Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T22:43:19.371Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

41 - Priscian of Lydia and Pseudo-Simplicius on the soul

from VI - Late Platonism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 May 2011

Lloyd Gerson
Affiliation:
University of Toronto
Get access

Summary

Little is known of the life of Priscian of Lydia (born late fifth century ce), who is not to be confused with his older namesake Priscian of Caesarea (fl. c. 500 ce), the famous Latin grammarian. Priscian of Lydia is one of the six philosophers listed by Agathias Histories 2.30–1 to have accompanied Damascius on his journey to the Sassanian king Chosroes I (reign 531–79 ce). Agathias suggests they came of their own accord guided by the false impression that Chosroes’ reign resembled a Platonic state; he does not connect their journey to the famous closure of the Athenian school in 529. The philosophers soon discovered that Chosroes was far from the ideal king and resolved to leave quickly. Because Chosroes was well disposed towards them Priscian and the others were able to leave Chosroes under the safeguard of a treaty the Persian king concluded with Rome in 532, which comprised a clause that ‘these men should be allowed to return to their own country and live there henceforth in safety, without being forced to adopt opinions which they did not hold, or to change their own faith’. Whether they settled in Athens, or perhaps in Carrhae (Harran), where over a century later a centre of Platonic philosophy was flourishing, is still a matter of controversy.

SOLUTIONES AD CHOSROEM

Priscian is credited with a work apparently written for King Chosroes, and known to us in Latin translation3 under the title Solutiones eorum de quibus dubitavit Chosroes Persarum rex. The text does not give us any indication about the circumstances in which it originated.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2000

