Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T09:39:25.919Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 January 2022

Steven Luper
Affiliation:
Trinity University, Texas
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Mortal Objects
Identity and Persistence through Life and Death
, pp. 189 - 200
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2022

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Altshuler, Roman, 2016, “Immortality, Identity, and Desirability,” in Cholbi, Michael, ed., 2016, Immortality and the Philosophy of Death, New York: Rowman & Littlefield .Google Scholar
Aristotle, 1984,Nicomachean Ethics, Categories, Topics, Metaphysics and Parts of Animals,” in Barnes, Jonathan, ed., The Complete Works of Aristotle, Vols. I and II, Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 17291866.Google Scholar
Árnadóttir, Steinvör Thöll, 2010, “Functionalism and Thinking Animals,” Philosophical Studies 147.3: 347354.Google Scholar
Ayers, Michael, 1991, Locke, Vol. 2, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Bailey, Andrew, 2014, “You Needn’t Be Simple,” Philosophical Papers 43.2: 145160.Google Scholar
Balme, David, 1987, “Aristotle’s Use of Division and Differentiae,” in Gotthelf, Allan and Lennox, James G, eds., Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 6989.Google Scholar
Barron, Andrew B., Maleszka, R., Helliwell, P. G., and Robinson, G. E., 2009, “Effects of Cocaine on Honey Bee Dance Behavior,” Journal of Experimental Biology 212: 163168.Google Scholar
Barron, Andrew B., Søvik, Eirik, and Cornish, Jennifer L, 2010, “The Roles of Dopamine and Related Compounds in Reward-Seeking Behavior across Animal Phyla,” Frontiers in Behavioral Neuroscience 4: 163.Google Scholar
Bayne, Tim, 2010, The Unity of Consciousness, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Baker, Lynne Rudder, 2000, Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View, Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Behrendt, Kathy, 2016, “Learning to Be Dead: The Narrative Problem of Mortality,” in Cholbi, 2016, pp. 157172.Google Scholar
Belshaw, Christopher, 2010, “Animals, Identity and Persistence,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89.3: 40419.Google Scholar
Bernstein, Mark, 1998, On Moral Considerability: An Essay On Who Morally Matters. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Blatti, Stephan, 2007, “Animalism, Dicephalus, and Borderline Cases,” Philosophical Psychology 20.5: 595608, DOI: 10.1080/09515080701540867.Google Scholar
Blatti, Stephan, 2012, “A New Argument for Animalism,” Analysis 72.4: 685690.Google Scholar
Bogen, James, 1966, “Identity and Origin,” Analysis 22.5: 160165.Google Scholar
Bortolotti, Lisa and Nagasawa, Yujin, 2009, “Immortality without Boredom,” Ratio 22.3: 261277.Google Scholar
Bradford, Gwen and Keller, Simon, 2016, “Well-Being and Achievement,” Fletcher, Guy, ed., Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Well-Being, London: Routledge, pp. 271–280.Google Scholar
Bradley, Ben, 2009, Well-Being and Death, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bradley, Ben, Feldman, Fred, and Johansson, Jens, eds., 2013, Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Death, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bradley, Ben, 2013, “Asymmetries in Benefiting, Harming and Creating,” The Journal of Ethics 17: 3749.Google Scholar
Broome, John, 1993, “Goodness Is Reducible to Betterness: The Evil of Death Is the Value of Life,” Koslowski, P and Shionoya, Y, eds., The Good and the Economical, Berlin: Springer-Verlag, pp. 7086.Google Scholar
Brown, Curtis, 2016, “Narrow Mental Content,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2016 Edition), Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2016/entries/content-narrow/.Google Scholar
Brueckner, Anthony, 2004, “Strategies for Refuting Closure,” Analysis 64: 333335.Google Scholar
Brueckner, Anthony and Fischer, John, 1986, “Why Is Death Bad?Philosophical Studies 50: 213221.Google Scholar
Buben, Adam, 2016, “Resources for Overcoming the Boredom of Immortality in Fischer and Kierkegaard,” in Cholbi 2016, pp. 205220.Google Scholar
Burley, Mikel, 2009, “Immortality and Meaning,” Philosophy 84.4: 529547.Google Scholar
Camus, Albert, 1955, Myth of Sisyphus, O’Brien, J., trans., London: H. Hamilton.Google Scholar
