Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-xbtfd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-02T18:57:19.524Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Misguided model of human behavior: Comment on C. H. Burt: “Challenging the utility of polygenic scores for social science…”

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 September 2023

Ken Richardson*
Affiliation:
Berwick upon Tweed, UK [email protected]

Abstract

This commentary emphasizes two problem areas mentioned by Burt. First, that within-family designs do not eradicate stratification confounds. Second, that the linear/additive model of genetic causes of form and variation is not supported by recent progress in molecular biology. It concludes with an appeal for a (biologically and psychologically) more realistic model of such causes.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

Behavior geneticists tend to think that their field is unfairly controversial because of past associations with racism and eugenics. But there's more to it than that. Over the history of BG many scholars have commented on its seeming existence in a parallel universe, demanding relaxed scientific standards, building castles in the air with much reliance on “promissory notes,” as Burt puts it. Regarding BG's grounding in unlikely assumptions, Kempthorne (Reference Kempthorne1978, p. 18) asked “How naive can you get?” An illustration is how variations in cognition, educational attainment (EA), height, weight, and so on, are considered to be equally “complex,” with similar causal patterns of form and variation, as if eons of evolution and gulfs of biological necessity had never happened.

Another example, of course, is how genome-wide association studies/polygenic scores (GWASs/PGSs) appeal to vague “phenotypes,” using poorly validated measures, “surrogates” and “proxies,” inferring causes from mountains of correlations that largely wash-out over time (Richardson & Norgate, Reference Richardson and Norgate2015). Noting such thin evidential gruel Fletcher (Reference Fletcher2021, p. 256) refers to the “sleights of hand and folk wisdom from behavioral genetics.” Burt expertly exposes such problems in BG's contemporary search for validation at the molecular level. This commentary enlarges on two aspects.

Population stratification within-families

Burt rightly notes that the problem of population stratification haunts all interpretations of GWASs/PGSs and cannot be easily eliminated. BG researchers, however, seem to agree with Zaidi and Mathieson (cited by Burt) that “family-based studies are immune to stratification,” and present the equivalent of a randomized controlled trial (RCT; Harden, Reference Harden2021). However, children are not merely passive vehicles of additive G and E effects. They actively constructive perceptions of their worlds and creatively react to them.

Burt (target article, sect. 5.1.2, para. 7) mentions family dynamics that create “micro-stratification” within families. However, such dynamics also interact with wider social contexts to further generate spurious SNP–trait correlations in GWASs/PGSs. Facial appearance; height; weight; body shape; subclinical medical conditions such as myopia; hair form; and skin color (e.g., Hall, Reference Hall2017), are all subject to positive/negative feedback from peers and teachers, as well as siblings and parents, acting to cultural norms. They create unequal psychological effects and reactions that course through individuals' school and occupational careers (Kraft, Kraft, Hagen, & Espeseth, Reference Kraft, Kraft, Hagen and Espeseth2022; Wilkinson & Pickett, Reference Wilkinson and Pickett2018). Yet all will involve hundreds or thousands of SNPs covarying non-causally with psychological traits, and producing spurious GWAS/PGS results. They completely confound the preconditions for an RCT that Harden (Reference Harden2021) and others recommend.

Genetic causes

Burt says that “no serious scientist can suggest that genetic differences do not influence – in some complex, context-dependent way – developmental differences” (target article, sect. 6, para. 6). But we need to be clear that “influence” is not necessarily tractable as prediction. Unfortunately, prediction in BG is still dominated by the Galton/Fisher model. Despite acknowledging roles for the “environment,” “interactions,” and so on, mere attenuation of linear/additive genetic effects is assumed. So we get genomes described as “blueprints” (Plomin, Reference Plomin2019); or even as “cookbooks” (Harden, Reference Harden2021); whereas Madole and Harden (Reference Madole and Harden2023) assert that PGSs reveal an individual's “genetic propensity for a trait” (Madole & Harden, Reference Madole and Harden2023; sect. 3.1, para. 4); and that “the parental genotype causes an increase in their education” (Madole & Harden, Reference Madole and Harden2023; note 4). Burt (e.g., target article, sect. 6, para. 6) reveals the fallacies, and the dangers, in such logic.

But so do waves of recent research in molecular biology. The creative, anticipatory dynamics mentioned above, at the socio-cognitive level, have evolutionary precursors in learning/cognitive functions in cells, physiology, brain, and behavior (Lyon, Keijzer, Arendt, & Levin, Reference Lyon, Keijzer, Arendt and Levin2021; Richardson, Reference Richardson2020; Shapiro, Reference Shapiro2020). Development of form and variation does not start with gene transcription. DNA can do nothing until activated by the organism. That arises from vast signaling and metabolic networks monitoring the dynamic complexity and changeability of most natural environments. Their precursors in cytoplasm are inherited with genes, and their developmental fates are best described as emergent intelligent systems in which statistical patterns predict impending states by assimilating the covariance structures of the past and present (Richardson, Reference Richardson2021; Shapiro, Reference Shapiro2020).

That fundamental, multi-level, intelligence is seen in the context-dependent recruitment of transcription factors, cofactors, enhancers, promoters, and so on (Isbel, Grand, & Schübeler, Reference Isbel, Grand and Schübeler2022). Alternative splicing produces a diversity of proteins from the same gene (Wright, Smith, & Jiggins, Reference Wright, Smith and Jiggins2022). A single gene can be associated with the development of a variety of structures and functions (Watanabe et al., Reference Watanabe, Stringer, Frei, Mirkov, de Leeuw, Polderman and Posthuma2019). And multiple alternative pathways to desirable structural/functional endpoints are constructed in spite of genetic variation (Biddle, Martinez-Corral, Wong, & Gunawardena, Reference Biddle, Martinez-Corral, Wong and Gunawardena2021; Wagner & Wright, Reference Wagner and Wright2007).