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Athanassiadi, P. (1993) ‘Persecution and Response in Late Paganism: the Evidence of Damascius’, Journal of Hellenic Studies 103:Google Scholar
Baltussen, H. (2008) Philosophy and Exegesis in Simplicius. The Methodology of a Commentator. London.
Barbotin, E. (1954) La théorie aristotélicienne de l’intellect d’après Théophraste. Louvain.
Blumenthal, H.J. (1982) ‘The Psychology of (?) Simplicius’ Commentary on the De anima’, in Blumenthal, H.J. and Lloyd, A.C. (eds.), Soul and the Structure of Being in later Neoplatonism: Syrianus, Proclus and Simplicius [Colloquium Liverpool]. Liverpool.Google Scholar
Blumenthal, H.J. (1996) Aristotle and Neoplatonism in Late Antiquity. Interpretations of the De anima. London.
Blumenthal, H.J. (1997) ‘Some Notes on the Text of Pseudo-Simplicius’ Commentary on Aristotle’s De anima, III.1–5’, in Joyal, M. (ed.), Studies in Plato and the Platonic Tradition. Aldershot.Google Scholar
Bossier, F., and Steel, C. (1972) ‘Priscianus Lydus en de In de Anima van Pseudo(?)-Simplicius’, Tijdschrift voor Filosofie 34:Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. (2002) ‘De anima II.5’, Phronesis 47..Google Scholar
Cameron, A. (1969–70) ‘Agathias on the Sassanians’, Dumbarton Oaks Papers 23:Google Scholar
Cappuyns, M. (1933) Jean Scot érigène: sa vie, son oeuvre, sa penseé. Louvain.
Chodaczek, A. (1936) De Prisciani Lydi Solutionum Capite VI, Acta Seminarii Philologici II Universitatis Ionneo-Casimirianae Leopoliensis 1. Lwów.
d’Alverny, M.-T. (1977) ‘Les “Solutiones ad Chosroem” de Priscianus Lydus et Jean Scot’, in Jean Scot érigène et l’histoire de la philosophie. Paris.Google Scholar
Dörrie, H. (1959) Porphyrios’ ‘Symmikta Zetemata’, Munich.
De Haas, F. A. J. (2000) ‘Recollection and Potentiality in Philoponus’, in Kardaun, M. and Spruijt, J. (eds.), The Winged Chariot. Collected Essays on Plato and Platonism in Honour of L.M. de Rijk. Leiden.Google Scholar
Diller, A. (1951) ‘A Source of the Mirabiles Auscultationes’, Classical Philology 46..Google Scholar
Esposito, M. (1918) ‘Priscianus Lydus and Johannes Scottus’, Classical Review 32:Google Scholar
French, R. (ed.) (1994) Ancient Natural History: Histories of Nature. London–New York.
Ganson, T. (2002) ‘A Puzzle concerning the Aristotelian Notion of a Medium of Sense-Perception’, in Fortenbaugh, W.W. and Wöhrle, G. (eds.), On the Opuscula of Theophrastus. Akten der 3. Tagung der Karl-und-Gertrud-Abel-Stiftung vom 19.-23. Juli 1999 in Trier. Stuttgart.Google Scholar
Gersh, S. E. (1986) Middle Platonism and Neoplatonism. The Latin Tradition. Edited by McInerny, Ralph. 2 vols, Publications in Medieval Studies. Notre Dame, IN.
Hällström, G.A. (1994) ‘The Closing of the Neoplatonic School in A.D. 529: an Additional Aspect’, in Castrén, P. (ed.), Post-Herulian Athens. Aspects of Life and Culture in Athens A.D. 267–529. Helsinki.Google Scholar
Hadot, I. (1978) Le problème du Néoplatonisme alexandrin: Hiérocles et Simplicius. Paris.
Hadot, I. (1982) ‘La doctrine de Simplicius sur l’âme raisonnable humaine dans le Commentaire sur le Manuel d’épictète’, in Blumenthal, H.J. and Lloyd, A.C. (eds.), Soul and the Structure of Being in Late Neoplatonism. Liverpool.Google Scholar
Hadot, I. (1987a) ‘La vie et l’oeuvre de Simplicius d’après des sources grecques et arabes’, in Hadot, I. (ed.), Simplicius, sa vie, son oeuvre, sa survie. Actes du colloque international de Paris, 1985 [Peripatoi. Philologisch-historische Studien zum Aristotelismus, 15]. Berlin.Google Scholar
Hadot, I. (1987b) ‘Recherches sur les fragments du commentaire de Simplicius sur la Métaphysique d’Aristote’, in Hadot, I. (ed.), Simplicius. Sa vie, son oeuvre, sa survie. Berlin–NY.Google Scholar
Hadot, I. (1997) ‘Aspects de la théorie de la perception chez les néoplatoniciens: sensation (αἴσθησις), sensation commune (κοινὴ αἴσησις), sensibles communs (κοινὰ αἰσθητά) et conscience de soi (συναίσθησις)’, Documenti e studi sulla tradizione filosofica medievale 8..Google Scholar
Hadot, I. (2002) ‘Simplicius or Priscianus? On the Author of the Commentary on Aristotle’s De anima (CAG XI): a Methodological Survey’, Mnemosyne 55:Google Scholar
Huby, P. (1993) ‘Priscian of Lydia as Evidence for Iamblichus’, in Blumenthal, H.J. and Clark, E.G., (eds.), The Divine Iamblichus. Philosopher and Man of Gods. London.Google Scholar
Huby, P. and Gutas, D. (1999) Theophrastus of Eresus: Sources for His Life, Writings, Thought and Influence. Commentary 4: Psychology. Philosophia Antiqua 81. Leiden.
Iamblichus De anima. Text, Translation and Commentary, eds. Finamore, J. F. and Dillon, J. M. (2002). Leiden.
Kamp, A. (2001) Philosophiehistorie als Rezeptionsgeschichte. Die Reaktion auf Aristoteles’ De Anima-Noetik. Der frühe Hellenismus, Bochumer Studien zur Philosophie 33. Amsterdam–Philadelphia, PA.
