Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-29T04:13:11.811Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Purity is linked to cooperation but not necessarily through self-control

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 October 2023

Samuel Murray
Affiliation:
Laboratorio de Juicios y Emociones Morales, Universidad de Los Andes, Bogotá, Colombia Philosophy Department, Providence College, Providence, RI, USA. [email protected]; samuelmurray.org Neuroscience Program, Providence College, Providence, RI, USA
Santiago Amaya
Affiliation:
Laboratorio de Juicios y Emociones Morales, Universidad de Los Andes, Bogotá, Colombia Department of Philosophy, Universidad de Los Andes, Bogotá, Colombia. [email protected]; https://cienciassociales.uniandes.edu.co/filosofia/profesores/santiago-amaya/
William Jiménez-Leal
Affiliation:
Laboratorio de Juicios y Emociones Morales, Universidad de Los Andes, Bogotá, Colombia Department of Psychology, Universidad de Los Andes, Bogotá, Colombia. [email protected]; https://cienciassociales.uniandes.edu.co/psicologia/profesores/william-jimenez-leal/

Abstract

Fitouchi et al. claim that seemingly victimless pleasures and nonproductive activities are moralized because they alter self-control. Their account predicts that: (1) victimless excesses are negatively moralized because they diminish self-control, and (2) restrained behaviors are positively moralized because they enhance self-control. Several examples run contrary to these predictions and call into question the general relationship between self-control and cooperation.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

Fitouchi et al. outline two puzzles related to puritanical morality, or the “moralization of apparently victimless pleasures.” The first concerns the heterogeneous set of moral concerns that purity norms encompass (the puzzle of association). The second concerns the moralization of behaviors that seem unrelated to concerns about cooperation (the puzzle of morality without cooperation).

The moral disciplining account is meant to resolve both puzzles. On this account, self-control is necessary for cooperation. Thus, behaviors that diminish the capacity for self-control are negatively moralized, whereas behaviors that enhance the capacity for self-control are positively moralized. Puritanical norms encompass behaviors that are perceived to either diminish or enhance self-control, such as substance abuse or ritual observance, respectively. These behaviors are indirectly harmful or beneficial because engaging in them makes one a better or worse cooperative partner in the long run. Thus, the moral disciplining account not only draws a link between puritanical morality and cooperation, but also explains why puritanical norms encompass the behaviors that they do: These are behaviors that are perceived to alter individual self-control.

Fitouchi et al. have made an important case for the relationship between purity and cooperation. In addition to the evidence they provide, we have also found significant, cross-culturally robust correlations between responses to the morality-as-cooperation scale (Curry, Chesters, & Van Lissa, Reference Curry, Chesters and Van Lissa2019) and judgments about the moral wrongness of purity violations depicted in the moral foundations vignettes (Clifford, Iyengar, Cabeza, & Sinnott-Armstrong, Reference Clifford, Iyengar, Cabeza and Sinnott-Armstrong2015; Jiménez-Leal, Carmona, Murray, & Amaya, Reference Jiménez-Leal, Carmona, Murray and Amaya2022). Insofar as MAC responses index attitudes about cooperation, this suggests that there is a cross-culturally stable association between attitudes about purity violations and attitudes about cooperation.

We want to raise three issues that might help refine and extend the moral disciplining account. The first concerns two specific predictions of the account stated explicitly by Fitouchi et al.:

Victimless excesses should be preemptively moralized when perceived to causally contribute, through their deleterious effects on self-control, to an increased prevalence of uncooperative behaviors. Restrained behaviors should be praised when perceived to positively contribute, through their preserving effects on self-control, to the improvement of people's cooperativeness. (target article, sect. 3.3, para. 2)

Purity violations are negatively moralized because they diminish self-control, whereas purity compliance is positively moralized because it enhances self-control. But puritanical behaviors and self-control sometimes dissociate. Consider someone who confesses having sexual fantasies about his coworkers. Such thoughts could constitute a purity violation that might be moralized, even if the individual exhibits exemplary self-control and never acts on them.

Fitouchi et al. might argue that these cases are grist for their mill. Impure thoughts are evidence of intra-psychic self-control while also indicating low trait self-control. But this strategy cannot accommodate other examples that raise different problems for their prediction. Defecating on someone's grave out of spite may be regarded as a purity violation. But people would not make negative moral judgments about it because of diminished self-control. For that to be the case, people would have to view these acts as signs of inappropriate temporal discounting, evidence of inability to delay gratification, or anything of this sort, depending on how they conceptualize self-control (Bermúdez, Murray, Chartrand, & Barbosa, Reference Bermúdez, Murray, Chartrand and Barbosa2023). But that seems implausible. In fact, the more deliberative (and less impulsive) these behaviors appear the worse the violation seems.