Not even mutations comprise the random genetic lottery that Harden (Reference Harden2021) imagines (Monroe et al., Reference Monroe, Srikant, Carbonell-Bejerano, Becker, Lensink, Exposito-Alonso and Weigel2022). There are also processes – what Shapiro calls natural genetic engineering (NGE) – through which intelligent cells can themselves change genetic information: “NGE is shorthand to summarize all the biochemical mechanisms cells have to cut, splice, copy, polymerize and otherwise manipulate the structure of internal DNA molecules…Totally novel sequences can result from de novo untemplated polymerization or reverse transcription of processed RNA molecules” (Shapiro, Reference Shapiro2013, p. 287).

In other words, genes are best described as intermediary resource-providers for the organism as a whole: Servants to intelligent systems, not autonomous instructors. With the exception of relatively rare disorders or single-gene (Mendelian) variations, there are no independent “effects” of genomes. This is why Noble (Reference Noble2016) says we've had things the wrong way around in our descriptions of genetic causes. Baverstock (Reference Baverstock2021) uses the analogy of genes as the merchants that provide the necessary materials to build a house, but are neither the architect nor the builder. He calls for a “Copernican revolution” in our geno-centric view of living things.

Help or hindrance?

Burt asks if PGSs will ever be useful and urges caution. Fundamentally, though, it's the scientific framework – the Galton/Fisher model of heredity – that is the root of the problem. It persists, attracts funding and research effort, in spite of the logical, epistemological, and statistical errors described by Kempthorne (Reference Kempthorne1978) and others, because it affirms prior socioeconomic structures. Until that model is replaced by a more biologically realistic one it will be more of a hindrance to the advancement of knowledge than a help.

Financial support

No funding agency involved.

Competing interest

None.

References

Baverstock, K. (2021). The gene: An appraisal. Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology, 164, 4662. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pbiomolbio.2021.04.005CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Biddle, J. W., Martinez-Corral, R., Wong, F., & Gunawardena, J. (2021). Allosteric conformational ensembles have unlimited capacity for integrating information. eLife, 10, e65498. doi: 10.7554/eLife.65498CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fletcher, J. (2021). Backdoor to a dead end: A review essay. Population and Development Review, 48, 253258. https://doi.org/10.1111/padr.12487CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hall, J. C. (2017). No longer invisible: Understanding the psychosocial impact of skin color stratification in the lives of African American women. Health & Social Work, 42, 7178, https://doi.org/10.1093/hsw/hlx001CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Harden, K. P. (2021). The genetic lottery: Why DNA matters for social equality. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Isbel, L., Grand, R. S., & Schübeler, D. (2022). Generating specificity in genome regulation through transcription factor sensitivity to chromatin. Nature Reviews Genetics, 23(12), 728740. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41576-022-00512-6CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kempthorne, O. (1978). Logical, epistemological and statistical aspects of nature–nurture data interpretation. Biometrics, 34(1), 123.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kraft, P., Kraft, B., Hagen, T., & Espeseth, T. (2022). Subjective socioeconomic status, cognitive abilities, and personal control: Associations with health behaviours. Frontiers in Psychology, 12, 784758. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2021.784758CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lyon, P., Keijzer, F., Arendt, D., & Levin, M. (2021). Reframing cognition: Getting down to biological basics. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, B, 376, 20190750. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2019.0750CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Madole, J. W., & Harden, K. P. (2023). Building causal knowledge in behavior genetics. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X22000681Google Scholar
Monroe, J. G., Srikant, T., Carbonell-Bejerano, P., Becker, C., Lensink, M., Exposito-Alonso, M., … Weigel, D. (2022). Mutation bias reflects natural selection in Arabidopsis thaliana. Nature, 602, 101105. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41586-021-04269-6CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Noble, D. (2016). Dance to the tune of life: Biological relativity. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Plomin, R. (2019). Blueprint: How DNA makes us who we are. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Richardson, K. (2020). In the light of the environment: Evolution through biogrammars not programmers. Biological Theory, 15, 212e222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richardson, K. (2021). Genes and knowledge: Response to Baverstock. Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology, 167, 1217. doi: 10.1016/j.pbiomolbio.2021.10.003CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Richardson, K. (2022). Understanding intelligence. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Richardson, K., & Norgate, S. H. (2015). Does IQ really predict job performance? Applied Developmental Science, 19, 153169.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Shapiro, J. A. (2013). How life changes itself: The read-write (RW) genome. Physics of Life Reviews, 10, 287323.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Shapiro, J. A. (2020). All living cells are cognitive. Biochemical and Biophysical Research Communications, 564, 134149.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wagner, A., & Wright, J. (2007). Alternative routes and mutational robustness in complex regulatory networks. BioSystems, 88, 163172.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Watanabe, K., Stringer, S., Frei, O., Mirkov, M. U., de Leeuw, C., Polderman, T. J. C., … Posthuma, D. (2019). A global overview of pleiotropy and genetic architecture in complex traits. Nature Genetics, 51, 13391348. doi: 10.1038/s41588-019-0481-0CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wilkinson, R., & Pickett, K. (2018). The inner level. Allen Lane.Google Scholar
Wright, C. J., Smith, C. W. J., & Jiggins, C. D. (2022). Alternative splicing as a source of phenotypic diversity. Nature Reviews Genetics, 23, 697710. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41576-022-00514-4CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed