Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-24T08:54:51.840Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Geometry

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

Douglas Jesseph
Affiliation:
University of South Florida
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

Traditionally, the science of geometry was taken to be an abstract inquiry into the properties of continuous spatial magnitudes (lines, surfaces, angles, and solids). The geometrical method proceeds by strict deduction from clearly grasped and transparently true first principles, such as Euclid's first axiom (see common notion): “Things which are equal to the same thing are equal to one another” (Euclid 1926[1956], 1:222). This account of geometry distinguishes it from the science of arithmetic on the basis of its object: whereas geometry is the science of continuous quantities, arithmetic is the deductively organized study of discrete quantities (“multitudes” or “numbers” in the traditional parlance). The great geometers of Greek antiquity, Euclid, Archimedes, Apollonius, and Pappus, left behind an immense body of results whose level of technical sophistication was unmatched until the seventeenth century. Much of the work of geometers in Descartes’ day was directed toward the preparation of editions and translations of the work of classical Greek geometers, as well as speculative “restorations” of lost treatises on a variety of geometrical subjects. With the 1637 publication of Descartes’ Geometry, the subject underwent a profound and permanent change.

The particulars of Descartes’ involvement with geometry before the publication of the Geometry are very difficult to assess. His mathematical education at La Flèche was certainly guided by study of the works of the Jesuit mathematician Christopher Clavius, notably his Latin edition of Euclid's Elements with its extensive commentary (first published in 1574 and a standard work in the Jesuit mathematical curriculum) as well as a 1608 Algebra. On his arrival in the Netherlands in 1628, Descartes was in possession of what Isaac Beeckman called an “Algebra” (Journal 3: 94–95) that was evidently an early version of the Geometry. In a 1619 letter to Beeckman, Descartes announced that he had “discovered four remarkable and completely new demonstrations” and declared his intention to produce “a completely new science that will provide a general solution of all possible sorts of problems involving any sort of quantity, whether continuous or discrete, each according to its nature” (AT X 154, 157). It is apparent that even at this early stage in his mathematical career Descartes sought to apply algebraic techniques to study all types of quantity, with the result that the classical division between arithmetic and geometry was undermined.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Beeckman, Isaac. 1939–53. Journal tenu par Isaac Beeckman de 1604 à 1634, 4 vols., intro. and notes by C. de Waard. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Euclid, . 1926. The Thirteen Books of Euclid's “Elements” Translated from the Text of Heiberg, 3 vols., ed. and trans. Heath, T. L.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (reprint, New York: Dover, 1956).Google Scholar
Pappus of Alexandria, . 1875. Pappi Alexandrini Collectionis quae Supersunt, e Libris Manu Scriptis Edidit, 3 vols., ed. and trans. Hultsch, F.. Berlin: Weidmann (reprint, Amsterdam: Adolf Hakkert, 1965).Google Scholar
Bos, Henk J. M. 2001. Redefining Geometrical Exactness: Descartes’ Transformation of the Early Modern Concept of Construction. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bos, Henk J. M. 1993. “The Structure of Descartes’ Géométrie,” in Lectures in the History of Mathematics, ed. Bos, H. J. M.. Providence, RI: American Mathematical Society, 37–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bos, Henk J. M. 1981. “On the Representation of Curves in Descartes’ Géométrie,” Archive for History of the Exact Sciences 24: 295–338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heath, Thomas L. 1931. A Manual of Greek Mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press (reprint, New York: Dover, 1963).Google Scholar
Mancosu, Paolo. 2008. “Descartes and Mathematics” in A Companion to Descartes, ed. Broughton, J. and Carrier, J.. Oxford: Blackwell, 103–23.Google Scholar
Mancosu, Paolo. 1992. “Descartes's Geometry and Revolutions in Mathematics,” in Revolutions in Mathematics, ed. Gilles, D.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 83–116.Google Scholar
Mancosu, Paolo, and Arana, Andrew. 2010. “Descartes and the Cylindrical Helix,” Historia Mathematica 37: 403–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Molland, A. G. 1976. “Shifting the Foundations: Descartes's Transformation of Ancient Geometry,” Historia Mathematica 3: 21–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sasaki, Chikara. 2003. Descartes's Mathematical Thought. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Serfati, Michel. 2005. “René Descartes, Géométrie,” in Landmark Writings in Western Mathematics, 1640–1940, ed. Grattan-Guinness, I.. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1–22.Google Scholar
Serfati, Michel. 1993. “Les compass cartésiens,” Archives de philosophie 56: 197–230.Google Scholar
Whiteside, D. T.Patterns of Mathematical Thought in the Later Seventeenth Century,” Archive for History of the Exact Sciences 1: 179–388.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Geometry
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.117
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Geometry
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.117
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Geometry
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.117
Available formats
×