Fitouchi et al. imply that people view certain behaviors as inherently addicting: “…intoxicants are moralized because they are perceived as favoring uncooperative behaviors…by leading people to lose control over immediate impulses and fueling disregard of future consequences” (target article, sect. 3.2.1, para. 3). They cite several studies that show people believe that alcohol consumption causes loss of self-control (Brett, Leavens, Miller, Lombardi, & Leffingwell, Reference Brett, Leavens, Miller, Lombardi and Leffingwell2016; Critchlow, Reference Critchlow1986; Leigh, Reference Leigh1987). But these studies measure attitudes about heavy drinking, which involve a recurrent pattern of behavior symptomatic of addiction. What about one-off purity violations? Is the family who eats the carcass of the dead pet losing control over some impulsive urge?

Fitouchi et al. are correct that we normally infer what others are like generally based on how they behave, and beliefs about self-control inform these inferences. Perceived self-control, however, is unlikely to fully mediate perceived cooperativeness, even for purity violations. We might look down on someone who defecates on a grave not because doing it makes them less self-controlled, but because it tells us something about how this person relates to things we respect. Perceptions of cooperativeness, therefore, can dissociate from perceptions of self-control when evaluating purity violations.

Suppose, for example, that someone is committed to the masculine ideal of the stiff upper lip. Upon hearing a touching story from a grieving friend, this person bursts out in tears. This is a case of inverse akrasia, where acting against one's better judgment ends up being morally appropriate (Arpaly, Reference Arpaly2000). In this situation, a failure of self-control ends up leading to behaviors that enhance the perceived cooperativeness of the individual: Weeping in solidarity with a friend can be a good thing, even if in doing so one violates a deeply held commitment. This is because in breaking this commitment, the individual shows that he cares for his friend. And caring is an important aspect of being a cooperative partner. Thus, perceived cooperativeness can dissociate from our judgments about individual capacity for self-control, which violates the first prediction of the moral disciplining account. In fact, the example suggests that diminished self-control can sometimes promote cooperation.

In sum, the moral disciplining account is correct that purity behaviors are moralized because of how such behaviors anchor inferences about what a person is like deep down. These inferences then shape how we think about people as cooperative partners, but they are distinct from judgments about individual control (Irving, Murray, Krasich, & Glasser, Reference Irving, Murray, Krasich and Glasser2023; Murray, Murray, Stewart, Sinnott-Armstrong, & De Brigard, Reference Murray, Murray, Stewart, Sinnott-Armstrong and De Brigard2023). Thus, puritanical morality is related to cooperation, although this relationship cannot be explained entirely through perceived alterations in self-control. Instead, it is explained by our perceptions of what an individual is like deep down (what she cares about, what she respects, etc.), which encompasses but also extends beyond how a person exercises self-control.

Financial support

The authors are supported by a grant from the James S. McDonnell Foundation (Grant no. 2020-1200).

Competing interest

None.

References

Arpaly, N. (2000). On acting rationally against one's best judgment. Ethics, 110(3), 488513.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bermúdez, J. P., Murray, S., Chartrand, L., & Barbosa, S. (2023) What's inside is all that counts? The contours of everyday thinking about self-control. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 14, 3355. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-021-00573-2CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Brett, E. I., Leavens, E. L., Miller, M. B., Lombardi, N., & Leffingwell, T. R. (2016). Normative perceptions of alcohol-related consequences among college students. Addictive Behaviors, 58, 1620. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.addbeh.2016.02.008CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Clifford, S., Iyengar, V., Cabeza, R., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2015). Moral foundations vignettes: A standardized stimulus database of scenarios based on moral foundations theory. Behavior Research Methods, 47(4), 11781198. https://doi.org/10.3758/s13428-014-0551-2CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Critchlow, B. (1986). The powers of John Barleycorn. Beliefs about the effects of alcohol on social behavior. The American Psychologist, 41(7), 751764. https://doi.org/10.1037//0003-066x.41.7.751CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Curry, O. S., Chesters, M. J., & Van Lissa, C. J. (2019). Mapping morality with a compass: Testing the theory of “morality-as-cooperation” with a new questionnaire. Journal of Research in Personality, 78, 106124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Irving, Z., Murray, S., Krasich, K., & Glasser, A. (2023). The catch-22 of forgetfulness: Responsibility for mental mistakes. Australisian Journal of Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2022.2157031CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jiménez-Leal, W., Carmona, G., Murray, S., & Amaya, S. (2022). Validation of the moral foundation vignettes in Latin America: The scope of moral foundations through the lens of an instrument. Manuscript under review.Google Scholar
Leigh, B. C. (1987). Beliefs about the effects of alcohol on self and others. Journal of Studies on Alcohol, 48(5), 467475.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Murray, S., Murray, E. D., Stewart, G., Sinnott-Armstrong, W., & De Brigard, F. (2023). Responsibility for forgetting. Philosophical Studies, 176(5), 11771201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar