Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-02T19:03:50.479Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

11 - The Argument from Epistemology

Claims of Equivalence

from Part Two - Responding to the Case for Inclusion

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 November 2011

Howard H. Schweber
Affiliation:
University of Wisconsin, Madison
Get access

Summary

Questions of epistemology arise in complicated ways. The case for constraint in the theory of public justification depends on the claim that there exist certain categories of arguments, of which “religious” names an important case, that ought not to be permitted in public political discourse. Inclusionist arguments often focus on claims that there are no good epistemological grounds for distinguishing among different kinds of justifications. These arguments can be divided into two sorts of claims: that there is no articulable difference at all among religious and other forms of arguments (“perfect equivalence”), and that some arguments that are characterized as religious are distinguishable from publicly accessible forms of reason, and hence are properly excluded, but that other forms of religious justifications do not fit that description (“partial equivalence”). In this chapter, I engage these forms of the epistemological argument for inclusion and in the next chapter, I attempt to move from that dialogue to a better formulation of what is meant by describing a proffered justification as “accessible.”

One thing that makes these arguments complicated is the sometimes uneasy relationship between assertions of fact and normative conclusions. Without prejudging the case, let us consider an easy (and hence not terribly interesting) hypothetical case. Imagine two arguments in favor of a law criminalizing the act of wearing wool and linen in the same garment (shatnes), an act that is forbidden in the Hebrew Bible (New Revised Standard Bible Translation Committee, 1990: Leviticus 19:19). One argument states simply, “This practice is prohibited by the Bible, and a majority of us believe that the laws of the Bible should be observed.” The gravamen of the entire argument of this book has been that without more, this would not describe a proper justification for using the power of the state to enforce the rule against shatnes among nonbelievers. But now consider a second case in which the speaker says, “This practice is prohibited by the Bible; the accounts of events contained in the Bible demonstrate that a nation's failure to follow its laws leads to God sending earthquakes, locust attacks, and foreign invaders against that nation; therefore we should prevent this practice by making it a crime.” Here, the immediate justification, which is eminently accessible, is a prediction of disastrous consequences. The difficulty is that the conclusion is based on a whole series of assumptions: the reliability of accounts of historical events in the biblical text; the reliability of the biblical assertion that these events were expressions of divine displeasure; the reliability of the assumption that God exists and continues to work in the manner described in the biblical text; and the reliability of the interpretation of the rule at issue (this last is obviously more problematic in some cases than in others).

Type
Chapter
Information
Democracy and Authenticity
Toward a Theory of Public Justification
, pp. 328 - 363
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Gamwell, Franklin 2004 69

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×