Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2brh9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T04:19:22.242Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 April 2020

Jamin Asay
Affiliation:
The University of Hong Kong
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
A Theory of Truthmaking
Metaphysics, Ontology, and Reality
, pp. 265 - 289
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2020

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Akiba, Takeshi. 2011. Why should the truthmaker principle be restricted? Kagaku Tetsugaku 44: 115134.Google Scholar
Alward, Peter. 2004. Review of Truth and Truthmakers, D. M. Armstrong. Disputatio 1: 7478.Google Scholar
Anderson, Alan Ross, and Belnap, Nuel D. Jr. 1975. Entailment: The Logic of Relevance and Necessity, Volume 1. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Angere, Staffan. 2015. The logical structure of truthmaking. Journal of Philosophical Logic 44: 351374.Google Scholar
Aristotle, . 1966. Metaphysics. Trans. Apostle, Hippocrates G.. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Aristotle, . 1995. Categories. In Selections, ed. and trans. Irwin, Terence and Fine, Gail, 112. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Armour-Garb, Bardley, and Woodbridge, James A.. 2010. Truthmakers, paradox, and plausibility. Analysis 70: 1123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 1969. Dispositions are causes. Analysis 30: 2326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 1973. Belief, Truth and Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 1978. Nominalism and Realism: Universals and Scientific Realism, Volume 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 1980. Against “ostrich” nominalism: a reply to Michael Devitt. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 61: 440449.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 1983. What Is a Law of Nature? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 1989a. C. B. Martin, counterfactuals, causality, and conditionals. In Cause, Mind, and Reality: Essays Honoring C. B. Martin, ed. Heil, John, 715. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 1989b. A Combinatorial Theory of Possibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 1989c. Universals: An Opinionated Introduction. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 1991. Classes are states of affairs. Mind (New Series) 100: 189200.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 1993. A world of states of affairs. Philosophical Perspectives 7: 429440.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 1997. A World of States of Affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 2000. Difficult cases in the theory of truthmaking. The Monist 83: 150160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 2003. Truthmakers for modal truths. In Real Metaphysics: Essays in Honour of D. H. Mellor, eds. Lillehammer, Hallvard and Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo, 1224. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 2004. Truth and Truthmakers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 2005. Reply to Simons and Mumford. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 83: 271276.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 2006. Reply to Heil. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84: 245247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 2007. Truthmakers for negative truths, and for truths of mere possibility. In Metaphysics and Truthmakers, ed. Monnoyer, Jean-Maurice, 99104. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 2010. Sketch for a Systematic Metaphysics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Asay, Jamin. 2009. Constructive empiricism and deflationary truth. Philosophy of Science 76: 423443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Asay, Jamin. 2010. How to express ontological commitment in the vernacular. Philosophia Mathematica 18: 293310.Google Scholar
Asay, Jamin. 2012. A truthmaking account of realism and anti-realism. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 93: 373394.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Asay, Jamin. 2013a. Primitive truth. Dialectica 67: 503519.Google Scholar
Asay, Jamin. 2013b. The Primitivist Theory of Truth. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Asay, Jamin. 2013c. Three paradigms of scientific realism: a truthmaking account. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 27: 121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Asay, Jamin. 2013d. Truthmaking for modal skeptics. Thought 2: 303312.Google Scholar
Asay, Jamin. 2013e. Truthmaking, metaethics, and creeping minimalism. Philosophical Studies 163: 213232.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Asay, Jamin. 2014. Against truth. Erkenntnis 79: 147164.Google Scholar
Asay, Jamin. 2015. Epistemicism and the liar. Synthese 192: 679699.Google Scholar
Asay, Jamin. 2016a. The facts about truthmaking: an argument for truthmaking necessitarianism. Ergo 3: 493500.Google Scholar
Asay, Jamin. 2016b. Logic and/of truthmaking. In Structural Analysis of Non-classical Logics: The Proceedings of the Second Taiwan Philosophical Logic Colloquium, eds. Yang, Syraya Chin-Mu, Deng, Duen-Min, and Lin, Hanti, 3755. Heidelberg: Springer.Google Scholar
Asay, Jamin. 2017. Run aground: Kit Fine’s critique of truthmaker theory. Philosophical Quarterly 67: 443463.Google Scholar
Asay, Jamin. 2018a. Putting pluralism in its place. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 96: 175191.Google Scholar
Asay, Jamin. 2018b. Realism and theories of truth. In The Routledge Handbook of Scientific Realism, ed. Saatsi, Juha, 383393. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Asay, Jamin. 2018c. We don’t need no explanation. Philosophical Studies 175: 903921.Google Scholar
Asay, Jamin. In press a. Truth: a concept unlike any other. Synthese.Google Scholar
Asay, Jamin. In press b. Truthmakers against correspondence. Grazer Philosophische Studien.Google Scholar
Asay, Jamin. In press c. Truth(making) by convention. American Philosophical Quarterly.Google Scholar
Asay, Jamin, and Baron, Sam. 2014. The hard road to presentism. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 95: 314335.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Asay, Jamin, and Baron, Sam. 2020. Deflating deflationary truthmaking. Philosophical Quarterly 70: 121.Google Scholar
Ayer, Alfred Jules. 1952. Language, Truth, and Logic. Reprint edition. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Azzouni, Jody. 1997. Thick epistemic access: distinguishing the mathematical from the empirical. Journal of Philosophy 94: 472484.Google Scholar
Azzouni, Jody. 2004. Deflating Existential Consequence: A Case for Nominalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Azzouni, Jody. 2006. Tracking Reason: Proof, Consequence, and Truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Azzouni, Jody. 2007. Ontological commitment in the vernacular. Noûs 41: 204226.Google Scholar
Azzouni, Jody. 2010. Talking about Nothing: Numbers, Hallucinations, and Fictions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Baia, Alex. 2012. Presentism and the grounding of truth. Philosophical Studies 159: 341356.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baker, Alan. 2009. Mathematical explanation in science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60: 611633.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balaguer, Mark. 1998. Platonism and Anti-Platonism in Mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bar-On, Dorit, Horisk, Claire, and Lycan, William G.. 2000. Deflationism, meaning and truth-conditions. Philosophical Studies 101: 128.Google Scholar
Barker, Stephen. 2012. Expressivism about making and truth-making. In Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality, eds. Correia, Fabrice and Schnieder, Benjamin, 272293. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Barker, Stephen. 2014. Semantic paradox and alethic undecidability. Analysis 74: 201209.Google Scholar
Barker, Stephen, and Jago, Mark. 2012. Being positive about negative facts. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85: 117138.Google Scholar
Barnes, Elizabeth. 2012. Emergence and fundamentality. Mind 121: 873901.Google Scholar
Barnes, Elizabeth. 2014. Going beyond the fundamental: feminism in contemporary metaphysics. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 114: 335351.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, Sam. 2013a. Presentism, truth and supervenience. Ratio (New Series) 26: 318.Google Scholar
Baron, Sam. 2013b. Talking about the past. Erkenntnis 78: 547560.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, Sam. 2013c. Tensed supervenience: a no-go for presentism. Southern Journal of Philosophy 51: 383401.Google Scholar
Baron, Sam. 2013d. A truthmaker indispensability argument. Synthese 190: 24132427.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, Sam. 2015a. A bump on the road to presentism. American Philosophical Quarterly 52: 345356.Google Scholar
Baron, Sam. 2015b. Tensed truthmaker theory. Erkenntnis 80: 923944.Google Scholar
Baron, Sam. 2016. Metaphysics as fairness. Synthese 193: 22372259.Google Scholar
Baron, Sam. 2017. Feel the flow. Synthese 194: 609630.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, Sam, and Miller, Kristie. 2013. Characterizing eternalism. In New Papers on the Present: Focus on Presentism, eds. Ciuni, Roberto, Miller, Kristie, and Torrengo, Giuliano, 3165. Munich: Philosophia.Google Scholar
