Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-18T22:08:21.108Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The German historical school on monetary calculation and the feasibility of socialism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 May 2023

Eduard Braun*
Affiliation:
Institute of Management and Economics, Clausthal University of Technology, Julius-Albert Straße 2, 38678 Clausthal-Zellerfeld, Germany
*
Corresponding author. Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Several scholars anticipated Ludwig von Mises's calculation argument against socialism. The present paper summarises the contributions by the members of the German Historical School of Economics who preceded Mises and provides several examples of anticipation that have not been discussed in the literature. Furthermore, the paper explains why it is not a coincidence that members of the Historical School claimed as early as the nineteenth century that socialism was unfeasible due to calculation and knowledge problems. In their attempts to understand historically specific features of capitalism, they developed an approach to capital that involved the institutions of private property, money, the market, the enterprise, and monetary calculation. Starting from this institutional approach to capital and capitalism, it was only a small step to the question of what it means for socialist systems that those institutions are lacking.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Millennium Economics Ltd.

Introduction

Almost everybody knows the most popular argument against socialism: Although socialism sounds great in theory, it cannot work in practice because it presupposes an unrealistic concept of man. Socialists do not realise, the argument runs, that labourers, managers, and bureaucrats are no angels. They need proper incentives in order to give their best. Yet socialism does not provide sufficient incentives because it abolishes private property and the possibility of making profits and earning performance-based wages. Accordingly, the population in socialist countries either becomes lazy or goes its own way and circumvents the central plan as much as possible, thus provoking totalitarian measures by the government.

This argument against socialism is not historically specific. It assumes a certain universal nature of man and claims that all laws and regulations – or economic systems, for that matter – that ignore this universal nature must perform miserably. Private property, in this argument, must be understood as a part of our natural condition, not as a social or legal institution (Hodgson, Reference Hodgson2015). Not only socialism but also the market economy becomes inefficient insofar as it ignores these natural conditions, as in the private production of public goods.

Ludwig von Mises (Reference Mises1920) brought forward a more powerful argument against socialism. He did not merely point out certain anthropological problems of socialism. In fact, he attempted to demonstrate the impossibility of rational economic calculation under socialism, that is, the impossibility of a calculation that helps to place the available means to the service of the chosen ends (Mises, Reference Mises1920: 16). Interestingly, Mises's argument is based much more strongly on historically specific features of capitalism. The reason why socialism is impossible, according to Mises, is that it does not have the (capitalistic) institutions of private property, money, a market for the means of production, and enterprises performing monetary calculation. A central planning board is not able to evaluate and compare different production processes because without these institutions, it is impossible to reduce the myriad of goods and services in modern societies to a common denominator.

It is well known that some elements of Mises's arguments were anticipated by other economists. Mises (Reference Mises1966: 701) himself mentions that Hermann Heinrich Gossen, Albert Schäffle, Vilfredo Pareto, Nikolaas G. Pierson, and Enrico Barone ‘touched upon the problem’. In his overview of the prehistory of Mises's argument, Ebeling (Reference Ebeling and Ebeling2003) adds the contributions of Paul Leroy Beaulieu, William Graham, Victor Cathrein, and Benedict Elder to this list. However, it escapes most observers that several members of the German Historical School of Economics anticipated Mises as well and criticised socialism along the same lines as he would in 1920. Mises is certainly partly responsible for the neglect of the Historical School on this matter. Although Mises (Reference Mises1966: 701) acknowledges that Schäffle, a member of the Historical School (Hodgson, Reference Hodgson and Vint2010: 297), touched upon the problem, a few lines later he considers the Historical School to be not in any way interested in demonstrating the impossibility of socialism.

Several recent publications have come to a different conclusion. Hodgson (Reference Hodgson and Vint2010) discusses Schäffle's argument against socialism and, while doing so, turns against Mises's claim that the Historical School was antieconomic or antitheoretical. Braun (Reference Braun2016) provides additional evidence for the quality of Schäffle's argument and demonstrates that two more members of the Historical School, Hildebrand ([Reference Hildebrand1848] 1922) and Stein (Reference Stein1887), criticised socialist plans on the grounds that the central planning board would not be able to calculate rationally. Braun and Wollboldt (Reference Braun and Wollboldt2022) present Stahl (Reference Stahl1863), a member of the Historical School of Law, as another predecessor of Mises: he dedicated half a book chapter to demonstrating that socialism is unfeasible.

The first purpose of the present paper is to summarise the known contributions of the Historical School to the impossibility argument against socialism and to add further examples. Knies (Reference Knies1885) was definitively aware of the problem and tried to cope with it, although with less clarity than others. Starting from the works of Albert Schäffle, the agronomist Calberla (Reference Calberla1877) also came to the conclusion that socialism was impossible due to calculation problems. The fact that these authors discovered the calculation problems of socialism long before there was any notable real-world example of socialism to consider makes their anticipation even more admirable.

