Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-g7gxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-08T06:32:45.231Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

3 - Meritocratic and civic dignity in Greco-Roman antiquity

from Part I - Origins of the concept in European history

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 March 2015

Josiah Ober
Affiliation:
Stanford University
Marcus Düwell
Affiliation:
Universiteit Utrecht, The Netherlands
Jens Braarvig
Affiliation:
Universitetet i Oslo
Roger Brownsword
Affiliation:
King's College London
Dietmar Mieth
Affiliation:
Eberhard-Karls-Universität Tübingen, Germany
Get access

Summary

Jeremy Waldron (2012) has pointed out conceptual similarities between the Kantian conception of universal human dignity as intrinsic and rights-generating, and an older conception of dignity as high standing. Waldron suggests that human dignity generalizes to all humanity the high standing formerly reserved for a privileged few. This chapter suggests that our understanding of dignity would benefit from attention to an intermediate stage: civic dignity, equal high standing among citizens, as it was practiced in classical Athens. Attending to how civic dignity was protected by coordinated citizen action in Athens reminds us that individuals are secure in their dignity only when others are willing and able to defend it. This chapter distinguishes rights-based human dignity from two predecessor forms in the ancient Greco-Roman world: meritocratic and civic dignity. Ancient conceptions of dignity must be understood in light of three assumptions, common to Greek and Roman ethical thought. First, the fundamental question of ethics is what it is for a life to go well. Second, because humans are social beings, as a practical matter ethics is inseparable from politics. Third, we understand politics better when we attend to history.

Dignity as non-humiliation and non-infantilization

For the Greeks and Romans, living with dignity meant, figuratively and literally, holding one's head up in the company of others and being properly acknowledged by them. This entails having one's claims recognized by others, having their respect, having some measure of control over one's life, having a say in decisions and having responsibility for one's choices. Like liberty, which has been variously defined by contemporary theorists as ‘non-interference’ (Berlin 1969) or ‘non-domination’ (Skinner 1998; Pettit 1997), Greco-Roman conceptions of dignity may best be expressed by what they stand against: dignity can be defined as non-humiliation and non-infantilization. We suffer indignity – humiliation and/or infantilization – when our public presence goes unacknowledged, when we cringe before the powerful, when we are unduly subject to the paternalistic will of others and when we are denied the opportunity to employ our reason and voice in making choices that affect us.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Cambridge Handbook of Human Dignity
Interdisciplinary Perspectives
, pp. 53 - 63
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Balot, R. K. 2004. ‘Courage in the Democratic Polis’, Classical Quarterly 54: 406–23Google Scholar
Berlin, I. 1969. Four Essays on Liberty. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Demosthenes, . 1990. Demosthenes, Against Meidias: Oration 21, ed. and trans. MacDowell, D. M.. Oxford, New York: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Domingo Gygax, M. Forthcoming. Benefaction and Rewards in the Ancient Greek City: The Origins of Euergetism. Cambridge University PressCrossRef
Fisher, N. R. E. 1992. Hybris: A Study in the Values of Honour and Shame in Ancient Greece. Warminster: Aris & PhillipsGoogle Scholar
Martin, R. P. 1989. The Language of Heroes: Speech and Performance in the Iliad. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University PressGoogle Scholar
Millett, P. C. 1989. ‘Patronage and Its Avoidance in Classical Athens’, in Wallace-Hadrill, A. (ed.), Patronage in Ancient Society. London: Routledge, 15–48Google Scholar
Nagy, G. 1979. The Best of the Achaeans: Concepts of the Hero in Archaic Greek poetry. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University PressGoogle Scholar
Ober, J. 1989. Mass and Elite in Democratic Athens: Rhetoric, Ideology, and the Power of the People. Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Ober, J. 2007. ‘“I Besieged That Man”: Democracy's Revolutionary Start’, in Raaflaub, K., Ober, J. and Wallace, R. W. (eds.), The Origins of Democracy in Ancient Greece. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 83–104CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ober, J. 2008. Democracy and Knowledge: Innovation and Learning in Classical Athens. Princeton University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ober, J. 2012. ‘Democracy's Dignity’, American Political Science Review 106(4): 827–46CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, P. 1997. Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government. Oxford, New York: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Skinner, Q. 1998. Liberty Before Liberalism. Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Waldron, J. 2012. Dignity, Rank, and Rights. Oxford University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wallace-Hadrill, A. (ed.). 1989. Patronage in Ancient Society. London: Routledge
Weingast, B. R. 1997. ‘The Political Foundations of Democracy and the Rule of Law’, American Political Science Review 91: 245–63CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whitehead, D. 1983. ‘Competitive Outlay and Community Profit: Philotimia in Democratic Athens’, Classica et Mediaevalia 34: 55–74Google Scholar
Whitehead, D. 1993. ‘Cardinal Virtues: The Language of Public Approbation in Democratic Athens’, Classica et Mediaevalia 44: 37–75Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×