Baron, Sam, Miller, Kristie, and Norton, James. 2014. Groundless truth. Inquiry 57: 175195.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, Sam, Chua, Reginald Mary, Miller, Kristie, and Norton, James. In press. Much ado about aboutness. Inquiry.Google Scholar
Barrio, Eduardo, and Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo. 2015. Truthmaker Maximalism defended again. Analysis 75: 38.Google Scholar
Baxter, Donald L. M. 2018. The problem of universals and the asymmetry of instantiation. American Philosophical Quarterly 55: 189202.Google Scholar
Beall, J. 2000. On truthmakers for negative truths. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 78: 264268.Google Scholar
Beebee, Helen, and Dodd, Julian. 2005. In Truthmakers: The Contemporary Debate, eds. Beebee, Helen and Dodd, Julian, 116. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bennett, Karen. 2004. Spatio-temporal coincidence and the grounding problem. Philosophical Studies 118: 339371.Google Scholar
Bennett, Karen. 2011. By our bootstraps. Philosophical Perspectives 25: 2741.Google Scholar
Bergmann, Michael, and Brower, Jeffrey. 2006. A theistic argument against Platonism (and in support of truthmakers and divine simplicity). In Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Volume 2, ed. Zimmerman, Dean W., 357386. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bernecker, Sven. 2011. Keeping track of the Gettier problem. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 92: 127152.Google Scholar
Bigelow, John. 1988. The Reality of Numbers: A Physicalist’s Philosophy of Mathematics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bigelow, John. 1996. Presentism and properties. Philosophical Perspectives 10: 3552.Google Scholar
Bigelow, John. 2009. Truthmakers and truthbearers. In The Routledge Companion to Metaphysics, eds. Le Poidevin, Robin, Simons, Peter, McGonigal, Andrew, and Cameron, Ross P., 389400. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Bird, Alexander. 2007. Nature’s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Biro, John. 2013. Showing the time. Analysis 73: 5762.Google Scholar
Biro, John. 2014. Clocks, evidence, and the “truth-maker solution.” Acta Analytica 29: 377381.Google Scholar
Björnsson, Gunnar. 2007. If you believe in positive facts, you should believe in negative facts. In Homage à Wlodek: Philosophical Papers Dedicated to Wlodek Rabinowicz, eds. Rønnow-Rasmussen, Toni, Petersson, Björn, Josefsson, Jonas, and Egonsson, Dan. Lund: Lund University, Department of Philosophy. Available at www.fil.lu.se/hommageawlodek/site/papper/BjornssonGunnar.pdfGoogle Scholar
Blackburn, Simon. 1981. Reply: rule-following and moral realism. In Wittgenstein: To Follow a Rule, eds. Holtzman, Steven H. and Leich, Christopher M., 163187. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Blackburn, Simon. 1984. Spreading the Word: Groundings in the Philosophy of Language. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Blackburn, Simon. 1986. Morals and modals. In Fact, Science and Morality: Essays on A. J. Ayer's Language, Truth and Logic, eds. Macdonald, Graham and Wright, Crispin, 119141. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Blackburn, Simon. 1988. How to be an ethical antirealist. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 12: 361375.Google Scholar
Blackburn, Simon. 1993. Introduction. In his Essays in Quasi-Realism, 311. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Blackburn, Simon. 1998. Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Blackburn, Simon. 2002. Realism: deconstructing the debate. Ratio (New Series) 15: 111133.Google Scholar
Boghossian, Paul Artin. 1996. Analyticity reconsidered. Noûs 30: 360391.Google Scholar
Boulter, Stephen. 2017. On the very possibility of historiography. Journal of the Philosophy of History 11: 196220.Google Scholar
Bourne, Craig. 2006a. A Future for Presentism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bourne, Craig. 2006b. A theory of presentism. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36: 123.Google Scholar
Brendel, Elke. In press. Truthmaker maximalism and the truthmaker paradox. Synthese.Google Scholar
Bricker, Phillip. 2006. The relation between general and particular: entailment vs. supervenience. In Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Volume 2, ed. Zimmerman, Dean W., 251287. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bricker, Phillip. 2015. Truthmaking: with and without counterpart theory. In A Companion to David Lewis, eds. Loewer, Barry and Schaffer, Jonathan, 159187. Oxford: Wiley Blackwell.Google Scholar
Briggs, R. A. 2012. Truthmaking without necessitation. Synthese 189: 1128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brink, David O. 1989. Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Brock, Stuart. 2010. The creationist fiction: the case against creationism about fictional characters. Philosophical Review 119: 337364.Google Scholar
Brower-Toland, Susan. 2006. Facts vs. things: Adam Wodeham and the later medieval debate about objects of judgment. Review of Metaphysics 60: 597642.Google Scholar
Bueno, Otávio. 2009. Mathematical fictionalism. In New Waves in Philosophy of Mathematics, eds. Bueno, Otávio and Linnebo, Øystein, 5979. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Callender, Craig. 2000. Shedding light on time. Philosophy of Science 67: S587S599.Google Scholar
Cameron, J. R. 2005. Review of Truth and Truthmakers, by D. M. Armstrong. Philosophy 80: 285289.Google Scholar
Cameron, Ross Paul. 2005. Truthmaker necessitarianism and maximalism. Logique et Analyse 48: 4356.Google Scholar
Cameron, Ross Paul. 2006. Tropes, necessary connections, and non-transferability. Dialectica 60: 99113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cameron, Ross Paul. 2008a. How to be a truthmaker maximalist. Noûs 42: 410421.Google Scholar
Cameron, Ross Paul. 2008b. Truthmakers and modality. Synthese 164: 261280.Google Scholar
Cameron, Ross Paul. 2008c. Truthmakers and ontological commitment: or how to deal with complex objects and mathematical ontology without getting into trouble. Philosophical Studies 140: 118.Google Scholar
Cameron, Ross Paul. 2008d. Truthmakers, realism and ontology. Philosophy 83: 107128.Google Scholar
Cameron, Ross Paul. 2010a. From Humean truthmaker theory to priority monism. Noûs 44: 178198.Google Scholar
Cameron, Ross Paul. 2010b. How to have a radically minimal ontology. Philosophical Studies 151: 249264.Google Scholar
Cameron, Ross Paul. 2010c. Necessity and triviality. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88: 401415.Google Scholar
Cameron, Ross Paul. 2011. Truthmaking for presentists. In Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Volume 6, eds. Bennett, Karen and Zimmerman, Dean W., 55100. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cameron, Ross Paul. 2012. How to be a nominalist and a fictional realist. In Art and Abstract Objects, ed. Uidhir, Christy Mag, 179196. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cameron, Ross Paul. 2013. Changing truthmakers: reply to Tallant and Ingram. In Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Volume 8, eds. Bennett, Karen and Zimmerman, Dean W., 362373. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cameron, Ross Paul. 2015. The Moving Spotlight: An Essay on Time and Ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cameron, Ross Paul. 2018. Truthmakers. In Oxford Handbook of Truth, ed. Glanzberg, Michael, 333354. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Caplan, Ben, and Sanson, David. 2011. Presentism and truthmaking. Philosophy Compass 6: 196208.Google Scholar
Caputo, Stefano. 2007. Truth-making: what it is not and what it could be. In Metaphysics and Truthmakers, ed. Monnoyer, Jean-Maurice, 275311. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
Caputo, Stefano. 2013. The dependence of truth on being: is there a problem for minimalism? In Varieties of Dependence: Ontological Dependence, Grounding, Supervenience, Response-Dependence, eds. Hoeltje, Miguel, Schnieder, Benjamin, and Steinberg, Alex, 297323. Munich: Philosophia.Google Scholar
Carmichael, Chad. 2010. Universals. Philosophical Studies 150: 373389.Google Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf. 1950. Empiricism, semantics, and ontology. Revue Internationale de Philosophie 4: 2040.Google Scholar
Cartwright, Richard. 1987. A neglected theory of truth. In his Philosophical Essays, 7193. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Casati, Filippo, and Fujikawa, Naoya. 2016. Nonexistent objects as truth-makers: against Crane’s reductionism. Philosophia 44: 423434.Google Scholar
Chang, Hasok. 2004. Inventing Temperature: Measurement and Scientific Progress. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cheyne, Colin, and Pigden, Charles. 2006. Negative truths from positive facts. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84: 249265.Google Scholar
Chrisman, Matthew. 2009. Expressivism, truth, and (self-) knowledge. Philosophers’ Imprint 9: 126.Google Scholar
Chrudzimski, Arkadiusz. 2002. Objects, properties and states of affairs: An Aristotelian ontology of truth making. Axiomathes 13: 187215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, Paul M. 1981. Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy 78: 67-90.Google Scholar
Clementz, François. 2007. Relational truthmakers. In Metaphysics and Truthmakers, ed. Monnoyer, Jean-Maurice, 163198. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
Colyvan, Mark. 1998. Is Platonism a bad bet? Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76: 115119.Google Scholar
Colyvan, Mark. 2000. Conceptual contingency and abstract existence. Philosophical Quarterly 50: 8791.Google Scholar
Colyvan, Mark. 2001. The Indispensability of Mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Colyvan, Mark. 2007. Mathematical recreation versus mathematical knowledge. In Mathematical Knowledge, eds. Leng, Mary, Paseau, Alexander, and Potter, Michael D., 109122. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Colyvan, Mark. 2010. There is no easy road to nominalism. Mind (New Series) 119: 285306.Google Scholar
Conee, Earl, and Sider, Theodore. 2005. Riddles of Existence: A Guided Tour of Metaphysics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Contessa, Gabriele. 2010. Modal truthmakers and two varieties of actualism. Synthese 174: 341353.Google Scholar
Cook, Roy T. 2011. The no-no paradox is a paradox. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89: 467482.Google Scholar
Corkum, Phil. 2014. Presentism, truthmakers and distributional properties. Synthese 191: 34273446.Google Scholar
Correia, Fabrice. 2011. From grounding to truth-making: some thoughts. In Philosophical Papers Dedicated to Kevin Mulligan, ed. Reboul, A., 1–13. Genève. www.unige.ch/lettres/philo/mulligan/festschrift/Correia-paper.pdfGoogle Scholar
Cox, Damian. 1997. The trouble with truth-makers. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 78: 4562.Google Scholar
Craig, William Lane. 2001. Middle knowledge, truth-makers, and the “grounding objection.” Faith and Philosophy 18: 337352.Google Scholar
Craig, William Lane. 2003. In defense of presentism. In Time, Tense, and Reference, eds. Jokić, Aleksandar and Smith, Quentin, 391408. Cambridge: Bradford Books.Google Scholar
Crisp, Thomas M. 2004a. On presentism and triviality. In Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Volume 1, ed. Zimmerman, Dean W., 1520. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Crisp, Thomas M. 2004b. Reply to Ludlow. In Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Volume 1, ed. Zimmerman, Dean W., 3746. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Crisp, Thomas M. 2007. Presentism and the grounding objection. Noûs 41: 90109.Google Scholar
Daly, Chris. 2000. Properties as truthmakers. Logique et Analyse 43: 95107.Google Scholar
Daly, Chris. 2005. So where’s the explanation? In Truthmakers: The Contemporary Debate, eds. Beebee, Helen and Dodd, Julian, 85103. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
David, Marian. 1994. Correspondence and Disquotation: An Essay on the Nature of Truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
David, Marian. 2005. Armstrong on truthmaking. In Truthmakers: The Contemporary Debate, eds. Beebee, Helen and Dodd, Julian, 141159. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
David, Marian. 2009. Truth-making and correspondence. In Truth and Truth-Making, eds. Lowe, E. J. and Rami, A., 137157. Stocksfield: Acumen.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 1969. True to the facts. Journal of Philosophy 66: 748764.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 1996. The folly of trying to define truth. Journal of Philosophy 93: 263278.Google Scholar
Davidson, Matthew. 2013. Presentism and grounding past truths. In New Papers on the Present: Focus on Presentism, eds. Ciuni, Roberto, Miller, Kristie, and Torrengo, Giuliano, 153172. Munich: Philosophia.Google Scholar
Deasy, Daniel. 2019. The triviality argument against presentism. Synthese 196: 33693388.Google Scholar
Demos, Raphael. 1917. A discussion of a certain type of negative proposition. Mind (New Series) 26: 188196.Google Scholar
deRosset, Louis. 2011. What is the grounding problem? Philosophical Studies 156: 173197.Google Scholar
deRosset, Louis. 2017. Grounding the unreal. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 95: 535563.Google Scholar
Deutsch, Max. 2015. The Myth of the Intuitive: Experimental Philosophy and Philosophical Method. Cambridge: Bradford Books.Google Scholar
Devitt, Michael. 1980. “Ostrich nominalism” or “mirage realism”? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 61: 433439.Google Scholar
Divers, John. 2002. Possible Worlds. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Dodd, Julian. 2000. An Identity Theory of Truth. London: Macmillan Press.Google Scholar
Dodd, Julian. 2002a. Is truth supervenient on being? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (New Series) 102: 6985.Google Scholar
Dodd, Julian. 2002b. “The world is the totality of things, not of facts”: a Strawsonain reply to Searle. Ratio (New Series) 15: 176193.Google Scholar
Dodd, Julian. 2007. Negative truths and truthmaker principles. Synthese 156: 383401.Google Scholar
Dodd, Julian. 2018. A minimalist explanation of truth’s asymmetry. American Philosophical Quarterly 55: 389404.Google Scholar
Donelson, Raff. 2018. Three problems with metaethical minimalism. Southwest Philosophy Review 34: 125131.Google Scholar
Dreier, James. 2004. Meta-ethics and the problem of creeping minimalism. Philosophical Perspectives 18: 2344.Google Scholar
Dretske, Fred I. 1977. Laws of nature. Philosophy of Science 44: 248268.Google Scholar
Dummett, Michael. 1958–1959. Truth. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (New Series) 59: 141162.Google Scholar
Dummett, Michael. 1978. Truth and Other Enigmas. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. 1996. Objectivity and truth: you’d better believe it. Philosophy and Public Affairs 25: 87139.Google Scholar
Edwards, Douglas. 2013. Truth as a substantive property. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91: 279294.Google Scholar
Edwards, Douglas. 2018. The Metaphysics of Truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Efird, David, and Stoneham, Tom. 2009. Is metaphysical nihilism interesting? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 90: 210231.Google Scholar
Einheuser, Iris. 2011. Toward a conceptualist solution of the grounding problem. Noûs 45: 300314.Google Scholar
Eklund, Matti. 2011. Recent work on vagueness. Analysis 71: 352363.Google Scholar
Embry, Brian. 2016. How not to be a truthmaker maximalist: Francisco Peinado on truthmakers for negative truths. In Oxford Studies in Medieval Philosophy, Volume 4, ed. Pasnau, Robert, 159183. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Englebretsen, George. 2010. Making sense of truth-makers. Topoi 29: 147151.Google Scholar
Everett, Anthony. 2013. The Nonexistent. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Field, Hartry. 1980. Science without Numbers. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Field, Hartry. 1989. Realism, Mathematics and Modality. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Fine, Arthur. 1984a. And not anti-realism either. Noûs 18: 5165.Google Scholar
Fine, Arthur. 1984b. The natural ontological attitude. In Scientific Realism, ed. Leplin, Jarrett, 83107. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Fine, Arthur. 1986. Unnatural attitudes: realist and instrumentalist attachments to science. Mind (New Series) 95: 149179.Google Scholar
Fine, Arthur. 2001. The scientific image twenty years later. Philosophical Studies 106: 107122.Google Scholar
Fine, Kit. 1982. Acts, events and things. In Language and Ontology: Proceedings of the Sixth International Wittgenstein Symposium, eds. Leinfellner, Werner, Kraemer, Eric, and Schank, Jeffrey, 97105. Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky.Google Scholar
Fine, Kit. 1985. Plantinga on the reduction of possibilist discourse. In Alvin Plantinga, eds. Tomberlin, James E. and van Inwagen, Peter, 145186. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Fine, Kit. 2001. The question of realism. Philosophers’ Imprint 1.1: 130.Google Scholar
Fine, Kit. 2012. Guide to ground. In Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality, eds. Correia, Fabrice and Schnieder, Benjamin, 3780. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fine, Kit. 2014. Truth-maker semantics for intuitionistic logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic 43: 549577.Google Scholar
Fiocco, M. Oreste. 2013. An absolute principle of truthmaking. Grazer Philosophische Studien 88: 131.Google Scholar
Firth, Roderick. 1952. Ethical absolutism and the ideal observer. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 12: 317345.Google Scholar
Fisher, A. R. J. 2015. Priority monism, partiality, and minimal truthmakers. Philosophical Studies 172: 477491.Google Scholar
Fisher, A. R. J. 2016. Truthmaking and fundamentality. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 97: 448473.Google Scholar
Forbes, Graeme A. 2016. The Growing Block’s past problems. Philosophical Studies 173: 699709.Google Scholar
Forrest, Peter, and Khlentzos, Drew. 2000. Introduction: truth maker and its variants. Logique et Analyse 43: 315.Google Scholar
Fox, John F. 1987. Truthmaker. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 65: 188207.Google Scholar
Frege, Gottlob. 1894. Review of Husserl’s Philosophie der Arithmetik. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und Philosophische Kritik 103: 313332.Google Scholar
Freitag, Wolfgang. 2008. Truthmakers (are indexed combinations). Studia Philosophica Estonia 1: 228248.Google Scholar
Friend, Stacie. 2007. Fictional characters. Philosophy Compass 2: 141156.Google Scholar
Fumerton, Richard. 2006. Review of Truthmakers: The Contemporary Debate, eds. Helen Beebee and Julian Dodd. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/24976-truthmakers-the-contemporary-debate/Google Scholar
Fumerton, Richard. 2010. Partnership in truth-making. Topoi 29: 9198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gettier, Edmund L. 1963. Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis 23: 121123.Google Scholar
Gibb, Sophie C. 2006. Space, supervenience and entailment. Philosophical Papers 35: 171184.Google Scholar
