1 Introduction and notation
For a domain $D \subset \mathbb C$ , we denote by $H(D)$ and $M(D)$ the spaces of holomorphic and meromorphic functions on D, respectively, and further set $M_{\infty }(D) := M(D) \cup \{f_{\infty }|_{D}\}$ , where $f_{\infty } \equiv \infty $ . Given two functions f and g defined on D, we say that g avoids f on D, if $g(z) \neq f(z)$ for every $z \in D$ . A function f is called unavoidable with respect to $A \subset M_{\infty }(D)$ , if there is no $g \in A$ that avoids f on D. Furthermore, we say that a family F of functions is unavoidable with respect to $A \subset M_{\infty }(D)$ , if there is no $g \in A$ that avoids every function $f \in F$ on D, that is, if for every $g \in A$ , there exists $f \in F$ such that the equation $g(z) = f(z)$ has at least one solution in D (including the possibility that both functions take the value $\infty $ ).
Unavoidable families seem to first have been investigated by Rubel and Yang [Reference Rubel and Yang12], who proved that for two functions $f_{1}$ and $f_{2} \in M(\mathbb C)$ , the family $\{f_{1}, f_{2}\}$ is never unavoidable with respect to $M(\mathbb C)$ . On the other hand, they also showed that any family consisting of three polynomials $p_{1}, p_{2}$ , and $p_{3}$ , such that $p_{1} - p_{2}$ and $p_{2} - p_{3}$ are not both constant, is unavoidable with respect to $M(\mathbb C)$ . Thus, the minimum cardinality of a family $F \subset M(\mathbb C)$ that is unavoidable with respect to $M(\mathbb C)$ is 3. Hayman and Rubel [Reference Hayman and Rubel5] considered similar questions for general domains $D \subset \mathbb C$ and proved that a family $F \subset M(D)$ consisting of two functions cannot be unavoidable with respect to $M(D)$ . In the other direction, it is shown in [Reference Hayman and Rubel5] that there exists a function $f \in H(D)$ , such that for every function $g \in M(D)$ , at least one of the three equations $g(z) = f(z), g(z) = -f(z)$ , and $g(z) = \infty $ has infinitely many solutions in D. In particular, it follows that the family $\{f, - f, f_{\infty }|_{D}\}$ is unavoidable with respect to $M_{\infty }(D)$ . Note that a result from [Reference Lappan7] shows that if $F \subset M_{\infty }(D)$ is a family of three functions that is unavoidable with respect to $M_{\infty }(D)$ , the three functions cannot avoid each other on D. The aforementioned result from [Reference Hayman and Rubel5] also implies that the family $\{f, -f\}$ is unavoidable with respect to the set of meromorphic functions in D that have at most finitely many poles. In particular, $\{f, -f\}$ is unavoidable with respect to $H(D)$ , and because for a function $g \in H(D)$ , the function $g + 1 \in H(D)$ avoids g on D, it follows that the minimum cardinality of a family $F \subset H(D)$ that is unavoidable with respect to $H(D)$ is 2. Again, according to [Reference Lappan7], the two functions cannot avoid each other on D in this case. We further mention some results from [Reference Logvinenko9], where unavoidable families of rational functions are investigated. For example, it is shown that the minimum cardinality of a family of rational functions, that no rational function can avoid on $\mathbb C$ , is 2. On the other hand, given two rational functions $r_{1}$ and $r_{2}$ , and a bounded domain $D \subset \mathbb C$ , there is a rational function that avoids both $r_{1}$ and $r_{2}$ on D. Finally, for any domain $D \subset \mathbb C$ , there exist two rational functions $r_{1}$ and $r_{2}$ , such that $\{r_{1}|_{D},r_{2}|_{D}\}$ is unavoidable with respect to $H(D)$ ; hence, $\{r_{1}|_{D},r_{2}|_{D}, f_{\infty }|_{D}\}$ is unavoidable with respect to $M_{\infty }(D)$ .
The abovementioned results show, in particular, that no single function $f \in M(D)$ is unavoidable with respect to $M_{\infty }(D)$ . However, a result of Lappan [Reference Lappan8] shows that for every simply connected domain $D \subset \mathbb C$ , there exists a continuous function on D that is unavoidable with respect to $M_{\infty }(D)$ . In a previous paper [Reference Lappan7], the same author constructed a function continuous on the unit disk $\mathbb D$ , which is unavoidable with respect to $H(\mathbb D)$ . In a similar vein, there may exist single functions $f \in M(D)$ that are unavoidable with respect to certain subsets of $M_{\infty }(D)$ . For example, in [Reference Lappan, Begehr, Gilbert and Wong6], it was proved that there exists a function $f \in M(\mathbb D)$ that is unavoidable with respect to the set of all normal functions in $M(\mathbb D)$ , and a corresponding result for $H(\mathbb D)$ is also given.
In this note, we prove further results on unavoidable families of meromorphic functions. We give new examples of families of cardinality 3 that are unavoidable with respect to $M_{\infty }(\mathbb C)$ and further construct families containing less than three functions that are unavoidable with respect to certain subsets of $M_{\infty }(\mathbb C)$ .
2 Unavoidable functions and zero–one sets
Let $(a_{n})$ and $(b_{n})$ be two (finite or infinite) disjoint sequences of complex numbers having no finite limit point. We say that $((a_{n}),(b_{n}))$ is a zero–one set, if there exists an entire function, whose zeros are exactly given by $(a_{n})$ and whose ones are exactly given by $(b_{n})$ , where multiple occurrences of elements $a_{n}$ and $b_{n}$ correspond to zeros and ones of the corresponding multiplicity. This notation was introduced in [Reference Rubel and Yang12], where it was shown that given sequences $(a_{n})$ and $(b_{n})$ , the set $((a_{n}),(b_{n}))$ is not, in general, a zero–one set. More precisely, [Reference Rubel and Yang12, Theorem 1] states that given any infinite sequence $(a_{n})$ in $\mathbb C$ without a finite limit point, there exists an infinite disjoint discrete sequence $(b_{n})$ , such that $((a_{n}),(b_{n}))$ is not a zero–one set. For further results related to zero–one sets, we refer the reader, for example, to [Reference Ozawa10, Reference Ozawa11, Reference Winkler14].
In the following, we show how the existence of sequences $(a_{n})$ and $(b_{n})$ , such that $((a_{n}),(b_{n}))$ is not a zero–one set, can be used to obtain unavoidable functions. Note that we always assume that $(a_{n})$ and $(b_{n})$ are disjoint and have no finite limit point.
Proposition 1 Let be given sequences $(a_{n})$ and $(b_{n})$ in $\mathbb C$ such that $((a_{n}),(b_{n}))$ is not a zero–one set. Consider a function $f \in H(\mathbb C)$ whose zeros are exactly given by $(a_{n})$ . Then, f is unavoidable with respect to the set of entire functions whose zeros are exactly given by $(b_{n})$ .
Proof Assuming that the statement is not correct, there exists a function $g \in H(\mathbb C)$ whose zeros are exactly given by $(b_{n})$ such that $f(z) \neq g(z)$ for every $z \in \mathbb C$ . Then, $f(z) - g(z) \neq 0$ , for all $z \in \mathbb C$ , and the function
is an entire function, whose zeros are exactly given by $(a_{n})$ and whose ones are exactly given by $(b_{n})$ . This contradicts the assumption that $((a_{n}),(b_{n}))$ is not a zero–one set.▪
To give an example, we recall that a classic result states that for two distinct rays $L_{0}$ and $L_{1}$ emanating from the origin, there is no transcendental entire function for which all zeros lie on $L_{0}$ and all ones lie on $L_{1}$ , while any (nonconstant) polynomial having this property is of degree 1 (e.g., [Reference Bergweiler and Eremenko1, Reference Bergweiler, Eremenko and Hinkkanen2]). Hence, given two sequences $(a_{n}) \subset L_{0}$ and $(b_{n}) \subset L_{1}$ having no finite limit point and such that $(a_{n})$ has at least two elements, the set $((a_{n}),(b_{n}))$ is not a zero–one set. Thus, if f is an entire function having at least two zeros and all whose zeros lie on a ray $L_{0}$ , we infer from Proposition 1 that f is unavoidable with respect to any entire function, all whose zeros are located on a ray that is different from $L_{0}$ .
Using a similar idea as in Proposition 1, we obtain the following result that gives examples of families $F \subset M(\mathbb C)$ of cardinality 3 that are unavoidable with respect to $M_{\infty }(\mathbb C)$ .