Campbell, John, 2012, “Cogito Ergo Sum: Christopher Peacocke and John Campbell: II–Lichtenberg and the Cogito,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society cxii.3: 361–378, DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9264.2012.003.Google Scholar
Chittka, Lars and Niven, Larry, 2009, “Are Bigger Brains Better?Current Biology 19: R995R1008.Google Scholar
Cholbi, Michael, ed., 2016, Immortality and the Philosophy of Death, New York: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Cholbi, Michael, 2016, “Immortality and the Exhaustibility of Value,” in Cholbi 2016, pp. 221236.Google Scholar
Cohen, Stewart, 2002, “Basic Knowledge and the Problem of Easy Knowledge,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65.2: 309329.Google Scholar
Cohen, Stewart, 2005, “Why Basic Knowledge is Easy Knowledge,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75.2: 417430.Google Scholar
Dasgupta, Partha, 1995, An Inquiry into Well-Being and Destitution, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald, 1987, “Knowing One’s Own Mind,” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 61: 441458.Google Scholar
DeGrazia, David and Rowan, Andrew, 1991, “Pain, Suffering, and Anxiety in Animals and Humans,” Theoretical Medicine 12.3: 193211.Google Scholar
DeGrazia, David, 2014, “The Nature of Human Death,” in Luper, Steven, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Life and Death, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 80-97.Google Scholar
Descartes, Rene, 1691, “Meditations on First Philosophy,” in Haldane, Elizabeth and Ross, G. R. T., trans., The Philosophical Works of Descartes, Vol. I, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, p. 1911.Google Scholar
Descartes, Rene, 1985, The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, translated by Cottingham, John, Stoothoff, Robert, and Murdock, Dugald, Vol. 1, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dickinson, D. J., Nelson, W. J., and Weis, W. I., 2011, “A Polarized Epithelium Organized by Beta- and Alpha- Catenin Predates Cadherin and Metazoan Origins,” Science 331: 13361339. DOI: 10.1126/science.1199633.Google Scholar
Dretske, Fred, 1970, “Epistemic Operators,” Journal of Philosophy 67: 10071023.Google Scholar
Dretske, Fred, 1971, “Conclusive Reasons,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 49: 122.Google Scholar
Dretske, Fred, 2003, “Skepticism: What Perception Teaches,” in Luper, Steven, 2003, The Skeptics, Hampshire: Ashgate, pp. 105118.Google Scholar
Dummett, Michael, 1973, Frege: Philosophy of Language, London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Dunn, Casey, 2005, “Complex Colony‐Level Organization of the Deep‐Sea Siphonophore Bargmannia elongata (Cnidaria, Hydrozoa) is Directionally Asymmetric and Arises by the Subdivision of Pro‐Buds,” Developmental Dynamics 234.4: 835845. https://doi.org/10.1002/dvdy.20483.Google Scholar
Ekendahl, Karl and Johansson, Jens, 2016, “Epicureanism, Extrinsic Badness, and Prudence,” in Cholbi, Michael, ed., 2016, Immortality and the Philosophy of Death, New York: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 3952.Google Scholar
Elmore, Susan, 2007, “Apoptosis: A Review of Programmed Cell Death,” Toxicologic Pathology 35.4: 495516. https://doi.org/10.1080/01926230701320337.Google Scholar
Epicurus, 1966, “Letter to Menoeceus,” in Saunders, John, ed., Greek and Roman Philosophy after Aristotle, New York: Free Press, pp. 49–52.Google Scholar
Feit, Neil, 2002, “The Time of Death’s Misfortune,” Noûs 36: 359383.Google Scholar
Feit, Neil, 2016, “Comparative Harm, Creation and Death,” Utilitas CJO2015: 128. DOI: 10.1017/S0953820815000308.Google Scholar
Feldman, Fred, 1991, “Some Puzzles About the Evil of Death,” Philosophical Review 100.2: 205227; Reprinted in Fischer, John, ed., The Metaphysics of Death, Stanford: Stanford University Press, pp. 307–326.Google Scholar
Feldman, Fred, 1973, “Sortal Predicates,” Noûs 7: 268282.Google Scholar
Feldman, Fred, 1992, Confrontations with the Reaper, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Feldman, Fred, 2000, “The Termination Thesis,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 24: 98115.Google Scholar
Feldman, Fred, 2004, Pleasure and the Good Life, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fischer, John M., ed., 1993, The Metaphysics of Death, Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Fletcher, Guy, 2016, The Philosophy of Well Being, New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Forbes, Graham, 1980, “Origin and Identity,” Philosophical Studies 37: 353362.Google Scholar