Gibbard, Allan. 1975. Contingent identity. Journal of Philosophical Logic 4: 187221.Google Scholar
Gill, Emily. 2012. Defending Quine on ontological commitment. In Rationis Defensor: Essays in Honour of Colin Cheyne, ed. Maclaurin, James, 177190. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Giordani, Alessandro. 2013. A logic of justification and truthmaking. Review of Symbolic Logic 2: 323342.Google Scholar
Giordani, Alessandro. 2015. The truthmaker solution to the Gettier problems. Epistemologia 38: 6880.Google Scholar
Goff, Philip. 2006. Propertied objects as truth-makers. In Topics on General and Formal Ontology, ed. Valore, Paolo, 181189. Milan: Polimetrica.Google Scholar
Goff, Philip. 2010. Orthodox truthmaker theory cannot be defended by cost/benefit analysis. Analysis 70: 4550.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin I. 1967. A causal theory of knowing. Journal of Philosophy 64: 357372.Google Scholar
Gołosz, Jerzy. 2015. In defence of an argument against truthmaker maximalism. Logic and Logical Philosophy 24: 105109.Google Scholar
Goodman, Nelson. 1983. Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. Fourth edition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Green, Karen. 2009. Necessitating nominalism. Acta Analytica 24: 193196.Google Scholar
Greenough, Patrick. 2008. Indeterminate truth. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 32: 213241.Google Scholar
Greenough, Patrick. 2011. Truthmaker gaps and the no-no paradox. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 82: 547563.Google Scholar
Gregory, Dominic. 2001. Smith on truthmakers. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 79: 422427.Google Scholar
Griffith, Aaron M. 2013. On some alleged truthmakers for negatives. Thought 1: 301308.Google Scholar
Griffith, Aaron M. 2014. Truthmaking and grounding. Inquiry 57: 196215.Google Scholar
Griffith, Aaron M. 2015a. How negative truths are made true. Synthese 192: 317335.Google Scholar
Griffith, Aaron M. 2015b. Towards a pluralist theory of truthmaking. Erkenntnis 80: 11571173.Google Scholar
Grover, Dorothy. 1992. A Prosentential Theory of Truth. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gupta, Anil. 1993. A critique of deflationism. Philosophical Topics 21: 5781.Google Scholar
Hale, Bob, and Wright, Crispin. 2001. The Reason’s Proper Study: Essays towards a Neo-Fregean Philosophy of Mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Harman, Gilbert. 1967. Quine on meaning and existence, I: the death of meaning. Review of Metaphysics 21: 124151.Google Scholar
Harman, Gilbert. 1975. Moral relativism defended. Philosophical Review 84: 322.Google Scholar
Heathcote, Adrian. 2003. Truthmaking and the alleged need for relevance. Logique et Analyse 46: 345364.Google Scholar
Heathcote, Adrian. 2006. Truthmaking and the Gettier problem. In Aspects of Knowing: Epistemological Essays, ed. Hetherington, Stephen, 151167. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
Heathcote, Adrian. 2012. Gettier and the stopped clock. Analysis 72: 309314.Google Scholar
Heathcote, Adrian. 2014a. The truthmaker account is not a causal theory. Acta Analytica 29: 383388.Google Scholar
Heathcote, Adrian. 2014b. Truthmaking, evidence of, and impossibility proofs. Acta Analytica 29: 363375.Google Scholar
Heathcote, Adrian. 2015. Testimony and Gettier: a reply to Vance. Ratio 29: 228233.Google Scholar
Heathcote, Adrian. 2018. Analyticity, truthmaking and mathematics. Open Journal of Philosophy 8: 243261.Google Scholar
Heathwood, Chris. 2007. On what will be: reply to Westphal. Erkenntnis 67: 137142.Google Scholar
Heil, John. 2000. Truth making and entailment. Logique et Analyse 43: 231242.Google Scholar
Heil, John. 2003. From an Ontological Point of View. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Heil, John. 2012. The Universe as We Find It. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Heil, John. In press. Truthmaking and fundamentality. Synthese.Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl G., and Oppenheim, Paul. 1948. Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science 15: 135175.Google Scholar
Hermes, Charles. 2014. Truthmakers and the direct argument. Philosophical Studies 167: 401418.Google Scholar
Hetherington, Stephen. 2005. Knowing (how it is) that p: degrees and qualities of knowledge. Veritas 50: 129152.Google Scholar
Hill, Christopher. 2002. Thought and World: An Austere Portrayal of Truth, Reference, and Semantic Correspondence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hinchliff, Mark. 1996. The puzzle of change. Philosophical Perspectives 10: 119136.Google Scholar
Hinchliff, Mark. 2000. A defense of presentism in a relativistic setting. Philosophy of Science 67: S575S586.Google Scholar
Hochberg, Herbert. 1992. Truth makers, truth predicates, and truth types. In Language, Truth and Ontology, ed. Mulligan, Kevin, 87117. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
Hochberg, Herbert. 1994. Facts and classes as complexes and as truth makers. The Monist 77: 170-191.Google Scholar
Hochberg, Herbert. 2007. “Is true” and “makes-true”: two predicates without properties. In Metaphysics and Truthmakers, ed. Monnoyer, Jean-Maurice, 199220. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
Hofmann, Frank. 2006. Truthmaking, recombination, and facts ontology. Philosophical Studies 128: 409440.Google Scholar
Hofmann, Frank, and Horvath, Joachim. 2008. In defence of metaphysical analyticity. Ratio (New Series) 21: 300313.Google Scholar
Hofweber, Thomas. 2000. Quantification and non-existent objects. In Empty Names, Fiction, and the Puzzles of Non-existence, eds. Everett, Anthony and Hofweber, Thomas, 249273. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Hofweber, Thomas. 2005. A puzzle about ontology. Noûs 39: 256283.Google Scholar
Hofweber, Thomas. 2009. Formal tools and the philosophy of mathematics. In New Waves in Philosophy of Mathematics, eds. Bueno, Otávio and Linnebo, Øystein, 197219. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Hornsby, Jennifer. 2005. Truth without truthmaking entities. In Truthmakers: The Contemporary Debate, eds. Beebee, Helen and Dodd, Julian, 3347. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Horwich, Paul. 1990. Truth. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Horwich, Paul. 1998. Truth. Second edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Horwich, Paul. 2006. A world without isms: life after realism, fictionalism, non-cognitivism, relativism, reductionism, revisionism, and so on. In Truth and Realism, eds. Greenough, Patrick and Lynch, Michael P., 188202. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Horwich, Paul. 2008. Being and truth. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 32: 258273.Google Scholar
Hume, David. 1993. Principal Writings on Religion including Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion and the Natural History of Religion. Ed. Gaskin, J. C. A.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hume, David. 1998. An Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals. Ed. Beauchamp, Tom L.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Husserl, Edmund. 2003. Philosophy of Arithmetic: Psychological and Logical Investigations with Supplementary Texts from 1887–1901. Trans. Willard, Dallas. Dordrecht: Springer Science+Business Media.Google Scholar
Ingram, David. 2018. Thisnesses, propositions, and truth. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 99: 442463.Google Scholar
Ingthorsson, Rögnvaldur. 2006. Truthmakers without truth. Metaphysica 72: 5371.Google Scholar
Ingthorsson, Rögnvaldur. 2017. Challenging the grounding objection to presentism. Manuscrito 40: 87107.Google Scholar
Jacquette, Dale. 1996. Is nondefectively justified true belief knowledge? Ratio (New Series) 9: 115127.Google Scholar
Jacquette, Dale. 2010. Truth breakers. Topoi 29: 153163.Google Scholar
Jacquette, Dale. 2015. Slingshot arguments and the intensionality of identity. European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 11: 522.Google Scholar
Jago, Mark. 2009. The conjunction and disjunction theses. Mind (New Series) 118: 411415.Google Scholar
Jago, Mark. 2011. Setting the facts straight. Journal of Philosophical Logic 40: 3354.Google Scholar
Jago, Mark. 2012a. The problem with truthmaker-gap epistemicism. Thought 1: 320329.Google Scholar
Jago, Mark. 2012b. The truthmaker non-maximalist’s dilemma. Mind (New Series) 121: 903918.Google Scholar
Jago, Mark. 2013. The cost of truthmaker maximalism. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 43: 460474.Google Scholar
Jago, Mark. 2017. Propositions as truthmaker conditions. Argumenta 2: 293308.Google Scholar
Jago, Mark. 2018. What Truth Is. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Johannson, Ingvar. 2004. Truthmaking: a cognition-independent internal relation with heterogeneous relata. In Experience and Analysis: Papers of the 27th International Wittgenstein Symposium, eds. Marek, Johan Christian and Reicher, Maria Elisabeth, 154156. Kirchberg am Wechsel: Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society.Google Scholar
Kalhat, Javier. 2008. A critique of Armstrong’s truthmaking account of possibility. Acta Analytica 23: 161176.Google Scholar
Kaplan, David. 1989. Afterthoughts. In Themes from Kaplan, eds. Almog, Joseph, Perry, John, and Wettstein, Howard, 565614. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Keller, Phillipp. 2007. A world of truthmakers. In Metaphysics and Truthmakers, ed. Monnoyer, J., 105156. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
Keller, Simon. 2004. Presentism and truthmaking. In Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Volume 1, ed. Zimmerman, Dean W., 83104. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Khlentzos, Drew. 2000. “What in the world would correspond to truth?Logique et Analyse 43: 109144.Google Scholar
Kierland, Brian. 2013. Grounding past truths: overcoming the challenge. In New Papers on the Present: Focus on Presentism, eds. Ciuni, Roberto, Miller, Kristie, and Torrengo, Giuliano, 173209. Munich: Philosophia.Google Scholar
Kierland, Brian, and Monton, Bradley. 2007. Presentism and the objection from being-supervenience. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 85: 485497.Google Scholar
Kirkham, Richard L. 1992. Theories of Truth: A Critical Introduction. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Kitamura, Naoaki. 2014. Is any alleged truthmaker for negatives explanatorily deficient? Thought 3: 200207.Google Scholar
Kitamura, Naoaki. 2016. The groundedness of negative truths. Annals of the Japan Association for Philosohpy of Science 24: 119.Google Scholar
Krämer, Stephan. 2010. How not to defend ontological cheats. Analysis 70: 290296.Google Scholar
Kriegel, Uriah. 2015. Thought and thing: Brentano’s reism as truthmaker nominalism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 91: 153180.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul A. 1976. Is there a problem about substitutional quantification? In Truth and Meaning: Essays in Semantics, eds. Evans, Gareth and McDowell, John, 325419. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul A. 1982. Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language: An Elementary Exposition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul A. 2013. Reference and Existence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kroon, Frederick W. 2000. Truthmaking and fiction. Logique et Analyse 43: 195210.Google Scholar
Kukso, Boris. 2006. The reality of absences. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84: 2137.Google Scholar
Kühl, Carl Erik. 2014. The existence and reality of negative facts. SATS: Northern European Journal of Philosophy 15: 121147.Google Scholar
Künne, Wolfgang. 2003. Conceptions of Truth. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Lange, Marc. 2009. Laws and Lawmakers: Science, Metaphysics, and the Laws of Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Latour, Bruno. 1998. Ramsès II est-il mort de la tuberculose? La Recherche 307: 8485.Google Scholar
Laudan, Larry. 1981. A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science 48: 1949.Google Scholar
Le Poidevin, Robin. 1991. Change, Cause and Contradiction: A Defense of the Tenseless Theory of Time. London: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Lee, Harold N. 1953. Father Parmenides: or, further concerning negative facts. Journal of Philosophy 50: 7074.Google Scholar
Leng, Mary. 2010. Mathematics and Reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 1978. Truth in fiction. American Philosophical Quarterly 15: 3746.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 1983. New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61: 343377.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 1986. On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 1992. Critical notice [of D. M. Armstrong, A Combinatorial Theory of Possibility]. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 70: 211224.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 1998. The truthmakers. Times Literary Supplement 4950: 3033.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 2001a. Forget about the “correspondence theory of truth.” Analysis 61: 275280.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 2001b. Truthmaking and difference-making. Noûs 35: 602615.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 2003. Things qua truthmakers. In Real Metaphysics: Essays in Honour of D. H. Mellor, eds. Lillehammer, Hallvard and Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo, 2542. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lewis, David, and Rosen, Gideon. 2003. Postscript to “Things qua truthmakers”: negative existentials. In Real Metaphysics: Essays in Honour of D. H. Mellor, eds. Lillehammer, Hallvard and Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo, 3942. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Liggins, David. 2005. Truthmakers and explanation. In Truthmakers: The Contemporary Debate, eds. Beebee, Helen and Dodd, Julian, 105115. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Liggins, David. 2016. Deflationism, conceptual explanation, and the truth explanation. Philosophical Quarterly 66: 84101.Google Scholar
Linsky, Bernard. 1994. Truth makers for modal propositions. The Monist 77: 192206.Google Scholar
Livingston, Paisley, and Sauchelli, Andrea. 2011. Philosophical perspectives on fictional characters. New Literary History 42: 337360.Google Scholar
Lombard, Lawrence Brian. 1999. On the alleged incompatibility of presentism and temporal parts. Philosophia 27: 253260.Google Scholar
López de Sa, Dan. 2009. Disjunctions, conjunctions, and their truthmakers. Mind (New Series) 118: 417425.Google Scholar
López de Sa, Dan, and Zardini, Elia. 2006. Does this sentence have no truthmaker? Analysis 66: 154157.Google Scholar
López de Sa, Dan, and Zardini, Elia. 2007. Truthmakers, knowledge and paradox. Analysis 67: 242250.Google Scholar
Lovett, Adam. 2014. The scope of the truthmaker requirement. Romanian Journal of Analytic Philosophy 8: 2329.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. 2005. The Four-Category Ontology: A Metaphysical Foundation for Natural Science. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. 2007. Truthmaking as essential dependence. In Metaphysics and Truthmakers, ed. Monnoyer, Jean-Maurice, 237259. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. 2009. An essentialist approach to truth-making. In Truth and Truth-Making, eds. Lowe, E. J. and Rami, A., 201216. Stocksfield: Acumen.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. 2013. Some varieties of metaphysical dependence. In Varieties of Dependence: Ontological Dependence, Grounding, Supervenience, Response-Dependence, eds. Hoeltje, Miguel, Schnieder, Benjamin, and Steinberg, Alex, 193210. Munich: Philosophia.Google Scholar
Ludlow, Peter. 2004. Presentism, triviality, and the varieties of tensism. In Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Volume 1, ed. Zimmerman, Dean W., 2136. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Lynch, Michael P. 1998. Truth in Context: An Essay on Pluralism and Objectivity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Lynch, Michael P. 2009. Truth as One and Many. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
MacBride, Fraser. 2002a. The problem of universals and the limits of truth-making. Philosophical Papers 31: 2737.Google Scholar
MacBride, Fraser. 2002b. Truth-making and analysis: a reply to Rodriguez-Pereyra. Philosophical Papers 31: 4961.Google Scholar
MacBride, Fraser. 2005. Lewis’s animadversions on the truthmaker principle. In Truthmakers: The Contemporary Debate, eds. Beebee, Helen and Dodd, Julian, 117140. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
MacBride, Fraser. 2013. For keeping truth in truthmaking. Analysis 73: 686695.Google Scholar
MacBride, Fraser. 2014. How truth depends on being. Analysis 74: 370378.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Maddy, Penelope. 1990. Realism in Mathematics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Maddy, Penelope. 1992. Indispensability and practice. Journal of Philosophy 89: 275289.Google Scholar
Maddy, Penelope. 2001. Naturalism: friends and foes. Philosophical Perspectives 15: 3767.Google Scholar
Markosian, Ned. 2004. A defense of presentism. In Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Volume 1, ed. Zimmerman, Dean W., 4782. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Markosian, Ned. 2013. The truth about the past and the future. In Around the Tree: Semantic and Metaphysical Issues Concerning Branching and the Open Future, eds. Correia, Fabrice and Iacona, Andrea, 127142. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Martin, C. B. 1996. How it is: entities, absences and voids. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74: 5765.Google Scholar
Martin, C. B. 2000. On Lewis and then some. Logique et Analyse 43: 4348.Google Scholar
Martin, C. B. 2008. The Mind in Nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Maudlin, Tim. 2007. The Metaphysics within Physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Maurin, Anna-Sofia. 2010. A world of tropes? In Worldviews, Science, and Us: Studies of Analytic Metaphysics, eds. Vanderbeeken, Robrecht and D’Hooghe, Bart, 107130. Brussels: World Scientific Publishers.Google Scholar
McDaniel, Brannon. 2014. A defense of Lucretianism. American Philosophical Quarterly 51: 373385.Google Scholar
McDaniel, Kristopher. 2011. Trenton Merricks’ Truth and Ontology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 83: 203211.Google Scholar
McGrath, Matthew. 2003. What the deflationist may say about truthmaking. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65: 666688.Google Scholar
McKinnon, Neil and Bigelow, John. 2012. Presentism, and speaking of the dead. Philosophical Studies 160: 253263.Google Scholar
Meinertsen, Bo R. 2018. Metaphysics of States of Affairs: Truthmaking, Universals, and a Farewell to Bradley’s Regress. Singapore: Springer.Google Scholar
Melia, Joseph. 2000. Weaseling away the indispensability argument. Mind (New Series) 109: 455480.Google Scholar