Second, the present paper delves deeper into the question why several members of the Historical School anticipated Mises. One element of the answer seems to be that their evolutionary perspective led some of them to doubt the human faculty to create new laws from scratch. The limits of human knowledge, implied in this view, lend themselves to a critique of central planning. Furthermore, it appears that the Historical School's preoccupation with the historically specific institutions of capitalism led them to a better understanding of the institutional preconditions of the nationwide or even worldwide division of labour. In its institutional approach to the theory of capital (Braun, Reference Braun2017; Hodgson, Reference Hodgson2014), the Historical School dealt with the specific problems that arise in a society where profit-oriented, privately owned enterprises produce goods and services more or less for the single purpose of making profits on the market (see, e.g., Sombart Reference Sombart1919; Reference Sombart1927). It even appears that this institutional approach to capital is indirectly the basis for Mises's (Reference Mises1920) argument. After all, Menger (Reference Menger1888) had adopted this approach to capital from the Historical School, and Mises (Reference Mises1932: 123), for his part, followed Menger.

Third, the paper briefly indicates why it was a mistake by the economics profession to abandon the approach to capital developed by the Historical School and adopted by Menger and Mises. As this approach is concerned with the actual role of capital and monetary calculation in organising the societal production process, it is able to serve as a basis for analysing and comparing different institutional arrangements. Next to the analysis of socialism, foreshadowed by the German Historical School itself, it has great potential to advance the study of reforms that tamper with the institutions of monetary calculation.

In the first two sections, the paper ponders the question of why so many members of the Historical School were able to anticipate Mises's critique of socialism. Their method led some of them to doubt whether humans had enough knowledge to create new laws or constitutions. Although they mainly targeted classical liberalism, some of them turned the argument against socialism (‘The historical school on the knowledge problem’ section). Further, it appears that it was their interest in understanding capitalistic institutions and the role they play in organising the production process that led Historical School economists to consider what happens when these institutions are missing – as in socialism. Their institutional theory of capital is designed to explain the peculiarities of the capitalistic production process (‘The institutional theory of capital’ section). ‘The components of Mises's argument against the possibility of economic calculation under socialism’ section reiterates Mises's original argument against socialism briefly and dissects it into its different components. The following sections discuss several members of the Historical School and demonstrate how much they anticipated Mises. These sections are arranged more or less chronologically, although it is difficult to be precise in this regard as the lifespans of the respective authors overlapped and the relevant books sometimes went through several editions and were revised in this process. ‘Friedrich Julius Stahl on the impossibility of socialism’ section starts with Friedrich Julius Stahl, who asserted the unfeasibility of socialism already in 1846. ‘Bruno Hildebrand on economic calculation under socialism’ and ‘Karl Knies on the role of money in capitalism and socialism’ sections deal with two of the three founders of the Historical School of Economics, Bruno Hildebrand and Karl Knies. Knies's position on the impossibility of socialism has, to the best of my knowledge, never been discussed. Wilhelm Roscher, the third founder, is not covered in this paper. Roscher (Reference Roscher1864: 140 ff.) also criticised socialism, claiming that the ‘central direction of all production and consumption’ would be a ‘despotism’ (151) never seen before.Footnote 1 However, Roscher did not deal with calculation or knowledge problems but with the incentive problem mentioned at the outset of this introduction. ‘Albert Schäffle on economic calculation under socialism and capitalism’ section is dedicated to Albert Schäffle. He is the author who comes closest to Mises in terms of the quality and completeness of the argument. ‘Further members of the German Historical School on the impossibility of socialism’ section presents the previously unrecognised contribution of Georg Calberla and some other, minor contributions by Historical School economists. Finally, ‘The continuing importance of the institutional theory of capital’ section explains why the institutional theory of capital is not only of historical importance as a helpful tool in the debates on socialism. Its current significance is indicated in the face of recent reforms of the institutions of monetary calculation and corporate governance.

The historical school on the knowledge problem

Mises belonged to the Austrian School of Economics. The Austrian School was opposed to the German Historical School of Economics in the famous Methodenstreit. These schools clearly were antagonists, and Mises (Reference Mises1966) wrote that the Historical School had no interest whatsoever in even considering the impossibility of economic calculation under socialism. Mises (701) stated that it is not puzzling that the ‘detractors of economics’ – that is, the historical and institutionalist schools – ‘failed to recognize the problem’. They ‘disparage economics […] in the interest of their interventionist or socialist propaganda’. We must count ourselves lucky that these schools ‘have not succeeded in suppressing the study of economics entirely’.