Theorem 1 Let be given sequences $(a_{n})$ and $(b_{n})$ in $\mathbb C$ such that $((a_{n}),(b_{n}))$ is not a zero–one set. Consider functions $f_{1}$ and $f_{2} \in H(\mathbb C)$ , whose zeros are exactly given by $(a_{n})$ and $(b_{n})$ , respectively. Then, the family $\{f_{1}, f_{2}, \frac {2f_{1} f_{2}}{f_{1} + f_{2}}\}$ is unavoidable with respect to $M_{\infty }(\mathbb C)$ .
Proof Let be given functions $f_{1}$ and $f_{2} \in H(\mathbb C)$ , such that the zeros of $f_{1}$ are exactly given by $(a_{n})$ and the zeros of $f_{2}$ are exactly given by $(b_{n})$ . Let further $g \in M(\mathbb C)$ , and suppose that g avoids both $f_{1}$ and $f_{2}$ in $\mathbb C$ . Then, $g(z) - f_{1}(z) \neq 0$ and $g(z) - f_{2}(z) \neq 0$ , for every $z \in \mathbb C$ ; in particular, g and $f_{1}$ , as well as g and $f_{2}$ , have no common zeros. Consider now the function
It follows from the assumptions that the zeros of F are exactly given by $(a_{n})$ , whereas its ones are exactly given by $(b_{n})$ . Because $((a_{n}),(b_{n}))$ is not a zero–one set, we must have $F \in M(\mathbb C) \,\backslash\, H(\mathbb C)$ . Thus, F must have at least one pole, implying that there exists $z_{0} \in \mathbb C$ such that $f_{1}(z_{0}) (g(z_{0}) - f_{2}(z_{0})) + f_{2}(z_{0}) (g(z_{0}) - f_{1}(z_{0})) = 0$ . It follows
and because $f_{1}$ and $f_{2}$ have no common zeros, we obtain
Hence, if the function $g \in M(\mathbb C)$ avoids $f_{1}$ and $f_{2}$ , it cannot avoid $\frac {2f_{1} f_{2}}{f_{1} + f_{2}}$ , and the family $\{f_{1}, f_{2}, \frac {2f_{1} f_{2}}{f_{1} + f_{2}}\}$ is unavoidable with respect to $M(\mathbb C)$ . By Proposition 1, the functions $f_{1}$ and $-f_{2}$ cannot avoid each other, and because they further have no common zeros, there exists $z_{1} \in \mathbb C$ with $f_{1}(z_{1}) + f_{2}(z_{1}) = 0$ and $f_{1}(z_{1}) \neq 0 \neq f_{2}(z_{1})$ . Thus, $z_{1}$ is a pole of $\frac {2f_{1} f_{2}}{f_{1} + f_{2}}$ , so that the family $\{f_{1}, f_{2}, \frac {2f_{1} f_{2}}{f_{1} + f_{2}}\}$ is unavoidable with respect to $M_{\infty }(\mathbb C)$ .▪
Remark If, in (1), we consider the function
we obtain that the family $\{f_{1}, f_{2}, \frac {f_{1}^{2} + f_{2}^{2}}{f_{1} + f_{2}}\}$ is unavoidable with respect to $M_{\infty }(\mathbb C)$ . Indeed, in this case, there exists $z_{0} \in \mathbb C$ such that $f_{1}(z_{0}) (g(z_{0}) - f_{1}(z_{0})) + f_{2}(z_{0}) (g(z_{0}) - f_{2}(z_{0})) = 0$ , and hence
Because $f_{1}$ and $f_{2}$ have no common zeros, it follows
3 Unavoidable functions with multiple zeros and poles
In the following, we will use some standard terminology from Nevanlinna Theory (e.g., [Reference Gol’dberg and Ostrovskii3, Reference Hayman4, Reference Yang15]), that is, for a nonconstant function $f \in M(\mathbb C)$ , a value $a \in \mathbb C_{\infty } := \mathbb C \cup \{\infty \}$ and $r \geq 0$ , we denote by $n(r,a,f)$ and $\overline {n}(r,a,f)$ the number of a-points (counting multiplicity) and of distinct a-points of f, respectively, in $\{z: \left |z\right | \leq r\}$ . The corresponding integrated counting functions will be denoted by $N(r,a,f)$ and $\overline {N}(r,a,f)$ , respectively. We write $T(r,f)$ for the characteristic function of f, and we recall that the deficiency $\delta (a,f)$ and the branching index $\Theta (a,f)$ of a are defined by
Note that $\delta (a,f) \leq \Theta (a,f)$ , and it is a consequence of the Second Fundamental Theorem that $\sum _{a \in \mathbb C_{\infty }} \Theta (a, f) \leq 2$ .