Melia, Joseph. 2005. Truthmaking without truthmakers. In Truthmakers: The Contemporary Debate, eds. Beebee, Helen and Dodd, Julian, 6784. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Mellor, D. H. 1995. The Facts of Causation. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Mellor, D. H. 2003. Real metaphysics: replies. In Real Metaphysics: Essays in Honour of D. H. Mellor, eds. Lillehammer, Hallvard and Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo, 212238. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Mellor, D. H. 2009. Truthmakers for what? In From Truth to Reality: New Essays in Logic and Metaphysics, ed. Dyke, Heather, 272290. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Merricks, Trenton. 2007. Truth and Ontology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Meyer, Ulrich. 2005. The presentist’s dilemma. Philosophical Studies 122: 213225.Google Scholar
Meyer, Ulrich. 2013. The triviality of presentism. In New Papers on the Present: Focus on Presentism, eds. Ciuni, Roberto, Miller, Kristie, and Torrengo, Giuliano, 6787. Munich: Philosophia.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. 1930. A System of Logic: Ratiocinative and Inductive. London: Longmans, Green, and Company.Google Scholar
Miller, Kristie. 2018. The new growing block theory vs presentism. Inquiry 61: 223251.Google Scholar
Milne, Peter. 2005. Not every truth has a truthmaker. Analysis 65: 221224.Google Scholar
Milne, Peter. 2013. Not every truth has a truthmaker II. Analysis 73: 473481.Google Scholar
Miyoshi, Yuki. 2007. Truthmakers for negative truths. Sorites 19: 92107.Google Scholar
Molnar, George. 2000. Truthmakers for negative truths. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 78: 7286.Google Scholar
Moltmann, Friederike. 2007. Events, tropes, and truthmaking. Philosophical Studies 134: 363403.Google Scholar
Moore, George Edward. 1903. Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Morris, Kevin. 2018. Physicalism, truthmaking, and levels of reality: prospects and problems. Topoi 37: 473482.Google Scholar
Mulligan, Kevin. 2007. Two dogmas of truthmaking. In Metaphysics and Truthmakers, ed. Monnoyer, Jean-Maurice, 5165. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
Mulligan, Kevin, Simons, Peter, and Smith, Barry. 1984. Truth-makers. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 44: 287321.Google Scholar
Mumford, Stephen. 2005. The true and the false. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 83: 263269.Google Scholar
Mumford, Stephen. 2007a. Negative truth and falsehood. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 107 (Part 1): 4571.Google Scholar
Mumford, Stephen. 2007b. A new solution to the problem of negative truth. In Metaphysics and Truthmakers, ed. Monnoyer, Jean-Maurice, 313329. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
Musgrave, Alan. 1989. NOA’s ark – fine for realism. Philosophical Quarterly 39: 383398.Google Scholar
Nef, Frédéric. 2007. Senex erit puer: truthmakers for tensed sentences. In Metaphysics and Truthmakers, ed. Monnoyer, Jean-Maurice, 221235. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
Newman, Andrew. 2002. The Correspondence Theory of Truth: An Essay on the Metaphysics of Predication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Newstead, Anne, and Franklin, James. 2012. Indispensability without Platonism. In Properties, Powers, and Structures: Issues in the Metaphysics of Realism, eds. Bird, Alexander, Ellis, Brian, and Sankey, Howard, 8197. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Ney, Alyssa. 2014. Metaphysics: An Introduction. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert. 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Oaklander, L. Nathan, and Miracchi, Silvano. 1980. Russell, negative facts, and ontology. Philosophy of Science 47: 434455.Google Scholar
O’Conaill, Donnchadh, and Tahko, Tuomas E.. 2016. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 97: 228244.Google Scholar
O’Leary-Hawthorne, John, and Oppy, Graham. 1997. Minimalism and truth. Noûs 31: 170196.Google Scholar
Oliver, Alex. 1996. The metaphysics of properties. Mind (New Series) 105: 180.Google Scholar
Pagès, Joan. 2005. Truthmaking and supervenience. Theoria 53: 191197.Google Scholar
Pagès, Joan. 2009. Truthmakers for negatives. Theoria 24: 4961.Google Scholar
Paoletti, Michele Paolini. 2014. Falsemakers: something negative about facts. Grazer Philosophische Studien 90: 169182.Google Scholar
Paoletti, Michele Paolini. 2017. From falsemakers to negative properties. Theoria 83: 5377.Google Scholar
Parfit, Derek. 1971. Personal identity. Philosophical Review 80: 327.Google Scholar
Parsons, Josh. 1999. There is no “truthmaker” argument against nominalism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77: 325334.Google Scholar
Parsons, Josh. 2005. Truthmakers, the past, and the future. In Truthmakers: The Contemporary Debate, eds. Beebee, Helen and Dodd, Julian, 161174. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Parsons, Josh. 2006. Negative truths from positive facts? Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84: 591602.Google Scholar
Parsons, Josh. 2009. Are there irreducibly relational facts? In Truth and Truth-Making, eds. Lowe, E. J. and Rami, A., 217226. Stocksfield: Acumen.Google Scholar
Parsons, Terence. 1980. Nonexistent Objects. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Pedersen, Nikolaj J. L. L., and Wright, Cory D.. 2013. Introduction. In their Truth and Pluralism: Current Debates, 118. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pendlebury, Michael. 1986. Facts as truthmakers. The Monist 69: 177188.Google Scholar
Pendlebury, Michael. 2010. Facts and truth-making. Topoi 29: 137145.Google Scholar
Perrine, Timothy. 2015. Undermining truthmaker theory. Synthese 192: 185200.Google Scholar
Petersen, Thorben. 2016. The grounding problem for eternalism. Philosophical Studies 173: 18191852.Google Scholar
Picazo, Gustavo. 2014. Truth and processes: a critical approach to truthmaker theory. Philosophia 42: 713739.Google Scholar
Pickel, Bryan, and Mantegani, Nicholas. 2012. A Quinean critique of ostrich nominalism. Philosophers’ Imprint 12.6: 121.Google Scholar
Pihlström, Sami. 2005. Truthmaking and pragmatist conceptions of truth and reality. Minerva 9: 105133.Google Scholar
Plato, . 1997. Euthyphro. In Complete Works, trans. Grube, G. M. A., ed. Cooper, John M., associate ed. Hutchinson, D. S., 216. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. 1963. Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge. New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Priest, Graham. 2000. Truth and contradiction. Philosophical Quarterly 50: 305319.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 1967a. Mathematics without foundations. Journal of Philosophy 64: 522.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 1967b. Time and physical geometry. Journal of Philosophy 64: 240247.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 1971. Philosophy of Logic. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 1975. What is mathematical truth? In his Mathematics, Matter and Method: Philosophical Papers, Volume 1, 6078. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 1978. Meaning and the Moral Sciences. Boston: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 2004. Ethics without Ontology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1948. On what there is. Review of Metaphysics 2: 2138.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1951. Two dogmas of empiricism. Philosophical Review 60: 2043.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1953. Logic and the reification of universals. In his From a Logical Point of View: 9 Logico-Philosophical Essays, 102129. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1960. Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1961. Reference and modality. In his From a Logical Point of View: 9 Logico-Philosophical Essays, Second, revised edition, 139159. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1966a. Carnap and logical truth. In Ways of Paradox and Other Essays, 100125. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1966b. Three grades of modal involvement. In his The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays, 156174. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1970. Philosophy of Logic. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1981. Things and their place in theories. In his Theories and Things, 123. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1990. Pursuit of Truth. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Railton, Peter. 1986. Moral realism. Philosophical Review 95: 163207.Google Scholar
Rami, Adolf. 2009. Introduction: truth and truth-making. In Truth and Truth-Making, eds. Lowe, E. J. and Rami, A., 136. Stocksfield: Acumen.Google Scholar
Rasmussen, Joshua. 2014. Defending the Correspondence Theory of Truth. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rayo, Agustín. 2009. Toward a trivialist account of mathematics. In New Waves in Philosophy of Mathematics, eds. Bueno, Otávio and Linnebo, Øystein, 239260. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Rayo, Agustín. 2013. The Construction of Logical Space. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Read, Stephen. 2000. Truthmakers and the disjunction thesis. Mind (New Series) 109: 6780.Google Scholar
Read, Stephen. 2010. Necessary truth and proof. Kriterion 51: 4767.Google Scholar
Restall, Greg. 1996. Truthmakers, entailment and necessity. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74: 331340.Google Scholar
Restall, Greg. 2009. Postscript to “Truth-makers, entailment and necessity.” In Truth and Truth-Making, eds. Lowe, E. J. and Rami, A., 98101. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.Google Scholar