Why, then, did several members of the Historical School anticipate large parts of Mises's famous argument against the possibility of rational economic calculation under socialism? For want of any historical source on this matter, it is impossible to answer this question precisely. What I do in this and the following section, therefore, is reflect on the relationship between Mises's argument and the work of the Historical School and highlight their overlap.

If we paid attention only to the statements by the Historical School on social philosophy, it would be difficult to find common ground with the Austrian School. When the German Historical Schools emerged at the turn of the nineteenth century, they turned against the attempts by classical liberalism and, more generally, the Enlightenment to construct human societies based on human reason. Friedrich Carl von Savigny founded the Historical School of Law as a direct reaction to the intention of progressive and classical liberal scholars who wanted to create a new civil law for all German countries more or less from scratch. Savigny (Reference Savigny and Hattenhauer1814: 164–65), as a conservative, argued that it is an illusion to think that humanity is able to step outside history and to invent new laws without a deep understanding of customs and the historical development that led to the present state of affairs. The entire history of the nation constitutes the material of law. Law is not arbitrary but emanates from the innermost nature of the nation and its history. Therefore, ‘[e]very age must judiciously intend to see through this material that is given with inner necessity, to rejuvenate it and to keep it alive’ (Savigny, Reference Savigny and Hattenhauer1815: 264).

The Historical School of Economics adopted this approach and tried to understand present-day economic phenomena by studying their role and place in history. For Savigny, the main target was the idea that humans are able to discover and understand natural rights based on their reason alone and without consulting history. In a parallel effort, the Historical School of Economics tended to criticise classical economists for their unhistorical treatment of human nature and economic laws and for their belief that human societies would flourish based on individual liberty alone – that is, without any rules or institutions except for private property. Karl Knies, one of the founders of the Historical School of Economics, expressed his concerns about classical economics as follows:

For Adam Smith himself, the devotion to theoretical absolutism was a natural consequence, first, of the then generally accepted conception of nations in which he saw completely similar, summary aggregates of general, human individuals who just happen to be separated by national borders and live under different systems of law; but probably even more, second, of the fact that the fundamental area of his research was human labour, an area where the relative, the historical, and the concrete tend to evade the observer and where a universal foundation of absolute results seems to be given. (Knies, Reference Knies1885: 27, emphasis in original)

Although the Historical School mainly targeted classical liberalism, it appears that its critical approach toward the creation of laws from scratch can easily be transferred to a critique of socialism. In any case, that is how several members of the Austrian School used this argument.

It is well known that Menger had praised Savigny for understanding law as a more or less unreflective product of a higher wisdom rather than as something derived from the planned action of a legislative body (Kolev and Dekker, Reference Kolev and Dekker2023). According to Roos (Reference Roos, Birner and Zijp1994: 295), much of what Hayek had to say about ‘embodied’ knowledge in law and society can also be traced back to the Historical School. Hayek knew Savigny's work, occasionally citing him approvingly. Hayek's (Reference Hayek2014: 46) view on the origin of rules is clearly reminiscent of Savigny:

[N]o single human intelligence is capable of inventing the most appropriate abstract rules because those rules which have evolved in the process of growth of society embody the experience of many more trials and errors than any individual mind could acquire.

Witt (Reference Witt1997: 47) points out that this argument, typical of Hayek since the late 1930s, is not consistent with the Austrian method. The younger Hayek himself had been keen to make deductions, in a logically consistent way, based on the premises of a pure equilibrium theory where there is no lack of knowledge at all. Raico (Reference Raico1995: sect. 7) presumes that both Menger and the older Hayek leaned toward spontaneous-order explanations for ideological reasons, that is, because they served to validate their liberal view of the social order. Tellingly, Hayek usually criticised socialism and interventionism for their pretence of knowledge but tended to ignore that Savigny, Knies, and others had used similar arguments against classical liberalism as well.

It is interesting to note that the Historical School of Economics itself did not attack only classical liberalism on the grounds that it tended to ignore history, customs, and institutions. Some of its members attacked socialism for the same reason. Bruno Hildebrand, for example, another founder of the Historical School of Economics, criticised socialists exactly because they overestimated the power of reason and ignored history:

They [socialists] break with the past and want to transform the rich, free, and diverse life of humanity into a dead, uniform mechanism. They approach the given world as if the first men were born a second ago and the first form of communal life should be created for them by reason. […] [T]hey do not see that every new creation that humanity passes through in its history can only be spawned from the old, given elements and draw its sustenance from the fluids of the available soil. (Hildebrand [Reference Hildebrand1848] 1922: 214)

Below we will see that several members of the Historical School, including Hildebrand himself, extended this rather general point and questioned the possibility of centrally planning the economy.