Gamp, Joe, 2020, “‘World’s Longest Creature’ Discovered in Ocean Depths Off Western Australian Coast,” Yahoo News UK, April 16, 2020, www.yahoo.com/news/worlds-longest-creature-discovered-ocean-australian-coast-125549234.html, downloaded May 4, 2020.Google Scholar
Geach, Peter. T, 1967, “Identity,” Review of Metaphysics 21: 312. Reprinted in Logic Matters (Oxford: Blackwell, 1972), pp. 238–47.Google Scholar
Ghiselin, Michael, 1974, “A Radical Solution to the Species Problem,” Systematic Zoology 23, pp. 536–44.Google Scholar
Gibbard, Allan, 1975, “Contingent Identity,” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 4.2: 187221.Google Scholar
Glannon, Walter, 2001, “Persons, Lives, and Posthumous Harms,” Journal of Social Philosophy 32.2, 127142.Google Scholar
Good, Irving John, 1965, “Speculations Concerning the First Ultraintelligent Machine,” in Alt, Franz L. and Rubinoff, Morris, eds., Advances in Computers, Vol. 6. New York: Academic Press, pp. 3188. DOI: 10.1016/S0065-2458(08)60418-0.Google Scholar
Gunnarsson, Logi, 2010, Philosophy of Personal Identity and Multiple Personality, New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Hachmo, Yafit, et al., 2020, “Oxygen Therapy Increases Telomere Length and Decreases Immunosenescence in Isolated Blood Cells : A Prospective Trial,” Aging 12 DOI: 10.18632/aging.202188. Online ahead of print.Google Scholar
Handberg-Thorsager, Mette, Fernández, Enrique, and Saló, Emili, 2008, “Stem Cells and Regeneration in Planarians,Frontiers in Bioscience 13:6374–94. PMID 18508666Google Scholar
Harman, Gilbert and Sherman, Brett, 2004, “Knowledge, Assumptions, Lotteries,” Philosophical Issues 14: 492500.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, John, 2006, Knowledge and Lotteries, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Heathwood, Christopher, 2010, “Welfare,” in Skorupski, John, ed., The Routledge Companion to Ethics, London: Routledge, pp. 645655.Google Scholar
Hershenov, David, 2005, “Do Dead Bodies Pose a Problem for Biological Approaches to Personal Identity?Mind 114: 3159.Google Scholar
Hershenov, David, 2009, “Problems with a Constitution Account of Persons,” Dialogue, 48(2): 291312. DOI: 10.1017/S001221730909026XGoogle Scholar
Heyd, David, 1992, Genethics: Moral Issues in the Creation of People, Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Higashi, Masahiko, Yamamura, Norio, Abe, Takuya, and Burns, Thomas, 1991, “Why Don’t All Termite Species have a Sterile Worker Caste?Proc Biol Sci. 246.1315: 2529. DOI: 10.1098/rspb.1991.0120Google Scholar
Hirsch, Eli, 1982, The Concept of Identity, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hirsch, Fred, 1977, The Social Limits to Growth, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas, 1655, De Corpore, Part II, in Molesworth, William ed., The Collected Works of Thomas Hobbes, London: Routledge/Thoemmes Press, pp. 135136.Google Scholar
Holtug, Nils, 2015, “The Value of Coming into Existence,” in Višak, Tatjana and Garner, Robert, eds., The Ethics of Killing Animals, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 101116.Google Scholar
Hooker, Brad, 2015, “The Elements of Well-being,” Journal of Practical Ethics 3: 1535.Google Scholar
Hull, David, 1976, “Are Species Really Individuals?Systematic Zoology 25: 174191.Google Scholar
Huxley, Aldous, 1932, Brave New World, London: Chatto & Windus.Google Scholar
James, Laurence, 2004, “Achievement and the Meaningfulness of Life,” Philosophical Papers 34: 429–42.Google Scholar
Johansson, Jens, 2010, “Being and Betterness,” Utilitas 22.3: 285302.Google Scholar
Johansson, Jens, 2013, “Past and Future Non-existence,” Journal of Ethics 17: 5164.Google Scholar
Johnston, Mark, 1992, “Constitution is not Identity,” Mind 101: 89105.Google Scholar
Kaczmarek, Łukasz, et al., 2019, “Staying Young and Fit? Ontogenetic and Phylogenetic Consequences of Animal Anhydrobiosis,” Journal of Zoology 309.1: 111 https://doi.org/10.1111/jzo.12677.Google Scholar
Kagan, Shelly, 2015, “An Introduction to Ill-being,” Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics 4: 261288.Google Scholar
Kaufman, Frederik, 1999, “Pre-Vital and Post-Mortem Non-Existence,” American Philosophical Quarterly 36: 119.Google Scholar
Keller, Simon, 2004, “Welfare and the Achievement of Goals,” Philosophical Studies 121: 2741.Google Scholar