Rettler, Bradley. 2016. The General Truthmaker View of ontological commitment. Philosophical Studies 173: 14051425.Google Scholar
Rhoda, Alan R. 2009. Presentism, truthmakers, and God. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 90: 4162.Google Scholar
Robinson, Denis. 2000. Identities, distinctnessess, truthmakers, and indiscernibility principles. Logique et Analyse 43: 145183.Google Scholar
Robinson, Michael. 2016. Truthmakers, moral responsibility, and an alleged counterexample to Rule A. Erkenntnis 81: 13331339.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo. 1998. Searle’s correspondence theory of truth and the slingshot. Philosophical Quarterly 48: 513522.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo. 1999. Truthmaking and the slingshot. In Metaphysics in the Post-Metaphysical Age: Papers of the 22nd International Wittgenstein Symposium, Volume VII (2), eds. Meixner, Uwe and Simons, Peter, 177184. Kirchberg am Wechsel: Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo. 2000. What is the problem of universals? Mind (New Series) 109: 255273.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo. 2002a. The problem of universals and the limits of conceptual analysis. Philosophical Papers 31: 3947.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo. 2002b. Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo. 2005. Why truthmakers. In Truthmakers: The Contemporary Debate, eds. Beebee, Helen and Dodd, Julian, 1731. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo. 2006a. Truthmaker Maximalism defended. Analysis 66: 260264.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo. 2006b. Truthmaking, entailment, and the conjunction thesis. Mind (New Series) 115: 957982.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo. 2009. The disjunction and conjunction theses. Mind (New Series) 118: 427443.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo. 2011. Review of Truth and Ontology, by Trenton Merricks. Mind (New Series) 120: 542552.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo. 2013. Resemblance nominalism, conjunctions and truthmakers. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 113: 2138.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo. 2015. Grounding is not a strict order. Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1: 517534.Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard. 1982. Consequences of Pragmatism (Essays: 1972–1980). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard. 1986. Pragmatism, Davidson and truth. In Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson, ed. LePore, Ernest, 333355. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, Jay F. 1972. Russell on negative facts. Noûs 4: 2740.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand. 1918. The philosophy of logical atomism [lectures 1–2]. The Monist 28: 495527.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand. 1919a. On propositions: what they are and how they mean. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 2: 143.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand. 1919b. The philosophy of logical atomism [lectures 3–4]. The Monist 29: 3263.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand. 1919c. The philosophy of logical atomism [lectures 5–6]. The Monist 29: 190222.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand. 1919d. The philosophy of logical atomism [lectures 7–8]. The Monist 29: 345380.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand. 1921. The Analysis of Mind. London: George Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand. 1924. Logical atomism. In Contemporary British Philosophy: Personal Statements, ed. Muirhead, J. H., 357383. London: George Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
Russell, Gillian. 2008. Truth in Virtue of Meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rychter, Pablo. 2014. Truthmaker theory without truthmakers. Ratio (New Series) 27: 276290.Google Scholar
Saenz, Noël Blas. 2014. The world and truth about what is not. Philosophical Quarterly 64: 8298.Google Scholar
Saenz, Noël Blas. In press. An account of truthmaking. Synthese.Google Scholar
Salmon, Nathan. 1986. Frege’s Puzzle. Cambridge: Bradford Books.Google Scholar
Salmon, Nathan. 1998. Nonexistence. Noûs 32: 277319.Google Scholar
Sanson, David, and Caplan, Ben. 2010. The way things were. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81: 2439.Google Scholar
Sayre-McCord, Geoffrey. 1986. The many moral realisms. Southern Journal of Philosophy 24 (Supplement): 122.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 2014. Being Realistic about Reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan. 2008a. Truth and fundamentality: On Merricks’s Truth and Ontology. Philosophical Books 49: 302316.Google Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan. 2008b. Truthmaker commitments. Philosophical Studies 141: 719.Google Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan. 2010. The least discerning and most promiscuous truthmaker. Philosophical Quarterly 60: 307324.Google Scholar
Scheffler, Uwe, and Shramko, Yaroslav. 2000. The logical ontology of negative facts: on what is not. In Things, Facts and Events, eds. Faye, Jan, Scheffler, Uwe, and Urchs, Max, 109131. Amsterdam: Rodopi.Google Scholar
Schiffer, Stephen. 1996. Language-created language-independent entities. Philosophical Topics 24: 149167.Google Scholar
Schipper, Arthur. 2018. Aboutness and negative truths: a modest strategy for truthmaker theorists. Synthese 195: 36853722.Google Scholar
Schnieder, Benjamin. 2006a. Troubles with truth-making: necessitation and projection. Erkenntnis 64: 6174.Google Scholar
Schnieder, Benjamin. 2006b. Truth-making without truth-makers. Synthese 152: 2146.Google Scholar
Schulte, Peter. 2011. Truthmakers: a tale of two explanatory projects. Synthese 181: 413431.Google Scholar
Schulte, Peter. 2014. Can truthmaker theorists claim ontological free lunches? European Journal of Philosophy 22: 249268.Google Scholar
Searle, John R. 1979. Expression and Meaning: Studies in the Theory of Speech Acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Shafer-Landau, Russ. 2003. Moral Realism: A Defence. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, Sydney. 1979. Identity, properties, and causality. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4: 321342.Google Scholar
Sidelle, Alan. 1989. Necessity, Essence, and Individuation: A Defense of Conventionalism. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Sider, Theodore. 1999. Presentism and ontological commitment. Journal of Philosophy 96: 325347.Google Scholar
Sider, Theodore. 2001. Four-Dimensionalism: An Ontology of Persistence and Time. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Sider, Theodore. 2006. Quantifiers and temporal ontology. Mind (New Series) 115: 7597.Google Scholar
Sider, Theodore. 2011. Writing the Book of the World. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Simons, Peter. 1992. Logical atomism and its ontological refinement: a defense. In Language, Truth and Ontology, ed. Mulligan, Kevin, 157179. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
Simons, Peter. 1997. Higher-order quantification and ontological commitment. Dialectica 51: 255271.Google Scholar
Simons, Peter. 2000a. Continuants and occurrents. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74: 5975.Google Scholar
Simons, Peter. 2000b. Truthmaker optimalism. Logique et Analyse 43: 1741.Google Scholar
Simons, Peter. 2005. Negatives, numbers, and necessity: some worries about Armstrong’s version of truthmaking. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 83: 253261.Google Scholar
Simons, Peter. 2007a. The price of positivity: Mumford and negatives. In Metaphysics and Truthmakers, ed. Monnoyer, Jean-Maurice, 331333. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
Simons, Peter. 2007b. Truth in virtue of meaning. In Metaphysics and Truthmakers, ed. Monnoyer, Jean-Maurice, 6778. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
Simons, Peter. 2010. Relations and truthmaking. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary 84: 199213.Google Scholar
Simpson, Matthew. 2014. Defending truthmaker non-maximalism. Thought 3: 288291.Google Scholar
Simpson, Matthew. 2016. MacBride on truth in truthmaking. Analysis 76: 1926.Google Scholar
Skiles, Alexander. 2014. Is there a dilemma for the truthmaker non-maximalist? Synthese 191: 36493659.Google Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. 1963. Philosophy and Scientific Realism. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Smith, Barry. 1982. Some formal moments of truth. In Language and Ontology: Proceedings of the 6th International Wittgenstein Symposium, ed. Leinfellner, Werner, 186190. Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky.Google Scholar
Smith, Barry. 1989. Constraints on correspondence. In Traditionen und Perspektiven der analytischen Philosophie: Festschrift für Rudolf Haller, eds. von Wolfgang, Herausgegeben, Gombocz, L., Rutte, Heiner, and Sauer, Werner, 415430. Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky.Google Scholar
Smith, Barry. 1999. Truthmaker realism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77: 274291.Google Scholar
Smith, Barry. 2002. Truthmaker realism: response to Gregory. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 80: 231234.Google Scholar
Smith, Barry, and Brogaard, Berit. 2000. A unified theory of truth and reference. Logique et Analyse 43: 4993.Google Scholar
Smith, Barry, and Simon, Jonathan. 2007. Truthmaker explanations. In Metaphysics and Truthmakers, ed. Monnoyer, Jean-Maurice, 7998. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
