Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Dedication
- Contents
- Acknowledgments
- List of abbreviations
- Introduction
- Part I Background
- Part II Kinds of arguments
- Part III Analysis of argument relations
- 6 Thematic relations
- 7 Agent and Patient
- 8 Role iteration
- 9 Separation
- 10 Event structure
- 11 Linking and framing
- Part IV Case studies
- Glossary
- References
- Index
10 - Event structure
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 January 2015
- Frontmatter
- Dedication
- Contents
- Acknowledgments
- List of abbreviations
- Introduction
- Part I Background
- Part II Kinds of arguments
- Part III Analysis of argument relations
- 6 Thematic relations
- 7 Agent and Patient
- 8 Role iteration
- 9 Separation
- 10 Event structure
- 11 Linking and framing
- Part IV Case studies
- Glossary
- References
- Index
Summary
INTRODUCTION
Abstracting from its noun phrases, a clause is semantically a predicate of events, (1). Call this the main event of the clause.
(1) λe[P(e)]
P might relate the main event to others, as in (2), which cashes out P as a predicate of events that bear R to some other event. R might be Cause, for example.
(2) λe[∃e′[R(e)′](e)]
A semantic analysis like this is called an event structure. The events to which the main event is related are called subevents of the clause. Sometimes subevents might be parts of the main event (Schein 1993, Rothstein 2004).
An event structure is complex when it includes more than one predicate of events. When a clause with a single audible predicate is given a complex event structure, this is a claim of semantic decomposition. I assume by default that decomposition is strict, in the sense of Chapter 2, but will sometimes consider alternatives.
This chapter is about a much-used class of event-structural decompositions that derive from sources including Lakoff (1965, 1971), McCawley (1971), Ross (1972) and Dowty (1972). These works advance analyses like (3–6), with (b) giving the meaning of (a).
(3) a The glass is hard.
b Hard(the glass)
(4) a Floyd viewed the glass.
b Dop 〈Floyd, View (Floyd, the glass)〉
(5) a The glass hardened.
b Become p 〈Hard(the glass)〉
(6) a Floyd hardened the glass.
b Causep ∃φ[Dop 〈Floyd, φ〉], Becomep 〈Hard(the glass)〉〉
Here Dop, Becomep and Causep are propositional operators. Event structures are often written in this format. Yet they are usually talked about as relations over events, and we can rewrite them explicitly in those terms. One possible revision is given in (7–10), roughly following Parsons (1990). For expository clarity I mark the main event as e1 and leave it bound only by a lambda; the meaning of the complete sentence would have this variable existentially quantified.
- Type
- Chapter
- Information
- Arguments in Syntax and Semantics , pp. 212 - 232Publisher: Cambridge University PressPrint publication year: 2015