Kingma, Elselijn, 2019. “Were You a Part of Your Mother?Mind, Vol. 128, Issue 511. pp. 609646, https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/fzy087.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip, 1984, “Species,” Philosophy of Science 51: 308333.Google Scholar
Klemke, E. D. and Cahn, Stephen, 2008, eds., The Meaning of Life, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul, 1971, “Identity and Necessity,” in Munitz, M., ed., Identity and Individuation, New York: New York University Press, pp. 8394.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul, 1980, Naming and Necessity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kurzweil, Raymond, 2005, The Singularity is Near: When Humans Transcend Biology, New York: Viking Press.Google Scholar
Lamichhaney, Sangeet, et al., 2018, “Rapid Hybrid Speciation in Darwin’s Finches,” Science 12.6372: 224228, DOI: 10.1126/science.aao4593Google Scholar
Landau, Iddo, 2011, “Immorality and the Meaning of Life,” Journal of Value Inquiry 45: 309317, DOI: 10.1007/s10790-011-9293-x.Google Scholar
Langley, Alexander R., et al., 2014, “New Insights into the Maternal to Zygotic Transition,” Development 141: 38343841, DOI: 10.1242/dev.102368.Google Scholar
LaPorte, Joseph. 2009. “On Two Reasons for Denying that Bodies Can Outlast Life,” Mind 118.471: 795801.Google Scholar
Lewis, David, 1973, Counterfactuals, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, David, 1991, Parts of Classes, Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lewis, David, 1976, “Survival and Identity,” in Rorty, A., ed., The Identities of Persons, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1740; Reprinted in Lewis, David, Philosophical Papers, Vol. I, New York: Oxford University Press, 1983, pp. 55–73.Google Scholar
Lewis, David, 1983, “Postscripts to ‘Survival and Identity’,” in David, Lewis, ed., Philosophical Papers, Vol. I, New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 7377.Google Scholar
Lewis, David, 1968, “Counterpart Theory and Quantified Modal Logic,” Journal of Philosophy 65: 113–26; Reprinted in Lewis, David, Philosophical Papers, Vol. I, New York: Oxford University Press, 1983, pp. 26–39.Google Scholar
Lewis, David, 1993, “Many, but Almost One,” in Campbell, Keith, Bacon, John, and Reinhardt, Lloyd, eds., Ontology, Causality, and Mind: Essays on the Philosophy of D. M. Armstrong, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; Reprinted in Lewis, David, Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999, pp. 164–182.Google Scholar
Liao, S. Matthew, 2006, “The Organism View Defended,” Monist 89: 334–50.Google Scholar
Lichtenberg, Georg, 1971, Schriften und Briefe, Sudelbucher II: Carl Hanser Verlag.Google Scholar
Licon, Jimmy, 2012, “Another Argument for Animalism: The Argument from Causal Powers,” Prolegomena: časopis za filozofiju 11.2: 169180.Google Scholar
Lin, Eden, 2017, “Enumeration and Explanation in Theories of Welfare,” Analysis 77: 6573.Google Scholar
Linzey, Andrew, 2009, Why Animal Suffering Matters, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Locke, John, 1975, Nidditch, Peter, ed., Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J.,1996, Subjects of Experience, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lucretius, 1951, On the Nature of the Universe, translated by Latham, R. E., Harmondsworth: Penguin.Google Scholar
Luper, Steven, 1985, “Annihilation,” The Philosophical Quarterly 37.148: 233–52. Reprinted in Fischer 1993: 269–290.Google Scholar
Luper, Steven, 1992, “The Absurdity of Life,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52: 117.Google Scholar
Luper, Steven, 2003, The Skeptics, Hampshire: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Luper, Steven, 2009a, “Review of Ben Bradley,” Well-being and Death (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), in Shields, Christopher, ed., Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews https://ndpr.nd.edu/reviews/well-being-and-death/.Google Scholar
Luper, Steven, 2009b, The Philosophy of Death, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Luper, Steven, 2012a, “Retroactive Harms and Wrongs,” in Feldman, Fred, Bradley, Ben, and Johansson, Jens, eds., 2012, Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Death, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 317336.Google Scholar
Luper, Steven, 2012b, “Exhausting Life,” The Journal of Ethics: An International Philosophical Review 16.3: 121.Google Scholar
