Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-07T23:11:59.605Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

7 - Extraordinary Beginnings I: Arendt's Critique of Schmitt

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 August 2010

Andreas Kalyvas
Affiliation:
New School for Social Research, New York
Get access

Summary

Arendt, apparently appalled by Schmitt's adherence to Nazism in 1933, never discussed his work directly. For this reason, I begin with a preliminary comparative discussion of Arendt and Schmitt, seeking to establish the terms of a dialogue that actually never took place. Her critique of sovereignty, her distinctive appropriation of the constituent power, and her theory of spontaneous beginnings become more intelligible if set against the background of Schmitt's political and constitutional theory. For example, the perplexing issue of extraordinary new beginnings, which is one of her central preoccupations, comes at times extremely close to Schmitt's constitutional writings. Arendt, much like Schmitt, focused on the relationship among radical breaks, revolutionary changes, and constitutional transformations. Both thinkers were similarly captivated by the politics associated with constitutional foundations and instituting, political practices.

Despite Arendt's lack of explicit engagement with Schmitt's political theory, one can still find some few, scattered remarks about Schmitt that reveal more than an accidental interest. In one of these, Arendt exhibits a hesitant appreciation of his “very ingenious theories” that “still make arresting reading.” On other occasions, she referred to Schmitt as “the famous professor of constitutional and international law” and as an “outstanding scholar[s]” and jurist. Although it is not clear what Arendt considered to be “ingenious” in Schmitt's theories or which attributes of his work qualify it as “famous” and “outstanding,” what stands out in these telegraphic comments is the importance she ascribed to the legal and constitutional dimension of his texts.

