany.
Patterson, R. 2007. “Diagrams, Dialectic, and Mathematical Foundations in Plato.” Apeiron 40: 1–33.
Popper, K. 1962. The Open Society and its Enemies, vol. 1: The Spell of Plato. Princeton.
Prauscello, L. 2010. “Patterns of Chorality in Plato's Laws.” In Music and Politics in Ancient Greek Societies, ed. Yatromanolakis, D.. New York and London.
Price, A. W. 2009. “Are Plato's Soul-Parts Psychological Subjects?Ancient Philosophy 29: 1–15.
Race, W. H. 1997. Pindar. 2 vols. Cambridge.
Randall, J. H. 1970. Plato: Dramatist of the Life of Reason. New York.
Reeve, C. D. C. 1988. Philosopher-Kings: The Argument of Plato's Republic. Princeton.
Reeve, C. D. C. 2003. “Plato's Metaphysics of Morals.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 25: 39–58.
Reeve, C. D. C. 2004. Plato: Republic. Indianapolis.
Richardson, H. 1926. “The Myth of Er (Plato Republic 616b).” Classical Quarterly 20: 113–33.
Robinson, R. 1953. Plato's Earlier Dialectic. 2nd edn. Oxford.
Roochnik, D. 2003. Beautiful City: The Dialectical Character of Plato's Republic. Ithaca.
Rosen, S. 2005. Plato's Republic: A Study. New Haven.
Rowe, C. 1999. “Myth, History and Dialectic in Plato.” In From Myth to Reason? Studies in the Development of Greek Thought, ed. Buxton, R.. Oxford, 263–78.
Rushdie, S. 1996. The Moor's Last Sigh. New York.
Ryle, G. 1966. Plato's Progress. Cambridge.
Sachs, D. 1963. “A Fallacy in Plato's Republic.” Philosophical Review 72: 141–58. Rpt in Smith 1998, vol. 2, 206–19.
Sallis, J. 1975. Being and Logos: The Way of Platonic Dialogue. Pittsburgh.
Santas, G. 1980. “The Form of the Good in Plato's Republic.” Philosophical Inquiry 2: 374–403.
Santas, G. 2001. “Plato's Criticism of the ‘Democratic Man’ in the Republic.” Journal of Ethics 5: 57–71.
Santas, G., ed. 2006. The Blackwell Guide to Plato's Republic. Oxford.
Saxonhouse, A. 1978. “Comedy in Callipolis: Animal Imagery in the Republic.” American Political Science Review 72: 881–901.
Scanlon, T. F. 2002. “‘The Clear Truth’ in Thucydides 1. 22. 4.” Historia 51: 131–48.
Schein, S. 1997. “The Iliad: Structure and Interpretation.” In A New Companion to Homer, ed. Morris, I. and Powell, B.. Leiden.
Schils, G. 1993. “Plato's Myth of Er: The Light and the Spindle.” Antiquité Classique 62: 101–14.
Schofield, M. 1972. “A Displacement in the Text of the Cratylus.” Classical Quarterly 22: 246–53.
Schofield, M. 2006. Plato: Political Philosophy. Oxford.
Schofield, M. 2007. “The Noble Lie.” In Ferrari, 2007, 138–64.
Scott, D. 2000. “Plato's Critique of the Democratic Character.” Phronesis 45: 19–37.
Scott, D. 2006. Plato's Meno. Cambridge.
Sedley, D. 2007. “Philosophy, the Forms, and the Art of Ruling.” In Ferrari 2007, 256–83.
Shields, Christopher. 2001. “Simple Souls.” In Essays on Plato's Psychology, ed. Wagner, E.. Maryland, 137–56.
Shields, Christopher. 2006. “Unified Agency and Akrasia in Plato's Republic.” In “Akrasia” in Ancient Philosophy, ed. Bobonich, C. and Destrée, P.. Leiden, 61–86.
Shorey, P., ed. and trans. 1930. Plato: Republic, vols. 1 and 2. Cambridge.
Shorey, P. 1963. “The Republic.” In The Collected Dialogues of Plato, ed. Hamilton, E. and Cairns, H.. Princeton.
Singpurwalla, R. 2006. “Plato's Defense of Justice.” In Santas, 2006, 263–82.
Singpurwalla, R. Forthcoming-1. “The Tripartite Theory of Motivation in Plato's Republic.” Blackwell Philosophy Compass.
Singpurwalla, R. Forthcoming-2. “Soul Division and Mimesis in Republic X.” In Plato and the Poets, ed. Destrée, Pierre and Herrmann, Fritz-Gregor (Brill Academic Publishers).
Smith, N. D. 1996. “Plato's Divided Line.” Ancient Philosophy 16: 25–46.
Smith, N. D., ed. 1998. Plato: Critical Assessments, vol. 3. London.
Smith, R., trans., comm. 1997. Aristotle: Topics Books I and VIII. Oxford.
Solomon, J. 2001. The Ancient World in the Cinema. New Haven.
Sparshott, F. 1982. “Aristotle's Ethics and Plato's Republic: A Structural Comparison.” Dialogue 21: 483–99.
Stalley, R. F. 1975. “Plato's Argument for the Division of the Reasoning and Appetitive Elements within the Soul.” Phronesis 20: 110–28.
Stanford, W. B. 1983. Greek Tragedy and the Emotions. London.
Stauffer, D. 2001. Plato's Introduction to the Question of Justice. Albany.
Stemmer, P. 1992. Platons Dialektik. Berlin.
Stewart, J. A. 1905. The Myths of Plato. New York.
Stocks, J. L. 1932. “The Divided Line of Plato Republic VI.” In The Limits of Purpose and Other Essays, ed. Stocks, J. L.. London.
Strauss, L. 1964. The City and Man. Chicago.
