Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-fbnjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-01T11:20:12.380Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

19 - The Socratic legacy

from PART V - ETHICS AND POLITICS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2008

Keimpe Algra
Affiliation:
Universiteit Utrecht, The Netherlands
Jonathan Barnes
Affiliation:
Université de Genève
Jaap Mansfeld
Affiliation:
Universiteit Utrecht, The Netherlands
Malcolm Schofield
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge
Get access

Summary

Introduction

From the perspective of 100 BC the history of ethics in the Hellenistic period is dominated by Stoicism and Epicureanism. The sceptical Academy had also made a significant contribution by criticizing the Stoics and by classifying alternative theories of the summum bonum, but in the Peripatos social philosophy, though it remained alive, was scarcely vigorous. When Epicurus and Zeno first established their schools at Athens, these developments could not have been foreseen. At that time the Academy was still the centre of doctrinal Platonism, and Theophrastus at the Peripatos included ethics among the numerous subjects on which he wrote and lectured. Many other philosophers were also stimulating reflection on the foundations of happiness and attracting followers – Cynics, Cyrenaics, Menedemus, Stilpo, Pyrrho. Ethics was a hotly debated subject around the year 300 BC.

That fact helps to explain why Epicurus and Zeno were rapidly able to acquire an audience. Yet there was no reason to predict that the schools they founded would soon become the main ethical options. Why did those schools achieve such a dominating position? With hindsight it can be seen that they offered an informed choice between two radically different ways for persons to orient themselves. Antithetical though they are in cosmology, theology, attitude to politics and evaluation of virtue relative to pleasure, Stoicism and Epicureanism closely resemble one another in being comprehensive philosophies of life. Both their mutual exclusiveness and their comprehensiveness are factors that help to explain the remarkable success both philosophies achieved. These, of course, are also retrospective judgements.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1999

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ausland, H. W. (1989) ‘On the moral origin of the Pyrrhonian philosophy’, Elenchos 10.Google Scholar
Becker, L. C., ed. (1992a) Encyclopedia of Ethics, 2 vols. (New York).Google Scholar
Becker, L. C., ed. (1992b) A History of Western Ethics (New York).Google Scholar
Brancacci, A. (1981) ‘La filosofia di Pirrone e le sue relazioni con il cinismo’, in Giannantoni, (1981a) I.
Classen, C. J. (1958) ‘Aristippos’, Hermes 86.Google Scholar
Decleva Caizzi, F. (1966) Antisthenis Fragmenta (Varese/Milan).Google Scholar
Decleva Caizzi, F., ed. (1981a) Pirrone: Testimonianze, Elenchos, 5 (Naples).Google Scholar
Döring, K. (1988) Der Sokratesschüler Aristipp und die Kyrenaiker, AAWM, Geistes- und Sozialwiss. Klasse, 1988.1 (Mainz).Google Scholar
Dudley, D. R. (1937) A History of Cynicism from Diogenes to the 6th Century A.D. (London; repr. 1976).Google Scholar
Fortenbaugh, W. W., Huby, P. M., Sharples, R. W. & Gutas, D., edd. (1992b) Theophrastus of Eresus: Sources for his Life, Writings, Thought, and Influence, 2 vols., Philosophia Antiqua (Leiden).Google Scholar
Foucault, M. (1988) ‘Technologies of the self’, in Martin, L. H., Gutman, H. & Hutton, P. H., edd., Technologies of the Self: a Seminar with Michel Foucault (Amherst).Google Scholar
Giannantoni, G. (1958) I Cirenaici. Raccolta delle fonti antiche, traduzione e studio introduttivo (Florence).Google Scholar
Goulet-Cazé, M.-O. (1982) ‘Un syllogisme stoïcien sur la loi dans la doxographie de Diogène le Cynique. A propos de Diogène Laërce VI 72’, RhM 125.Google Scholar
Hahm, D. E. (1992) ‘Diogenes Laertius VII: On the Stoics’, in Haase, W., ed., ANRW 11 36.6 (Berlin/New York).Google Scholar
Höistad, R. (1948) Cynic Hero and Cynic King: Studies in the Cynic Conception of Man (Uppsala).Google Scholar
Irwin, T. (1986) ‘Stoic and Aristotelian conceptions of happiness’, in Schofield, & Striker, (1986a).Google Scholar
Kahn, Ch. (1985) ‘Democritus and the origins of moral psychology’, AJPh 106.Google ScholarPubMed
Kindstrand, J. F. (1976) Bion of Borysthenes: A Collection of the Fragments with Introduction and Commentary, Acta Universitatis Upsaliensis, Studia Graeca Upsaliensia 11 (Uppsala).Google Scholar
Kleve, K. (1983) ‘Scurra Atticus. The Epicurean view of Socrates’, in AA. VV. (1983) I.Google Scholar
Laks, A. (1993b) ‘Annicéris et les plaisirs psychiques. Quelques préalables doxographiques’, in Brunschwig & Nussbaum (1993).Google Scholar
Long, A. A. (1968) ‘Aristotle's legacy to Stoic ethics’, BICS 15.Google Scholar
Long, A. A. (1978a) ‘Timon of Phlius: Pyrrhonist and satirist’, PCPhS 204 (n.s. 24).Google Scholar
Long, A. A. (1988a) ‘Stoic eudaimonism’, in Cleary & Shartin (1988) ; repr. in Long, (1996).Google Scholar
Long, A. A. (1988b) ‘Socrates in Hellenistic philosophy’, CQ 38 ; repr. in Long, (1996).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Long, A. A. (1993a) ‘Hellenistic ethics and philosophical power’, in Green, P., ed., Hellenistic History and Culture (Berkeley/Los Angeles).Google Scholar
Long, A. A. (1997) ‘Theophrastus and the Stoa’, in Ophuijsen, & Raalte, (1997).Google Scholar
Long, A. A. & Sedley, D. N., edd. (1987) The Hellenistic Philosophers, 2 vols.: i. Translations of the principal sources with philosophical commentary; ii. Greek and Latin texts with notes and bibliography (Cambridge, various reprints).Google Scholar
Mansfeld, J. (1986) ‘Diogenes Laertius on Stoic philosophy’, in Giannantoni, (1986a) ; repr. in Mansfeld, (1990b).Google Scholar
Mansfeld, J. (1988b) (rev. Goulet-Cazé 1986) CR 38.Google Scholar
Mette, H. J. (1984) ‘Zwei Akademiker heute: Krantor und Arkesilaos’, Lustrum 26.Google Scholar
Morrison, D. (1987) ‘On Professor Vlastos' Xenophon’, AncPhil 7.Google Scholar
Niehues Pröbsting, H. (1979) Der Kynismus des Diogenes und der Begriff des Zynismus, Humanistische Bibliothek, Reihe 1 Bd. 40 (Munich).Google Scholar
Sandbach, F. H. (1985) Aristotle and the Stoics, PCPhS suppl. vol. 10 (Cambridge).Google Scholar
Schofield, M. (1991) The Stoic Idea of the City (Cambridge).Google Scholar
Vlastos, G. (1991) Socrates: Ironist and Moral Philosopher (Cambridge).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×