Type
Chapter
Information
Democracy and the Politics of the Extraordinary
Max Weber, Carl Schmitt, and Hannah Arendt
, pp. 194 - 231
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, Foundations of Transcendental Philosophy [1796–1799], Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1992, p. 292.Google Scholar
Michelet, Jules, Cours au collège de la France: 1838–1851, Vol. I, Paris: Gallimard, 1995, p. 19.Google Scholar
Honig, Bonnie, Political Theory and the Displacement of Politics, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1993Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy, “Arendt's Constitutional Politics,” in The Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt, ed. Villa, Dana R., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000, pp. 201–219CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Villa, Dana R., Arendt and Heidegger: The Fate of the Political, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996, pp. 76–77.Google Scholar
Beatty, Joseph, “Thinking and Moral Considerations: Socrates and Arendt's Eichmann,” in Hannah Arendt: Critical Essays, ed. Hinchman, Lewis P. and Hinchman, Sandra K., Albany: State University of New York Press, 1994, pp. 57–78Google Scholar
Benhabib, Seyla, “Judgment and the Moral Foundations of Politics in Hannah Arendt's Thought,” in Situating the Self: Gender, Community, and Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics, New York: Routledge, 1992, pp. 121–147.Google Scholar
Lichtheim, George, “Two Revolutions,” in The Concept of Ideology and Other Essays, New York: Random House, 1967, pp. 115–122.Google Scholar
Hobsbawn, Eric J., “Hannah Arendt on Revolution,” in Revolutionaries: Contemporary Essays, New York: Pantheon Books, 1973, pp. 201–208.Google Scholar
Young-Bruehl, Elisabeth, Hannah Arendt: For the Love of the World, New Haven: Yale University Press, 1982, pp. 402–406.Google Scholar
Miller, James, “The Pathos of Novelty: Hannah Arendt's Image of Freedom in the Modern World,” in Hannah Arendt: The Recovery of the Public World, ed. Hill, Melvyn A., New York: St. Martin's Press, 1979, p. 177.Google Scholar
Pitkin, Hanna F., The Attack of the Blob: Hannah Arendt's Concept of the Social, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998, pp. 219, 223, 225.Google Scholar
Canovan, Margaret, Hannah Arendt: An Interpretation of Her Political Thought, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992, p. 249.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parekh, Bikhu, “Hannah Arendt's Critique of Marx,” in Hannah Arendt: The Recovery of the Public World, ed. Hill, Melvyn A., New York: St. Martin's Press, 1979, pp. 77–78Google Scholar
Benhabib, Seyla, The Reluctant Modernism of Hannah Arendt, Thousand Oaks, Calif.: Sage Publications, 1996, pp. 155–166Google Scholar
Honeywell, J. A., “Revolution: Its Potentialities and Its Degradations,” Ethics, 80:4 (1970), pp. 251–265CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernstein, Richard, “Rethinking the Social and the Political,” in Philosophical Profiles: Essays in a Pragmatic Mode, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1986, pp. 238–259Google Scholar
Elshtain, Jean Bethke, “Hannah Arendt's French Revolution,” Salmagundi, 84 (1989), pp. 203–213Google Scholar
Fehér, Ferenc, “Freedom and the ‘Social Question’ (Hannah Arendt's Theory of the French Revolution),” Philosophy and Social Criticism, 12:1 (1987), p. 24Google Scholar
Arendt, Hannah, “Revolution and Freedom/A Lecture,” in In Zwei Welten: Siegfried Moses zum füfundsiebzigsten Geburtstag, ed. Trimmer, Hans, Tel Aviv: Verlag Bitaon, 1962, p. 584.Google Scholar
Lefort, Claude, Democracy and Political Theory, trans. Macey, David, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1988, p. 55.Google Scholar
Adamson, Walter L., “Beyond ‘Reform or Revolution’: Notes on Political Education in Gramsci, Habermas and Arendt,” Theory and Society, 6:3 (1978), pp. 429–460.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jay, Martin, “The Political Existentialism of Hannah Arendt,” in Permanent Exiles: Essays on the Intellectual Migration from Germany to America, New York: Columbia University Press, 1985, pp. 237–256.Google Scholar
Kateb, Georges, “Death and Politics: Hannah Arendt's Reflections on the American Constitution,” Social Research, 54:3 (1987), pp. 612–613.Google Scholar
Entrèves, Maurizio Passerin d', The Political Philosophy of Hannah Arendt, London: Routledge, 1994, pp. 86–87Google Scholar
Malberg, Raymond Carré, Contribution à la théorie générale de l'État, Vol. II, Paris, Librairie de la société du Recueil Sirey, p. 494.
Derrida, Jacques, “Declarations of Independence,” New Political Science, 15 (1986), pp. 7–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ingram, David, “Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Trial of (Post) Modernity or the Tale of the Two Revolutions,” in Hannah Arendt: Twenty Years Later, ed. May, Larry and Kohl, Jerome, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1996, pp. 221–250.Google Scholar
Gottsegen, Michael, The Political Thought of Hannah Arendt, Albany: State University of New York Press, 1994, p. 39.Google Scholar
Markell, Pachen, “The Rule of the People: Arendt, Arché, and Democracy,” American Political Science Review, 100:1 (2006), pp. 11–13.Google Scholar
Arendt, Hannah, “On Hannah Arendt,” in Hannah Arendt: The Recovery of the Public World, ed. Hill, Melvyn A., New York: St. Martin's Press, 1979, p. 310.Google Scholar
Kateb, George, Hannah Arendt: Politics, Conscience, Evil, Totowa, N.J.: Rowman & Allanheld Publishers, 1983, p. 18.Google Scholar
Arendt, Hannah, “Some Questions of Moral Philosophy,” Social Research, 61:4 (Winter 1994), pp. 747–748.Google Scholar
Lefort, Claude, “Hannah Arendt and the Political,” in Democracy and Political Theory, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1988, p. 51.Google Scholar
Kalyvas, Andreas, “From the Act to the Decision: Hannah Arendt and the Question of Decisionism,” Political Theory, 32:4 (2004), pp. 320–346.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gierke, Otto, Political Theories of the Middle Age, trans. Maitland, F. W., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1900, pp. 37–61.Google Scholar
Kelsen, Hans, Allgmeine Staatslehre, Vienna: Nachdruck, 1993, pp. 102–119.Google Scholar
Aristotle, , Politics, trans. Rackham, H., Loeb Classical Collection, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990, I. i. 7–9, p. 9.Google Scholar
Cohen, Jean, “Rights and Citizenship in Hannah Arendt. Dilemmas of Arendtian Republicanism,” Constellations, 3:2 (1996), pp. 164–189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grotius, Hugo, Le droit de la guerre et de la paix, Paris: PUF, 1999, book I, chap. 3, para. 7, p. 98.Google Scholar
Spinoza, Benedict, A Theologico-Political Treatise, trans. Elwes, R. H. M.New York: Dover Publications, 1951, p. 211.Google Scholar
Austin, John, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined and the Uses of the Study of Jurisprudence, Indianapolis: Hackett, 1998, pp. 255, 254.Google Scholar
Hobbes, , Leviathan, ed. Tuck, Richard, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992, part II, chap. 26, p. 184Google Scholar
Villa, Dana R., Politics, Philosophy, Terror: Essays on the Thought of Hannah Arendt, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999, pp. 81, 109, 123.Google Scholar
Madison, James, “Letter to George Washington, Oct. 18, 1787,” in Writings, ed. Rakove, Jack, New York: Library of America, 1999, p. 141.Google Scholar
Keenan, Alain, “Promises, Promises. The Abyss of Freedom and the Loss of the Political in the Work of Hannah Arendt,” Political Theory, 22:2 (1994), p. 310.Google Scholar
Hirschman, Albert O., The Rhetoric of Reaction: Perversity, Futility, Jeopardy, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1991.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×