Szlezák, T. 1985. Platon und die Schriftlichkeit der Philosophie. Berlin.
Taft, R. 1982. “The Role of Compulsion in the Education of Plato's Philosopher-King.” Auslegung 9: 311–32.
Taylor, A. E. 1939. “The Decline and Fall of the State in the Republic VIII.” Mind 48: 23–38.
Taylor, C. C. W. 1999. “The Atomists.” In The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy, ed. Long, A. A.. Cambridge, 181–204.
Thayer, H. S. 1988. “The Myth of Er.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 5(4): 369–84.
Thesleff, H. 1993. “Looking for Clues: An Interpretation of Some Literary Aspects of Plato's ‘Two-Level’ Model.” In Plato's Dialogues: New Studies and Interpretations, ed. Press, G.. Lanham, 17–46.
Thionville, E. 1983. De la Théorie des Lieux Communs dans les Topiques d'Aristote. Paris (1855).
Tonsfeldt, H. W. 1977. “Ring-structure in Beowulf.” Neophilologus 61: 443–52.
Tracy, S. V. 1997. “The Structures of the Odyssey.” In A New Companion to Homer, ed. Morris, I. and Powell, B.. Leiden, 360–79.
Vegetti, M. 1999. “L'autocritica di Platone: il Timeo e le Leggi.” In La Repubblica di Platone nella tradizione antica, ed. Abbate, M. and Vegetti, M.. Naples.
Vernezze, P. 1998. “The Philosophers' Interest.” In Smith, 1998, 153–73.
Vidal-Naquet, P. 1964. “Athènes et l'Atlantide.” Revue des Etudes Grecques 77: 420–44.
Vidal-Naquet, P. 2008. The Atlantis Story: A Short History of Plato's Myth. Exeter.
Vlastos, G. 1954. “The Third Man Argument in the Parmenides.” The Philosophical Review 63(3): 319–49.
Vlastos, G. 1971. “Justice and Happiness in the Republic.” In Plato II: Ethics, Politics, and Philosophy of Art and Religion; A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. Vlastos, G.. Notre Dame, 66–95.
Vlastos, G. 1977. “The Theory of Social Justice in the Polis in Plato's Republic.” In Interpretations of Plato, ed. North, H.. Leiden.
Vlastos, G. 1981a. “Isonomia politikê.” In Platonic Studies, 2nd edn., ed. Vlastos, G.. Princeton, 164–203.
Vlastos, G. 1981b. “Justice and Happiness in the Republic.” In Platonic Studies 2nd edn., ed. Vlastos, G.. Princeton, 111–39.
Vlastos, G. 1991. Socrates: Ironist and Moral Philosopher. Ithaca.
Wagner, E. 2005. “Compulsion Again in the Republic.” Apeiron 38: 131–45.
Wallace, R. W. 2004. “Damon of Oa: A Music Theorist Ostracized.” In Music and the Muses, ed. Murray, P. and Wilson, P.. Oxford.
Waterlow, Sarah. 1972–73. “The Good of Others in Plato's Republic.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 72: 19–36.
Weiss, R. 2001. Virtue in the Cave: Moral Inquiry in Plato'sMeno. Oxford.
Wekselbaum, C. 2006. “Keeping Up Appearances: A Pattern of Degeneration in Plato's Republic.” Washington University Undergraduate Research Digest 2(1): 23–46.
Wenskus, O. 1982. Ringkomposition, anaphorisch-rekapitulierende Verbindung und Anknüpfende Wiederholung im Hippokratischen Corpus. Frankfurt.
West, M. L. 1992. Ancient Greek Music. Oxford.
White, N. P. 1984. “The Classification of Goods in Plato's Republic.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 22: 393–421.
White, N. P. 1986. “The Ruler's Choice.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 68: 22–46.
White, N. P. 2002. Individual and Conflict in Ancient Greek Ethics. Oxford.
Whitman, C. 1963. Homer and the Heroic Tradition. Cambridge.
Wilberding, J. 2004. “Prisoners and Puppeteers in the Cave.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 27: 117–39.
Williams, B. 1973. “The Analogy of the City and Soul in Plato's Republic.” In Exegesis and Argument: Studies in Greek Philosophy Presented to Gregory Vlastos, Phronesis suppl. vol. 1, ed. Lee, E. N., Mourelatos, A. P. D., and Rorty, R. M.. Assen, 196–206.
Wolenski, J. 2004. “Alêtheia in Greek Thought until Aristotle.” Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 127: 339–60.
Wolin, S. S. 1960. Politics and Vision. Boston.
Worthington, I. 1991. “Greek Oratory, Revision of Speeches and Historical Reliability.” Classica et Medievalia 42: 55–74.
Worthington, I. 1993. “Two Letters of Isocrates and Ring Composition.” Electronic Antiquity. (http://scholar.lib.vt.edu/ejournals/elant/v1n1/worthington.html)

Metrics

Altmetric attention score

Full text views

Total number of HTML views: 0
Total number of PDF views: 0 *
Loading metrics...

Book summary page views

Total views: 0 *
Loading metrics...

* Views captured on Cambridge Core between #date#. This data will be updated every 24 hours.

Usage data cannot currently be displayed.