Luper, Steven, 2014a, “Persimals,” The Southern Journal of Philosophy, Spindel supplement to volume 52: 140162.Google Scholar
Luper, Steven, 2014b, “Life’s Meaning,” in Cambridge Companion to Life and Death, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 198–212.Google Scholar
Luper, Steven, 2015, “The Existence of the Dead,” in Coady, David, Lippert-Rasmussen, Kasper and Brownlee, Kimberley, eds., Blackwell Companion to Applied Philosophy, New Jersey: Wiley Blackwell, pp. 224–236.Google Scholar
Luper, Steven, 2016a, “Animal Interests,” in Višak, Tatjana and Garner, Robert, eds., The Ethics of Killing Animals, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 86101.Google Scholar
Luper, Steven, 2016b, “Epistemic Closure,” in Zalta, Edward N., ed.,The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2020 edition), Revised and updated in 2007, 2010, and 2016, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/closure-epistemic/Google Scholar
Luper, Steven, 2018, “Never Existing,” Mortality 23.2: 173183.Google Scholar
Mackie, David, 1999, “Personal Identity and Dead People,” Philosophical Studies 95.3: 219242.Google Scholar
Mackie, Penelope, 1994, “Sortal Concepts and Essential Properties,” The Philosophical Quarterly 44.176: 311333.Google Scholar
McMahan, Jeff, 1988, “Death and the Value of Life,” Ethics 99.1: 3261. Reprinted in Fischer, John, ed., The Metaphysics of Death, Stanford: Stanford University Press, pp.233–266. Page references to the reprinted version.Google Scholar
McMahan, Jeff, 2013, “Causing People to Exist and Saving People’s Lives,” The Journal of Ethics 17: 535.Google Scholar
McMahan, Jeff, 2002, The Ethics of Killing, Oxford, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McShea, Daniel W., 2001, “The Hierarchical Structure of Organisms: A Scale and Documentation of a Trend in the Maximum,” Paleobiology 27.2: 405423.Google Scholar
Mayr, Ernst, 1942, Systematics and the Origin of Species from the Viewpoint of a Zoologist, New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Millikan, Ruth Garrett, 2010, “On Knowing the Meaning; With a Coda on Swampman,” Mind 119.473: 4381.Google Scholar
Mills, Eugene, 2008, “The Egg and I: Conception, Identity, and Abortion,” The Philosophical Review 117: 323–48.Google Scholar
Mitton, Jeffry B. and Grant, Michael C., 1996, “Genetic Variation and the Natural History of Quaking Aspen,” BioScience 46 (1): 2531. DOI: 10.2307/1312652Google Scholar
Moore, G. E., 1939, “Proof of an External World,” Proceedings of the British Academy 25: 273300.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E., 1953, “Hume’s Theory Examined,” in Some Main Problems of Philosophy, New York: Humanities Press, 108126.Google Scholar
Morono, Yuki, Ito, Motoo, and Hoshino, Tatsuhiko, et al. 2020, “Aerobic Microbial Life Persists in Oxic Marine Sediment as Old as 101.5 Million Years,” Nat Commun 11: 3626. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41467-020-17330-1.Google Scholar
Mouton, S., Willems, M., Houthoofd, W., Bert, W., and Braeckman, B. P., 2011, “Lack of Metabolic Ageing in the Long-lived Flatworm Schmidtea Polychroa,” Exp Gerontol 46: 755761.Google Scholar
Murray, Thomas, 2011Interests, Identities, and Synthetic Biology,” Hastings Center Report 41.4: 3136.Google Scholar
Mummery, Christine and Roelen, Bernard, 2013, “Cloning Human Embryos,” Nature 498: 174175. https://doi.org/10.1038/498174aGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, 1970 , “Death,” Noûs 4.1: 7380. Reprinted (with notes) in Nagel, Mortal Questions, New York: Cambridge U. Press, 1979, pp. 1–10.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, Friedrich, 1983, Untimely Meditations, Hollingdale, R. J., trans., Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Noonan, Harold, 1998, “Animalism Versus Lockeanism: A Current Controversy,” Philosophical Quarterly, 48: 302318.Google Scholar
Noonan, Harold, 2003, Personal Identity, 2nd ed., London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Notton, David and Stringer, Chris, 2021, “Who Is the Type of Homo Sapiens?” International Commission on Zoological Nomenclature, accessed on September 10, 2020 here: https://web.archive.org/web/20190514111833/http://iczn.org/content/who-type-homo-sapiensGoogle Scholar