As mentioned in the introduction, a result from [Reference Hayman and Rubel5] states the existence of an entire function f, such that for every $g \in M(\mathbb C)$ having at most finitely many poles, at least one of the two equations $g(z) = f(z)$ and $g(z) = -f(z)$ has infinitely many solutions in $\mathbb C$ . Using similar ideas as in [Reference Hayman and Rubel5], we show the following result.
Theorem 2 Let $f \in M(\mathbb C)$ have infinitely many zeros, of which at most finitely many are simple. Suppose further that $g \in M(\mathbb C)$ has at most finitely many simple poles. Then, at least one of the two equations $g(z) = f(z)$ and $g(z) = -f(z)$ has infinitely many solutions in $\mathbb C$ . In particular, the family $\{f, -f\}$ is unavoidable with respect to the set of meromorphic functions having at most finitely many simple poles.
Proof Suppose that $f \in M(\mathbb C)$ has infinitely many zeros, of which at most finitely many are simple. Assuming that the statement is not correct, there exists a function $g \in M(\mathbb C)$ that has at most finitely many simple poles, such that both equations $g(z) = f(z)$ and $g(z) = -f(z)$ have at most finitely many solutions in $\mathbb C$ . In particular, f and g then have at most finitely many common zeros, and it follows from the assumptions that the function
has infinitely many zeros, of which at most finitely many are simple. Using the First Fundamental Theorem, this implies
and hence $\Theta (0, F) \geq \frac {1}{2}$ . Furthermore, it follows that the equations $F(z) = 1$ and $F(z) = -1$ have at most finitely many roots, so that we obtain $\Theta (1, F) = 1$ and $\Theta (-1, F) = 1$ , because F is transcendental. Finally, $\Theta (0, F) + \Theta (1, F) + \Theta (-1, F)> 2$ , in contradiction to the Second Fundamental Theorem.▪
Remark As previously mentioned, it was shown in [Reference Rubel and Yang12] that a family consisting of two meromorphic functions is never unavoidable with respect to $M(\mathbb C)$ . In particular, given $f \in M(\mathbb C)$ , there exists $g \in M(\mathbb C)$ such that $g(z) \neq f(z)$ and $g(z) \neq -f(z)$ , for every $z \in \mathbb C$ . It follows from the above theorem that if f has infinitely many zeros, of which at most finitely many are simple, then such a function g necessarily has infinitely many simple poles.
The following is an immediate consequence of Theorem 2.
Corollary 1 Let $f \in M(\mathbb C)$ have infinitely many zeros, of which at most finitely many are simple. Let further $g \in M(\mathbb C)$ and $n, m \in \mathbb N$ with $m \geq 2$ be given. Then, the following hold:
-
(i) At least one of the two equations $g^{(n)}(z) = f(z)$ and $g^{(n)}(z) = -f(z)$ has infinitely many solutions in $\mathbb C$ .
-
(ii) At least one of the two equations $g^{m}(z) = f(z)$ and $g^{m}(z) = -f(z)$ has infinitely many solutions in $\mathbb C$ .
In particular, for every $n, m \in \mathbb N$ with $m \geq 2$ , the family $\{f, -f\}$ is unavoidable with respect to the sets $\{g^{(n)}: g \in M(\mathbb C)\}$ and $\{g^{m}: g \in M(\mathbb C)\}$ .
If we make stronger assumptions on the zeros and poles, we can also obtain single functions $f \in M(\mathbb C)$ that are unavoidable with respect to certain subsets of $M(\mathbb C)$ .
Proposition 2 Let $f \in M(\mathbb C)$ be a meromorphic function having infinitely many zeros and poles, at most finitely many of which have multiplicity less than 3. If $g \in M(\mathbb C)$ has at most finitely many zeros and poles with multiplicity less than 3, the equation $g(z) = f(z)$ has infinitely many solutions in $\mathbb C$ .
