Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jkksz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-24T08:56:54.098Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Shape

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

Timothy Crockett
Affiliation:
University of California, Berkeley
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

From quite early in his career, Descartes lists shape as one of the three genuine “modes” of extension or ways of being extended, the other two being size and motion. This austere ontology of body is in sharp contrast to the Aristotelian Scholastic model of the explanation of natural phenomena that appeals to an elaborate scheme of forms and qualities. As a proponent of mechanistic scientific explanations, Descartes held instead that all natural phenomena can be explained entirely in terms of the arrangements of corpuscles, or extended microbodies, characterized solely in terms of size, shape, and motion.

Although motion plays a central role in Descartes’ natural philosophy, shape is no less important to his scheme of scientific explanation. This is because the way that motion is characterized seems to presuppose that body has a determinate extension or shape. According to the “proper” characterization of motion Descartes introduces in the Principles, it consists in “the transfer of one piece of matter, or one body, from the vicinity of the other bodies which are in immediate contact with it, and which are regarded as being at rest, to the vicinity of other bodies” (AT VIIIA 53, CSM I 233). Yet this account presupposes the individuation of bodies from one another, which in turn seems to presuppose that a body, insofar as it is delineated from the bodies that surround it, has at any particular moment a determinate extension or shape. Further evidence for the explanatory importance of the mode of shape can be found in Descartes’ insistence in his early work, the Rules, that shape plays a central role in all cases of sense perception: “Sense perception occurs in the same way in which wax takes on an impression from a seal. It should not be thought that I have a mere analogy in mind here” (AT X 412–13, CSM I 40–41).

As obvious as the idea that shape is a modification of extension might seem, there are deep interpretative and philosophical difficulties with Descartes’ claim. The principle interpretative difficulty is that it is not clear what he means by “shape,” a difficulty that is exacerbated by the fact that he never offers an explicit explanation.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ariew, Roger, and Garber, Daniel, ed. 1989. G. W. Leibniz: Philosophical Essays. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Arthur, Richard, ed. 2001. The Labyrinth of the Continuum: Writings on the Continuum Problem, 1672–1686, by G. W. Leibniz. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Couturat, Louis, ed. 1903. Opuscules et fragments inédits de Leibniz. Paris.Google Scholar
Gerhardt, C. I., ed. 1875–90. Die philosophischen Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, vols. 2, 4, and 7. Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. 1923. Samtliche Shriften und Briefe. Philosophische Schriften, vol. 6. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag.Google Scholar
Mason, H. T., ed. 1985. The Leibniz-Arnauld Correspondence. New York: Garland.Google Scholar
Crockett, Timothy. 2009. “The Fluid Plenum: Leibniz on Surfaces and the Individuation of Body,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 17: 735–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crockett, Timothy. 2005. “Leibniz on Shape and the Cartesian Conception of Body,” in A Companion to Rationalism, ed. Nelson, A.. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing, 262–81.Google Scholar
Hoffman, Paul. 1990. “Cartesian Passions and Cartesian Dualism,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 71: 310–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levey, Samuel. 2005. “Leibniz on Precise Shapes and the Corporeal World,” in Leibniz: Nature and Freedom, ed. Cover, J. and Rutherford, D.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 69–94.Google Scholar
Sleigh, R. C. 1990. Leibniz and Arnauld: A Commentary on Their Correspondence.New Haven: Yale University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sowaal, Alice. 2004. “Cartesian Bodies,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34: 217–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Shape
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.232
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Shape
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.232
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Shape
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.232
Available formats
×