Kapetanaki, S. and Sharples, R.W. (2006) Pseudo-Aristoteles (Pseudo-Alexander), Supplementa Problematorum. Peripatoi 20. Berlin–New York.
Kupreeva, I. (1999) ‘Review of P. Huby, C. Steel, J.O. Urmson, P. Lautner, On Theophrastus on Sense-Perception and Simplicius On Aristotle On the Soul 2.5–12, Ithaca 1997’, Bryn Mawr Classical Review. URL http://ccat.sas.upenn.edu/bmcr/99/99–10-18.html.Google Scholar
Lameer, J. (1997) ‘From Alexandria to Bagdad: Reflections on the Genesis of a Problematical Tradition’, in Endress, G. and Kruk, R. (eds.), The Ancient Traditions in Christian and Islamic Hellenism: Studies on the Transmission of Greek Philosophy and Sciences dedicated to H.J. Drossaart Lulofs on his Ninetieth BirthdayLeiden.Google Scholar
Lane Fox, R. (2005) ‘Harran, the Sabians and the Late Platonist “Movers”’, in Smith, A. (ed.), The Philosopher and Society in Late Antiquity. Swansea.Google Scholar
Lautner, P. (1992) ‘Philoponus, in De Anima III: Quest for an Author’, Classical Quarterly 42:Google Scholar
Lautner, P. (1994) ‘Rival Theories of Self-awareness in Late Neoplatonism’, Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies of the University of London 39:Google Scholar
Luna, C. (2001) ‘Review of R. Thiel, Simplicius und das Ende der neuplatonischen Schule in Athen, Stuttgart 1999’, Mnemosyne 54:Google Scholar
Moraux, P. (ed.) (1984) Der Aristotelismus bei den Griechen. Von Andronikos bis Alexander von Aphrodisias. Der Aristotelismus im I. und II. Jahrhundert n.Chr. Vol. II, Peripatoi. Philologischhistorische Studien zum Aristotelismus 6. Berlin–New York.
Oldfather, W. A. (1936) ‘Review of De Prisciani Lydi Solutionum Capite VI by Aline Chodaczek’, The Classical Weekly 30.Google Scholar
Perkams, M. (2003) ‘Doppelte Entelecheia: das Menschenbild in “Simplikios”, Kommentar zu Aristoteles’ “De anima”, Elenchos 24:Google Scholar
Perkams, M. (2005) ‘Priscian of Lydia, Commentator on the De anima in the Tradition of Iamblichus’, Mnemosyne 58:Google Scholar
Perkams, M. (2008) Selbstbewusstsein in der Spätantike. Die neuplatonischen Kommentare zu Aristoteles’ “De anima”, Quellen und Studien zur Philosophie 85. Berlin.
Prisciani Lydi quae extant Metaphrasis in Theophrastum et Solutionum ad Chosroem liber, ed. Bywater, I. (1886). CAG Supplementum Aristotelicum 1.2.
,Priscianus. On Theophrastus on Sense-Perception, with ‘Simplicius’ On Aristotle on the Soul 2.5–12, trans. Huby, Pamela and Steel, Carlos (1997). London.
Quicherat, J. (1853) ‘Solution des problèmes proposés par Chosroès. Traité inédit de Priscien le Philosophe’, Bibliothèque de l’école des Chartes 3.4:Google Scholar
Rashed, M. (2000) ‘Traces d’un Commentaire de Simplicius sur la Métaphysique a Byzance?’, Revue des Sciences Philosophiques et Théologiques 84:Google Scholar
Schmitt, C.B. (1969) ‘Some Notes on Jacobus Dalechampius and His Translation of Theophrastus (Manuscript: BN.Lat. 11,857)’, Gesnerus 26:Google Scholar
Schmitt, C.B. (1976) ‘Priscianus Lydus’, in Cranz, F.E. and Kristeller, P.O. (eds.), Catalogus translationum et commentariorum. Mediaeval and Renaissance Latin Translations and Commentaries. Washington DC.Google Scholar
Sharples, R.W. (1987) ‘Alexander of Aphrodisias. Scholasticism and innovation’, ANRW II.36.2: Berlin-New York.Google Scholar
Silverstein, T. (1952) ‘Adelard, Aristotle, and the De natura deorum’, Classical Philology 47. 2:Google Scholar
Simplicii in libros Aristotelis De anima commentaria, ed. Hayduck, Michael (1882). CAG XI.
,Simplicius. Commentaire sur le Manuel d’é pictète. Introduction et édition critique du texte grec par Ilsetraut Hadot (1996). Leiden.
,Simplicius. On Aristotle’s On the Soul 1.1–2.4, trans. Lautner, P., and Urmson, J. O. (1995). Ithaca, NY.
,Simplicius. On Aristotle’s On the Soul 3.1–5, trans. Blumenthal, H. J. (2000). London–Ithaca, NY.
Steel, C. G. (1978) The Changing Self: A Study on the Soul in Later Neoplatonism: Iamblichus, Damascius and Priscianus. Verhandelingen van de Koninklijke Academie voor Wetenschappen, Letteren en Schone Kunsten van België, Klasse der Letteren Jaargang 40, Nr. 85. Brussels.
Tardieu, M. (1986) ‘Sabiens coraniques et Sabiens de Harran’, Journal Asiatique 274:Google Scholar
Taub, L. C. (2003) Ancient Meteorology. London–New York.
Thiel, R. (1999) ‘Simplikios und das Ende der neuplatonischen Schule in Athen’, Akademie der Wissenschaften und der Literatur Mainz. Abhandlungen der geistes- und sozialwissenschaftlichen Klasse, no. 8.Google Scholar
Westerink, L. G. (1973) ‘Proclus on Plato’s Three Proofs of Immortality’, in Zetesis. Liber amicorum De Strycker, Antwerp–Utrecht.Google Scholar
Wilmart, A. (1937) ‘Les réponses de Priscien le Philosophe sous le nom de Saint AugustineRevue Bénédictine 49:Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×