Proof Let be given a function $f \in M(\mathbb C)$ having infinitely many zeros and poles, at most finitely many of which have multiplicity less than 3. Assuming that the statement does not hold, there exists a function $g \in M(\mathbb C)$ that has at most finitely many zeros and poles with multiplicity less than 3, such that the equation $g(z) = f(z)$ has at most finitely many solutions in $\mathbb C$ . In particular, f and g then have at most finitely many common zeros and poles, so that the function
has infinitely many zeros and poles, at most finitely many of which have multiplicity less than 3. As before, this implies
and hence $\Theta (0, F) \geq \frac {2}{3}$ . A similar argumentation gives $\Theta (\infty , F) \geq \frac {2}{3}$ , and because F is a transcendental function taking at most finitely many times the value $1$ , we further have $\Theta (1, F) = 1$ . Hence, $\Theta (0, F) + \Theta (1, F) + \Theta (\infty , F)> 2$ , in contradiction to the Second Fundamental Theorem.▪
Corollary 2 Let $f \in M(\mathbb C)$ have infinitely many zeros and poles, and consider $g \in M(\mathbb C)$ . Then, for every $n, m \in \mathbb N$ with $n, m \geq 3$ , the equation $g^{n}(z) = f^{m}(z)$ has infinitely many solutions in $\mathbb C$ .
Note that it follows from Theorem 2 that if $f \in M(\mathbb C)$ has infinitely many zeros, then for $g \in M(\mathbb C)$ and every $n, m \in \mathbb N$ with $n, m \geq 2$ , at least one of the two equations $g^{n}(z) = f^{m}(z)$ and $g^{n}(z) = -f^{m}(z)$ has infinitely many solutions in $\mathbb C$ .
It is easily seen that similar results can be obtained for entire functions.
Proposition 3 Let $f \in H(\mathbb C)$ be an entire function having infinitely many zeros, at most finitely many of which have multiplicity less than 3. If $g \in H(\mathbb C)$ has at most finitely many simple zeros, the equation $g(z) = f(z)$ has infinitely many solutions in $\mathbb C$ .
Indeed, assuming that the statement does not hold, there exists a function $g \in H(\mathbb C)$ that has at most finitely many simple zeros, such that the equation $g(z) = f(z)$ has at most finitely many solutions in $\mathbb C$ . The function $F(z) = \frac {f(z)}{g(z)}$ is then transcendental, and it follows as before that $\Theta (F,0) \geq \frac {2}{3}$ , $\Theta (F,\infty ) \geq \frac {1}{2}$ and $\Theta (F,1) = 1$ , which leads to a contradiction.
Corollary 3 Let $f \in H(\mathbb C)$ have infinitely many zeros, and consider $g \in H(\mathbb C)$ . Then, for every $n, m \in \mathbb N$ with $n \geq 2$ and $m \geq 3$ , the equation $g^{n}(z) = f^{m}(z)$ has infinitely many solutions in $\mathbb C$ .
In the following, we will show the existence of meromorphic functions that are unavoidable with respect to functions in $M(\mathbb C)$ whose number of zeros and poles are bounded in some sense. We therefore introduce the following notation. Given a continuous increasing function $\varphi : [0,\infty ) \to [1,\infty )$ with $\varphi (r) \to \infty $ for $r \to \infty $ , we denote by $M_{\varphi }(\mathbb C)$ the set of all functions $f \in M(\mathbb C)$ such that $n(r,0,f) = \mathcal {O}(\varphi (r))$ and $n(r,\infty ,f) = \mathcal {O}(\varphi (r))$ . Our result will be an immediate consequence of the following more general statement.
Theorem 3 Let be given a continuous increasing function $\varphi : [0,\infty ) \to [1,\infty )$ with $\varphi (r) \to \infty $ for $r \to \infty $ . There exists a function $f \in M(\mathbb C)$ , such that for every function $g \in M_{\varphi }(\mathbb C)$ , we have $\Theta (a, \frac {f}{g}) = 0$ for every $a \in \mathbb C \,\backslash\,\{0\}$ .
