Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T18:15:55.750Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

17 - Social-Practice Legal Positivism and the Normativity Thesis

from Part IV - Main Tenets

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 January 2021

Torben Spaak
Affiliation:
Stockholms Universitet
Patricia Mindus
Affiliation:
Uppsala Universitet, Sweden
Get access

Summary

Bertea considers two ways of understanding the social thesis, along the lines of either legal conventionalism or the conception of law as a shared activity, arguing that on neither interpretation of the social thesis can legal positivism account for the necessary normativity of law, that is, for the necessary capacity of law to impose (genuine) obligations and confer (genuine) rights on both officials and citizens. He points out that there are fundamentally two ways in which legal positivists conceptualise legal obligation – either as a genuine requirement set forth in the law or as a perspectival requirement – and that on the former conceptualisation, legal obligations will bind only those who are committed to the legal enterprise, that is, the officials, and that on the latter, they will bind only those who adopt the standpoint of the legal system itself. Further, he objects that on the former conceptualisation, legal positivism fails to account for legal obligations that apply to the citizens, and that on the latter interpretation, it turns out that law might not be necessarily normative in the first place.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bertea, S. 2019. A Theory of Legal Obligation. Cambridge University Press: 74103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bix, B. 2005. ‘Legal Positivism’. In Golding, M. and Edmundson, W. (eds.). The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Blackwell: 2949.Google Scholar
Bratman, M. 2002. ‘Shapiro on Legal Positivism and Jointly Intentional Activity’. Legal Theory 8(4): 511–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coleman, J. 2001a. ‘Incorporationism, Conventionality, and the Practical Difference Thesis’. In Coleman, J.. Hart’s Postscript. Oxford University Press: 99147.Google Scholar
Coleman, J. 2001b. The Practice of Principle. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Coleman, J. and Leiter, B. 1996. ‘Legal Positivism’. In Patterson, D. (ed.). A Companion to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Blackwell: 241–60.Google Scholar
Den Hartog, G. 2002. Mutual Expectations. Kluwer.Google Scholar
Gardner, J. 2001. ‘Legal Positivism: 5½ Myths’. American Journal of Jurisprudence 46: 199227.Google Scholar
Green, L. 1983. ‘Law, Co-ordination and the Common Good’. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 3: 299324.Google Scholar
Green, L. 1985. ‘Authority and Convention’. Philosophical Quarterly 35: 329–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, L. 1988. The Authority of the State. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Green, L. 1999Positivism and Conventionalism’. Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 12: 3552.Google Scholar
Green, L. 2018. ‘Legal Positivism’. In Zalta, E. N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/legal-positivism/.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. [1961]1994. The Concept of Law. 2nd ed. With a Postscript. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hershovitz, S. 2015. ‘The End of Jurisprudence’. The Yale law Journal 124(4): 11601204.Google Scholar
Himma, K. E. 2004. ‘Inclusive legal Positivism’. In Coleman, J. and Shapiro, S. (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law. Oxford University Press: 126–65.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. 1934. ‘The Pure Theory of Law’. The Law Quarterly Review 50: 474–98.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. 1945. General Theory of Law and State. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. 1967. Pure Theory of Law. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Kutz, C. 2001. ‘The Judicial Community’. Philosophical Issues 11: 442–69.Google Scholar
Lagerspetz, E. 1995. The Opposite Mirror. Kluwer.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2001. Positive Law and Objective Values. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2006. ‘How Law Is Like Chess’. Legal Theory 12: 347–71.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2007. ‘Deep Conventions’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74: 586610.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2009. Social Conventions: From Language to Law. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2011. Philosophy of Law. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Perry, S. 2009. ‘Beyond the Distinction between Positivism and Non-positivism’. Ratio Juris 22: 311–25.Google Scholar
Postema, G. 1982. ‘Coordination and Convention at the Foundations of Law’. Journal of Legal Studies 11: 165203.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Postema, G. 1987. ‘The Normativity of Law’. In Gavison, R. (ed.). Issues in Contemporary Legal Philosophy. Oxford University Press: 81104.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1979. The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1994. Ethics in the Public Domain: Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1999. Engaging Reason. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 2009. Between Authority and Interpretation. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sanchez Brigido, R. 2009. ‘Collective Intentional Activities and the Law’. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 29: 309–24.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. 2002. ‘Law, Plans, and Practical Reason’, Legal Theory 8: 387441.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. 2011. Legality. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Spaak, T. 2018. ‘Legal Positivism, Conventionalism, and the Normativity of Law’. Jurisprudence 9: 126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×