Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-lnqnp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-29T10:07:08.492Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter 23 - Animals, the Environment, and Global Health

from Section 4 - Environmental/Ecological Considerations and Planetary Health

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 February 2021

Solomon Benatar
Affiliation:
Emeritus Professor of Medicine, University of Cape Town
Gillian Brock
Affiliation:
Professor of Philosophy, University of Auckland
Get access

Summary

When people talk about global health and the ethics thereof, they almost invariably mean global human health. This is not because it is impossible to have more expansive notions of global health that include other species. Instead, it is because most people who are concerned about global health, like most of those who are concerned about local health, are either not concerned at all or are much less concerned with the health of other species. Thus, global health ethics, although expanding the reach of health ethics geographically, has not extended moral concern to other species within that global space.

Type
Chapter
Information
Global Health
Ethical Challenges
, pp. 304 - 315
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Benatar, D. (2005). Sexist language: alternatives to the alternatives. Public Affairs Quarterly 19, 19.Google Scholar
Benatar, D. (2006). Better Never to Have Been: The Harm of Coming Into Existence. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benatar, D. (2007). The chickens come home to roost. American Journal of Public Health 97, 15451546.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Boyd, W. (2001). Making meat: science, technology and American poultry production. Technology and Culture 42, 631664.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, A. (1990). Justice as reciprocity versus subject-centered justice. Philosophy and Public Affairs 19, 227252.Google Scholar
Caney, S. (2009). Climate change and the future: discounting for time, wealth and risk. Journal of Social Philosophy 40, 163186.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DeGrazia, D. (1996). Taking Animals Seriously. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Feinberg, J. (1984). Harm to Others. New York, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Feinberg, J. (1992). Wrongful life and the counterfactual element in harming, in Freedom and Fulfilment. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, pp. 336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gao, F., Bailes, E., Robertson, D. L., et al. (1999). Origin of HIV-1 in the chimpanzee Pan troglodytes troglodytes. Nature 397, 436441.Google Scholar
Glover, J. (1975). It makes no difference whether or not I do it. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume XLIX, 171190.Google Scholar
Gorman, J. (2020). Significance of pangolin viruses in human pandemic remains murky. New York Times, March 30. Available at www.nytimes.com/2020/03/26/science/pangolin-coronavirus.html (accessed April 22, 2020).Google Scholar
Guan, Y., Zheng, B. J., He, Y. Q., et al. (2003). Isolation and characterization of viruses related to the SARS coronavirus from animals in Southern China. Science 302, 276278.Google Scholar
Houghton, J. T., Jenkins, G. J, & Ephraums, J. J. (eds.) (1990). Climate Change: The IPCC Scientific Assessment. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Matheny, G. (2002). Expected utility, contributory causation, and vegetarianism. Journal of Applied Philosophy 19, 293297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMichael, A. J. (1993). Planetary Overload: Global Environmental Change and the Health of the Human Species. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
McMichael, A. (2001). Human Frontiers, Environments and Disease. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Osterholm, M. T. (2005). Preparing for the next pandemic. New England Journal of Medicine 352, 18391852.Google Scholar
Pachauri, R. K., & Reisinger, A. (eds.) (2007). Summary for policymakers, in Climate Change 2007: Synthesis Report. A Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. Geneva: IPCC, pp. 122.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and Persons. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Regan, T. (1983). The Case for Animal Rights. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Scott, M. R., Will, R. G., Ironside, J., et al. (1999). Compelling transgenetic evidence for transmission of bovine spongiform encephalopathy prions to humans. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science USA 96, 1513715142.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Shafer-Landau, R. (1994). Vegetarianism, causation and ethical theory. Public Affairs Quarterly 8, 85100.Google Scholar
Sharp, P., Bailes, E., Chaudhuri, R. R., et al. (2001). The origins of acquired immune deficiency syndrome viruses: where and when? Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B 356, 867876.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Singer, P. (1990). Animal Liberation, 2nd ed. New York: Avon Books.Google Scholar
Sinnott-Amstrong, W. (2005). It’s not my fault: global warming and individual moral obligations, in Sinnott-Armstrong, W., & Howarth, R. B. (eds.), Perspectives on Climate Change: Science, Economics, Politics and Ethics, Advances in the Economics of Environmental Resources, vol. 5. Amsterdam: Elsevier, pp. 285307.Google Scholar
Weber, J., & Alcorn, K. (2000). Origins of HIV and the AIDS epidemic. Medscape General Medicine 2, 16.Google Scholar
Webster, R. G. (2004). Wet markets: a continuing source of severe acute respiratory syndrome and influenza. Lancet 365, 234236.Google Scholar
Will, R. G., Ironside, J. W., Zeidler, M., et al. (1996). A new variant of Creutzfeldt-Jakob disease in the UK. Lancet 347, 921925.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Zhang, L., Shen, F-M., & Lin, Z. (2020). Origin and evolution of 2019 novel coronavirus. Clinical Infectious Diseases 71, 882–883.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×