Proof Because $M_{\varphi _{1}}(\mathbb C) \subset M_{\varphi _{2}}(\mathbb C)$ if $\varphi _{1}(r) \leq \varphi _{2}(r)$ for $r \in [0,\infty )$ , we may assume that $r \leq \varphi (r)$ for $r \in [0,\infty )$ . We shall show that any function $f \in M(\mathbb C)$ with “sufficiently few” distinct zeros and poles, but “sufficiently many” zeros and poles (counting multiplicity) has the claimed property. We therefore consider a function $f_{1} \in H(\mathbb C)$ such that for every $n \in \mathbb N$ , the function $f_{1}$ has a zero at $z = n$ with multiplicity $[\varphi (n + 2)]!$ and $f_{1}(z) \neq 0$ for $z \in \mathbb C \,\backslash\, \mathbb N$ , where, here and in the following, we denote by $[r]$ the integer part of the real number r. We then define $f_{2}(z) := f_{1}(-z)$ and set $f(z) = \frac {f_{1}(z)}{f_{2}(z)}$ . We claim that f satisfies the statement of the theorem.
Let therefore $g \in M_{\varphi }(\mathbb C)$ be given. There exist $g_{1}$ and $g_{2} \in H(\mathbb C)$ , such that $g_{1}$ and $g_{2}$ have no common zeros and such that $g = \frac {g_{1}}{g_{2}}$ . Because $g \in M_{\varphi }(\mathbb C)$ , we have $n(r,0,g_{1}) = \mathcal {O}(\varphi (r))$ and $n(r,0,g_{2}) = \mathcal {O}(\varphi (r))$ , and considering the function
we obtain for $r> 0$ sufficiently large
where $c_{1}> 0$ and $c_{2}> 0$ are suitable constants. Moreover, for $r> 0$ sufficiently large, we have
for a suitable constant $c_{3}> 0$ .
Let now $\varepsilon> 0$ be given. Then, there exists $k \in \mathbb N$ such that $\varepsilon> \frac {1}{k} > 0$ , and from (2) and (3), we obtain that there exists $R_{k}> 0$ , such that for $r> R_{k}$ , we have
which, using the First Fundamental Theorem, implies
This finally yields $\Theta (0,F) \geq \frac {k-1}{k}> 1 - \varepsilon $ , and thus $\Theta (0,F) = 1$ .
By a similar argumentation, we obtain that $\Theta (\infty ,F) = 1$ ; hence, $\Theta (\infty ,F) + \Theta (0,F) = 2$ , so that $\Theta (a,F) = 0$ for every $a \in \mathbb C \,\backslash\, \{0\}$ by the Second Fundamental Theorem.▪
Corollary 4 Let be given a continuous increasing function $\varphi : [0,\infty ) \to [1,\infty )$ with $\varphi (r) \to \infty $ for $r \to \infty $ . There exists a function $f \in M(\mathbb C)$ , such that for every function $g \in M_{\varphi }(\mathbb C) \cup \{0, f_{\infty }\}$ , the equation $g(z) = f(z)$ has infinitely many solutions in $\mathbb C$ . In particular, f is unavoidable with respect to $M_{\varphi }(\mathbb C) \cup \{0, f_{\infty }\}$ .
It is easily seen that the function f from the proof of Theorem 3 satisfies the requirement, for, assuming this is not the case, there exists a function $g \in M_{\varphi }(\mathbb C) \cup \{0, f_{\infty }\}$ such that the equation $g(z) = f(z)$ has at most finitely many solutions in $\mathbb C$ . Because f has infinitely many zeros and poles, we have that $g \in M_{\varphi }(\mathbb C)$ , and the function $\frac {f}{g}$ takes at most finitely many times the value $1$ . Because $\frac {f}{g}$ is transcendental, this implies $\Theta (1, \frac {f}{g}) = 1$ , which is in contradiction to Theorem 3.
Remark
-
(i) Note that if the function $\varphi $ is such that for every $n \in \mathbb N$ , we have $\frac {\varphi (r)}{r^{n}} \to \infty $ for $r \to \infty $ , the set $M_{\varphi }(\mathbb C)$ contains every meromorphic function g of the form $g = g_{1} \, e^{g_{2}}$ , where $g_{1} \in M(\mathbb C)$ is of finite order of growth and $g_{2} \in H(\mathbb C)$ .
-
(ii) We further mention that it is a consequence of a generalization of the Second Fundamental Theorem (e.g., [Reference Hayman4, Theorem 2.5]) that given a function $f \in M(\mathbb C)$ and three functions $g_{1},g_{2}$ , and $g_{3} \in M(\mathbb C)$ that are “small” with respect to f, that is, functions satisfying $T(r,g_{i}) = o(T(r,f))$ for $r \to \infty $ , at least one of the three equations $g_{1}(z) = f(z)$ , $g_{2}(z) = f(z)$ , and $g_{3}(z) = f(z)$ has infinitely many solutions in $\mathbb C$ . Hence, a meromorphic function can avoid at most two small functions; in particular, a meromorphic function of infinite order can avoid at most two functions of finite order. Moreover, it follows from the deficiency relation for small functions (e.g., [Reference Yang15, p. 41]) that if $f \in M(\mathbb C)$ is a function that takes every value $a \in \mathbb C_{\infty }$ infinitely many times and satisfies $\sum _{a \in \mathbb C_{\infty }} \delta (a,f) = 2$ , the equation $g(z) = f(z)$ has infinitely many solutions in $\mathbb C$ for every function $g \in M(\mathbb C)$ that is small with respect to f. In particular, such a function f is unavoidable with respect to the set of small functions.
4 No $f \in M(\mathbb C)$ is unavoidable with respect to $H(\mathbb C)$
In the other direction, we have the following result.
Theorem 4 Given $f \in M(\mathbb C)$ , there exists a function $g \in H(\mathbb C)$ that avoids f on $\mathbb C$ . In particular, no $f \in M(\mathbb C)$ is unavoidable with respect to $H(\mathbb C)$ .
Proof Let $f \in M(\mathbb C)$ be given. Then, there exist entire functions $f_{1}$ and $f_{2}$ that have no common zeros such that $f = \frac {f_{1}}{f_{2}}$ . Denote by A the set of zeros of $f_{2}$ , and denote the order of a zero $a \in A$ by $p_{a}$ . We can assume that $A \neq \emptyset $ , because otherwise f is entire and the function $g = f + 1$ avoids f on $\mathbb C$ . Because $f_{1}$ and $f_{2}$ have no common zeros, for every $a \in A$ , there exists $\varepsilon _{a}> 0$ such that $f_{1}(z) \neq 0$ in $D_{a} := \{z: \left |z - a\right | < \varepsilon _{a}\}$ . Hence, for every $a \in A$ , there exists a function $g_{a} \in H(D_{a})$ such that $e^{g_{a}(z)} = f_{1}(z)$ holds for every $z \in D_{a}$ . For $a \in A$ and $z \in D_{a}$ , we have the expansion
According to a classic interpolation result (e.g., [Reference Rudin13, p. 304]), there exists a function $\varphi \in H(\mathbb C)$ that has, at every $a \in A$ , the same power series development up to $(z - a)^{p_{a} - 1}$ as $g_{a}$ . Hence, for every $a \in A$ and $z \in D_{a}$ , we obtain
where $Q_{a}$ has a zero of order $p_{a}$ at the point a. Thus, $e^{\varphi (z)} = f_{1}(z) \, e^{Q_{a}(z)}$ for $a \in A$ and $z \in D_{a}$ , so that the function $f_{1} - e^{\varphi }$ has a zero of order $p_{a}$ at the point a. It follows that the function
is entire, and because
is zero-free, the function g avoids f on $\mathbb C$ .▪
Remark
-
(i) Because the interpolation result we use in the proof also holds for arbitrary domains $D \subset \mathbb C$ , it follows that the result also holds in this case; hence, no $f \in M(D)$ is unavoidable with respect to $H(D)$ . In [Reference Lappan7], it is shown that there exists a continuous function f on $\mathbb D$ that is unavoidable with respect to $H(\mathbb D)$ . Theorem 4 shows that there exists no $f \in M(\mathbb D)$ with such a property.
-
(ii) As stated in the introduction, results from [Reference Hayman and Rubel5, Reference Rubel and Yang12] show that given $f_{1}$ and $f_{2} \in M(\mathbb C)$ , there exists $g \in M(\mathbb C)$ that avoids both $f_{1}$ and $f_{2}$ on $\mathbb C$ . The proof given in [Reference Hayman and Rubel5, Reference Rubel and Yang12] does, however, not directly apply in case that $f_{1} = f_{\infty }$ or $f_{2} = f_{\infty }$ , from which Theorem 4 would immediately follow. Nevertheless, we use similar ideas in our proof of Theorem 4.