Nozick, Robert, 1974, Anarchy, State and Utopia, New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert, 1981, Philosophical Explanations, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Ng, Wei Long, Chua, Chee Kai, and Shen, Yu-Fang, 2019, “Print Me An Organ! Why We Are Not There Yet,” Progress in Polymer Science 97: 101145, DOI:10.1016/j.progpolymsci.2019.101145Google Scholar
Olson, , Eric, T., 1997, The Human Animal: Personal Identity Without Psychology, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Olson, , Eric, T., 2001, “Material Coincidence and the Indiscernibility Problem,” The Philosophical Quarterly 51: 337355.Google Scholar
Olson, , Eric, T., 2007, What Are We? A Study in Personal Ontology, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Olson, , Eric, T., 2013, “The Person and the Corpse,” in Bradley, Ben, Feldman, Fred, and Johansson, Jens, eds., Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Death, Oxford: Oxford University Press , pp. 8096.Google Scholar
Olson, , Eric, T., 2014, “The Metaphysical Implications of Conjoined Twinning,” The Southern Journal of Philosophy 52.S1: 2440.Google Scholar
Olson, , Eric, T., 2015, “Animalism,” in Goncalves, J, ed., Metaphysics of the Self, Bern: Peter Lang, pp. 2140.Google Scholar
Okada, Yô K., 1930, “Transplantationsversuche an Protozoen,” Arch. Protistenk 69: 3964.Google Scholar
Overall, Christine, 2003, Aging, Death, and Human Longevity: A Philosophical Inquiry, Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Parfit, Derek, 1984, Reasons and Persons, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Parfit, Derek, 2012, “We Are Not Human Beings,” Philosophy 87: 528.Google Scholar
Peacocke, Christopher 2012, “Descartes Defended,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 86: 109125.Google Scholar
Perry, Clint J and Barron, Andrew B., 2013, “Neural Mechanisms of Reward in Insects,” Annual Review of Entomology 58: 543562.Google Scholar
Piraino, Stefano, Boero, Ferdinando, Aeschbach, Brigitte, and Schmid, Volker, 1996, “Reversing the Life Cycle: Medusae Transforming into Polyps and Cell Transdifferentiation in Turritopsis Nutricula (Cnidaria, Hydrozoa),” Biological Bulletin 190.3: 302312.Google Scholar
Prange, Stéphane, et al., 2018, “Historical Crossroads in the Conceptual Delineation of Apathy in Parkinson’s Disease,” Brain 141.2: 613619.Google Scholar
Psihoyos, Louie, 1994, Hunting Dinosaurs, New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Purves, Duncan, 2016, “The Harms of Death,” in Cholbi, Michael, ed., 2016, Immortality and the Philosophy of Death, New York: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 6784.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary, 1962, “It Ain’t Necessarily So,” Journal of Philosophy 59.22: 658671.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary, 1975, “The Meaning of ‘Meaning’,” in Gunderson, Keith, ed., Language, Mind and Knowledge, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press; Reprinted in Putnam, Hilary, Mind, Language and Reality, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979, pp. 131–193.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary, 1981, “Brains in a Vat,” in Reason, Truth, and History, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Chapter 1: 121.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O, 1948, “On What There Is,” The Review of Metaphysics 2.5: 2138, Reprinted in Quine 1961, pp. 1–19.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O, 1951, “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,”Philosophical Review 60: 2043.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O, 1961, From a Logical Point of View, 2nd ed., Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Quinn, P., 1997, “The Meaning of Life According to Christianity,” in Klemke, E. D. and Cahn, Stephen, 2008, eds., The Meaning of Life, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 3541.Google Scholar
Quinn, Warren, 1984, “Abortion: Identity and Loss,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 13.1: 2454.Google Scholar
Rice, Christopher, 2013, “Defending the Objective List Theory of Well-being,” Ratio 26: 196211.Google Scholar
Roberts, Melinda, 2003, “Can It Ever Be Better Never to Have Existed At All?Journal of Applied Philosophy 20.2: 159185.Google Scholar