Sorensen, Roy. 2001. Vagueness and Contradiction. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Stenwall, Robin. 2010. Causal truthmaking. Metaphysica 11: 211222.Google Scholar
Stenwall, Robin. 2016. Truthmaker internalism and the mind-dependence of propositions. Acta Analytica 31: 5976.Google Scholar
Stenwall, Robin. 2017. Causal grounds for negative truths. Philosohical Studies 174: 29732989.Google Scholar
Stoneham, Tom. 2009. Time and truth: the presentism-eternalism debate. Philosophy 84: 201218.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. 1959. Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Sundholm, Göran. 1994. Existence, proof and truth-making: a perspective on the intuitionistic conception of truth. Topoi 13: 117126.Google Scholar
Tahko, Tuomas E. 2013. Truth-grounding and transitivity. Thought 2: 332340.Google Scholar
Tahko, Tuomas E. 2016. Armstrong on truthmaking and realism. In Metaphysics and Scientific Realism: Essays in Honour of David Malet Armstrong, ed. Calemi, Francesco F., 207218. Boston: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
Tałasiewicz, Mieszko, Odrowąż-Sypniewska, Joanna, Wciórka, Wojciech, and Wilkin, Piotr. 2013. Do we need a new theory of truthmaking? Some comments on Disjunction Thesis, Conjunction Thesis, Entailment Principle and explanation. Philosophical Studies 165: 591604.Google Scholar
Tallant, Jonathan. 2009a. Ontological cheats might just prosper. Analysis 69: 422430.Google Scholar
Tallant, Jonathan. 2009b. Presentism and truth-making. Erkenntnis 71: 407416.Google Scholar
Tallant, Jonathan. 2010a. Not a total failure. Philospohia 38: 795810.Google Scholar
Tallant, Jonathan. 2010b. Still cheating, still prospering. Analysis 70: 502506.Google Scholar
Tallant, Jonathan. 2010c. There’s no existent like “no existence” like no existent I know. Philosophical Studies 148: 387400.Google Scholar
Tallant, Jonathan. 2013. Recent work: time. Analysis 73: 369379.Google Scholar
Tallant, Jonathan. 2018. Truth and the World: An Explanationist Theory. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Tallant, Jonathan and Ingram, David. 2012a. Presentism and distributional properties. In Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Volume 7, eds. Bennett, Karen and Zimmerman, Dean W., 305314. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tallant, Jonathan and Ingram, David. 2012b. Time for distribution? Analysis 72: 264270.Google Scholar
Tallant, Jonathan and Ingram, David. 2017. Truth and dependence. Ergo 4: 955980.Google Scholar
Tarski, Alfred. 1956. The concept of truth in formalized language. In Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics: Papers From 1923 to 1938, trans. Woodger, J. H., 152278. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, Richard. 1952. Negative things. Journal of Philosophy 49: 433449.Google Scholar
Thomas, Andrew. 2011. Deflationism and the dependence of truth on reality. Erkenntnis 75: 113122.Google Scholar
Thomasson, Amie L. 1996. Fiction, modality and dependent abstracta. Philosophical Studies 84: 295320.Google Scholar
Thomasson, Amie L. 1999. Fiction and Metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Thomasson, Amie L. 2003a. Fictional characters and literary practices. British Journal of Aesthetics 43: 138157.Google Scholar
Thomasson, Amie L. 2003b. Speaking of fictional characters. Dialectica 57: 205223.Google Scholar
Thomasson, Amie L. 2009. Non-descriptivism about modality. Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 4: 126.Google Scholar
Thomasson, Amie L. 2014. Deflationism in semantics and metaphysics. In Metasemantics: New Essays on the Foundations of Meaning, eds. Burgess, Alexis and Sherman, Brett, 185213. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Thomasson, Amie L. 2015a. Fictional discourse and fictionalisms. In Fictional Objects, eds. Brock, Stuart and Everett, Anthony, 255274. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Thomasson, Amie L. 2015b. Ontology Made Easy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Timpe, Kevin. 2007. Truth-making and divine eternity. Religious Studies 43: 299315.Google Scholar
Tooley, Michael. 1977. The nature of laws. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7: 667698.Google Scholar
Tooley, Michael. 1997. Time, Tense, and Causation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Torrengo, Giuliano. 2013. The grounding problem and presentist explanations. Synthese 190: 20472063.Google Scholar
Torrengo, Giuliano. 2014. Ostrich presentism. Philosophical Studies 170: 255276.Google Scholar
Ushenko, A. 1931. On negative facts. Philosophical Review 40: 379384.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas C. 1969. Facts and tautological entailments. Journal of Philosophy 66: 477487.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas C. 1980. The Scientific Image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
van Inwagen, Peter. 1977. Creatures of fiction. American Philosophical Quarterly 14: 299308.Google Scholar
van Inwagen, Peter. 2004. A theory of properties. In Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Volume 1, ed. Zimmerman, Dean W., 107138. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Vance, Chad. 2014. Truthmaker theory does not solve the Gettier problem. Ratio 27: 291305.Google Scholar
Veber, Michael. 2008. How to derive a “not” from an “is”: a defense of the incompatibility view of negative truths. Metaphysica 9: 7991.Google Scholar
Vision, Gerald. 2003. Lest we forget “the correspondence theory of truth.” Analysis 63: 136142.Google Scholar
Vision, Gerald. 2005. Deflationary truthmaking. European Journal of Philosophy 13: 364380.Google Scholar
Vision, Gerald. 2010. Intensional specifications of truth-conditions: “because”, “in virtue of”, and “made true by…” Topoi 29: 109123.Google Scholar
Voltolini, Alberto. 2006. How Ficta Follow Fiction. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Waechter, Jonas. 2017. Positive truthmakers for negative truths: a solution to Molnar’s problem. Philosophical Studies 174: 579592.Google Scholar
Warren, Jared. 2015. The possibility of truth by convention. Philosophical Quarterly 65: 8493.Google Scholar
Westphal, Jonathan. 2006. The future and the truth-value links: a common sense view. Analysis 66: 19.Google Scholar
Williams, Michael. 1999. Meaning and deflationary truth. Journal of Philosophy 96: 545564.Google Scholar
Williams, Michael. 2002. On some critics of deflationism. In What Is Truth?, ed. Schantz, Richard, 146158. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Williamson, Timothy. 1994. Vagueness. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Williamson, Timothy. 1998. Bare possibilia. Erkenntnis 48: 257273.Google Scholar
Williamson, Timothy. 1999. Truthmakers and the converse Barcan formula. Dialectica 53: 253270.Google Scholar
Williamson, Timothy. 2007. The Philosophy of Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Williamson, Timothy. 2013. Modal Logic as Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, Alastair. 2018. Metaphysical causation. Noûs 52: 723751.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1922. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Trans. Ogden, C. K.. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner and Company.Google Scholar
Wright, Crispin. 1983. Frege’s Conception of Numbers as Objects. Aberdeen: Aberdeen University Press.Google Scholar
Wright, Crispin. 1986. Scientific realism, observation and the verification principle. In Fact, Science and Morality: Essays on A .J. Ayer's Language, Truth and Logic, eds. Macdonald, Graham and Wright, Crispin, 247274. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wright, Crispin. 1992. Truth and Objectivity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wright, Crispin. 1995. Truth in ethics. Ratio (New Series) 8: 209226.Google Scholar
Wyatt, Jeremy. 2016. The many (yet few) faces of deflationism. Philosophical Quarterly 66: 362382.Google Scholar
Yagisawa, Takashi. 2001. Against creationism in fiction. Philosophical Perspectives 15: 153172.Google Scholar
Yalcin, Seth. 2007. Epistemic modals. Mind (New Series) 116: 9831026.Google Scholar
Yip, Jack. 2015. Truthmaking as an account of how grounding facts hold. Kriterion 29: 1132.Google Scholar
Young, James O. 2009. Truth, correspondence and deflationism. Frontiers of Philosophy in China 4: 563575.Google Scholar
Zalta, Edward N. 1983. Abstract Objects: An Introduction to Axiomatic Metaphysics. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Zamani, Mohsen. 2017. The totality of states of affairs and the minimal truthmaker. Theoria 83: 471483.Google Scholar
Zardini, Elia. 2017. Further reflections on sentences saying of themselves strange things. Logic and Logical Philosophy 26: 563581.Google Scholar
Zimmerman, Dean W. 2005. The A-theory of time, the B-theory of time, and “taking tense seriously.” dialectica 59: 401457.Google Scholar
Zimmerman, Dean W. 2008. The privileged present: defending an “A-theory” of time. In Contemporary Debates in Metaphysics, eds. Sider, Theodore, Hawthorne, John, and Zimmerman, Dean W., 211225. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • Jamin Asay, The University of Hong Kong
  • Book: A Theory of Truthmaking
  • Online publication: 18 April 2020
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • Jamin Asay, The University of Hong Kong
  • Book: A Theory of Truthmaking
  • Online publication: 18 April 2020
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • Jamin Asay, The University of Hong Kong
  • Book: A Theory of Truthmaking
  • Online publication: 18 April 2020
Available formats
×