Rosati, Connie, 1995, “Persons, Perspectives, and Full Information Accounts of the Good,” Ethics 105: 296325.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, Jay, 1983, Thinking Clearly About Death, Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Roth, Michael, ed., 1990, Doubting: Contemporary Perspectives on Skepticism, Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Ruf, Thomas, Streicher, Ulrike, Stalder, Gabrielle L., Nadler, Tilo, and Walzer, Chris, 2015, “Hibernation in the Pygmy Slow Loris (Nycticebus pygmaeus): Multiday Torpor in Primates is not Restricted to Madagascar,” Scientific Reports 5: 17392, DOI: 10.1038/SREP17392.Google Scholar
Rumpho, Mary, Pelletreau, Karen, Moustafa, Ahmed, and Bhattacharya, Debashish, 2011, “The Making of a Photosynthetic Animal,” The Journal of Experimental Biology 214: 303311, DOI: 10.1242/jeb.046540.Google Scholar
Sartre, Jean-Paul, 1984, Barnes, Hazel, trans., Being and Nothingless, New York: Washington Square Press.Google Scholar
Sauchelli, Andrea, 2017, “The Animal, the Corpse, and the Remnant Person,” Philosophical Studies 174: 205218, DOI: 10.1007/s11098-016-0677-4.Google Scholar
Scheffler, Samuel,2013, Death and the Afterlife, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schlick, Moritz, 1979, “On the Meaning of Life,” in Mulder, H. L. and van de Velde-Schlick, B. F., eds., Philosophical Papers, Dordrecht: D. Reidel, pp. 112129.Google Scholar
Schopenhauer, Arthur, 1958, The World as Will and Representation, Vols. I and II, E. F. J. Payne, Trans., New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Schopenhauer, Arthur, 1962, “On the Suffering of the World,” in Richard, Taylor, ed., The Will to Live: Selected Writings of Arthur Schopenhauer, New York: Frederick Ungar pp. 215227.Google Scholar
Scudellari, Megan, 2013, “Penetrating the Brain,” The Scientist, www.the-scientist.com/bio-business/penetrating-the-brain–38484.Google Scholar
Sharpe, Kevin, 2015, “Animalism and Person Essentialism,” Metaphysica 16.1: 5372.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, Sidney, 1963, Self-Knowledge and Self-Identity, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, Sidney, 1999, “Self, Body, and Coincidence,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 73: 287306.Google Scholar
Singer, Peter, 1993, Practical Ethics, 2nd ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Silver, David, et al., 2017, “Mastering Chess and Shogi by Self-Play with a General Reinforcement Learning Algorithm,” arXiv 1712.01815 [cs.AI] Ithaca: Cornell University, https://arxiv.org/pdf/1712.01815v1.pdf.Google Scholar
Smuts, Aaron, 2011, “Immortality and Significance,” Philosophy and Literature 35.1: 134149.Google Scholar
Smuts, Aaron, 2012, “Less Good But Not Bad: In Defense of Epicureanism About Death,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 93: 197227.Google Scholar
Snowdon, Paul, 1990, “Persons, Animals, and Ourselves,” in Gill, Christopher, ed., The Person and the Human Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 83107.Google Scholar
Spamer, Earle, 1999, “Know Thyself: Responsible Science and the Lectotype of Homo sapiens Linnaeus,” Proceedings of the Academy of Natural Sciences of Philadelphia 149: 109114.Google Scholar
Stearn, William, 1959, “The Background of Linnaeus’s Contributions to the Nomenclature and Methods of Systematic Biology,” Systematic Zoology 8: 422.Google Scholar
Tadros, W. and Lipshitz, H. D., 2009. “The Maternal-to-Zygotic Transition: A Play in Two Acts,” Development 136: 30333042. DOI: 10.1242/dev.033183.Google Scholar
Technau, Ulrich, von Laue, Christoph Cramer, Rentzsch, Fabian, Luft, Susanne, Hobmayer, Bert, Bode, Hans R., and Holstein, Thomas W., 2000, “Parameters of Self-organization in Hydra Aggregates,” PNAS October 24, 2000 97.22: 1212712131, https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.97.22.12127.Google Scholar
Thomson, J. J. T., 1983, “Parthood and Identity across Time,” Journal of Philosophy 80: 201–20.Google Scholar
Thomasson, Amie, 2007, Ordinary Objects, Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195319910.001.0001Google Scholar
Toner, Patrick, 2008, “Emergent Substance,” Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition 141.3: 281297.Google Scholar
Toner, Patrick, 2011, “Hylemorphic Animalism,” Philosophical Studies 155.1: 6581.Google Scholar
Unger, Peter, 1979, “I Do Not Exist,” in MacDonald, G. F ed., Perception and Identity, London: Macmillan 235–252.Google Scholar
Unger, Peter, 1980, “The Problem of the Many,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5: 411467.Google Scholar
Unger, Peter, 1990, Identity, Consciousness, and Value, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
University of Utah Health Sciences, 2016, “Ancient Viral Invaders in Our DNA Help Fight Today’s Infections,” Science Daily, March 3, 2016. www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2016/03/160303145539.htm.Google Scholar
van Inwagen, Peter, 1981, “The Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts,”Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 62: 123137.Google Scholar
van Inwagen, Peter, 1990, Material Beings, Cornell: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
van Inwagen, Peter, 2008, “Quine’s 1946 Lecture on Nominalism,” in Zimmerman, Dean, ed., Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Vol. 4, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 125142.Google Scholar
van Inwagen, Peter, 2019, “Against Analytic Existence Entailments,” in Cumpa, Javier and Brewer, Bill, eds., The Nature of Ordinary Objects, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 173197. DOI: 10.1017/978126612897.009Google Scholar
Varner, Gary, 2012, Personhood, Ethics, and Animal Cognition, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Velasco, Silvia, Kedaigle, Amanda, Simmons, Sean, et al., 2019, “Individual Brain Organoids Reproducibly Form Cell Diversity of the Human Cerebral Cortex,” Nature 570: 523527. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41586-019-1289-xGoogle Scholar
Vogel, Jonathan, 1990, “Are There Counterexamples to the Closure Principle?” in Roth, M. and Ross, G., eds., Doubting: Contemporary Perspectives on Skepticism, Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Volk, Thomas, 2002, “The Humongous Fungus – Ten Years Later,” Inoculum 53.2: 48.Google Scholar
Warren, James, 2001, “Lucretius, Symmetry Arguments, and Fearing Death,” Phronesis 46: 466491.Google Scholar
Warwick, Kevin, 2004, I, Cyborg, Chicago: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
Wiggins, David, 1967, Identity and Spatio-Temporal Continuity, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wiggins, David, 1968, “On Being in the Same Place at the Same Time,” Philosophical Review, 77.1: 9095.Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard, 1993, “The Makropulos Case: Reflections on the Tedium of Immortality,” Reprinted in Fischer 1993, pp. 73–92, and in Williams, B., ed., Problems of the Self, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 82100.Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard, 1970, “The Self and the Future,” Philosophical Review 79.2: 161180.Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard, 1979, “Moral Luck,” in Moral Luck, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 2039.Google Scholar
Williamson, Timothy, 2000, Knowledge and Its Limits, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wolf, Susan, 1997, “Happiness and Meaning: Two Aspects of the Good Life,”Social Philosophy and Policy, 14: 207225.Google Scholar
Woodard, Christopher, 2013, “Classifying Theories of Welfare,” Philosophical Studies 165.3: 787803.Google Scholar
Xu, Fei, 2007, “From Lot’s Wife to a Pillar of Salt: Evidence that Physical Object is a Sortal Concept,” Mind and Language 12.3: 365392.Google Scholar
Yang, Eric, 2015, “Unrestricted Animalism and the Too Many Candidates Problem,Philosophical Studies 172.3: 635652.Google Scholar
Yashina, Svetlana, Gubin, Stanislav, Maksimovich, Stanislav, Yashina, Alexandra, Gakhova, Edith, and Gilichinsky, David, 2012, “Regeneration of Whole Fertile Plants from 30,000-y-old Fruit Tissue Buried in Siberian Permafrost,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 109.10: 40084013, DOI: 10.1073/pnas.1118386109Google Scholar
Zuccaro, Michael, et al., 2020, “Allele-Specific Chromosome Removal after Cas9 Cleavage in Human Embryos,” Cell, published online, www.cell.com/cell/fulltext/S0092-8674(20)31389-1.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • Steven Luper, Trinity University, Texas
  • Book: Mortal Objects
  • Online publication: 27 January 2022
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108981316.013
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • Steven Luper, Trinity University, Texas
  • Book: Mortal Objects
  • Online publication: 27 January 2022
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108981316.013
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • Steven Luper, Trinity University, Texas
  • Book: Mortal Objects
  • Online publication: 27 January 2022
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108981316.013
Available formats
×