The institutional theory of capital

Given that the Historical School influenced the Austrian School on the issue of the limit of human knowledge, it does not appear to be a coincidence that it also anticipated the Austrian argument against the possibility of socialism. Yet, the relationship between the approach of the Historical School and the Austrian argument against socialism is even closer. This is particularly true for Mises's original version of the argument.

Not many economists know that Mises deviated from his fellow Austrians when it came to his treatment of capital and the institutions that underlie it in capitalistic societies (Braun et al., Reference Braun, Lewin and Cachanosky2016). The standard Austrian theory of capital concentrates on the physical activities of roundabout production processes and defines capital as produced means of production – i.e., as physical factors of production. In this sense, capital is not specific to a certain economic system or historical period but a universal phenomenon – a phenomenon that all humans can understand and discuss based on their reason and is independent of historical circumstances (Braun, Reference Braun2017).

Mises deviated from this approach (Lewin and Cachanosky, Reference Lewin and Cachanosky2018: 424). Following a rather unknown and often misinterpreted essay by Menger (Reference Menger1888; see Braun Reference Braun2015a for a summary and Braun Reference Braun2020 for a partial translation), Mises, when he talked about capital, concerned himself with the organisation of capitalism. He argued explicitly that capital is not a universal production factor but a historically specific concept. Mises (Reference Mises1966: 264) stated that the ‘concept of capital cannot be separated from the context of monetary calculation and from the social structure of a market economy.’ Mises (Reference Mises1932: 123) defined it as the tangible and intangible properties of business enterprises, whether they consist of money or are only expressed in money terms.

It is highly probable that Menger (Reference Menger1888) had adopted his view of capital from Richard Hildebrand, a member of the Historical School and the son of Bruno Hildebrand (Braun, Reference Braun, Bylund and Howden2015b: 78 ff.). This notion of capital revolves around the capitalistic institutions of private property, money, markets, the capitalistic enterprise, and financial accounting. The Historical and Institutional Schools claimed, as Hodgson (Reference Hodgson2014: 1,070) writes, that capital is historically specific to capitalism and must be analysed as such because only in this way can important features of this economic system be grasped.

A mature discussion of capital and its role in capitalism by a member of the Historical School can be found in Werner Sombart's writings. Sombart rejected the standard Austrian theory of capital. Böhm-Bawerk's famous books on capital and interest ‘fall outside the area of what I consider to be fruitful economic theory’ (Sombart, Reference Sombart1927: 128). It is ‘ridiculous’ to call a child that is picking berries and placing them in a basket a capitalist who is producing capitalistically (Sombart, Reference Sombart1927: 134). Capital is not a universal phenomenon; it is specific to capitalism, where capital-based enterprises organise the production process rationally by means of calculation and accounting (Sombart, Reference Sombart1927: 130). Sombart (Reference Sombart1927: 129) was explicit on this point:

Capital is a historical-economic term, i.e., a term that evolved within the context of a certain economic system – the capitalistic one. It is misleading to use this term for different economic systems. Only since business wealth [capital] assumed an independent existence in capitalistic thinking did it adopt a certain, well-defined meaning.

It is only because certain amounts of wealth came to be dedicated to the purpose of making profit and separated from personal concerns that the ‘principle of acquisition’ (Erwerbsprinzip), distinctive of capitalism, was able to develop without limits. According to Sombart (Reference Sombart1919: 119), the institution of double-entry bookkeeping creates the capitalistic enterprise as a separate, acting entity. By means of accounting, the enterprise ‘assumes a separate existence’ and becomes ‘an entity which emerges as a subject conducting individual economic acts and which leads a separate life, outlasting the life of individuals’ (Sombart, Reference Sombart1919: 101). Capital is inextricably linked to these capitalistic enterprises, which combine the production factors and organise the production process under capitalism according to the principle of profit maximisation.

Mises (Reference Mises1966) constructed a theory of capital based on his historically specific approach to capital. It explains how the invisible hand of the market arranges for profit-oriented, capitalistic enterprises to organise the allocation of resources according to consumer demand (Braun, Reference Braun2017).

Again, it was the Historical School and, ironically, Karl Marx who preceded Mises in the development of such an institutional theory of capital. Marx (Reference Marx1859: 101 ff.) tried to understand and explain the logic of production under capitalism. He described the acquisitive activities of the capitalistic enterprise with the following formula:

$${\rm Money\ndash Commodity\ndash Money^{\prime}}$$

This formula, according to Marx (Reference Marx1859: 102), describes the ‘current form of bourgeois production.’ For capitalistic enterprises, money is not a means but the be-all and end-all of all transactions, ‘the starting point and the end point of movement’ (Marx, Reference Marx1859: 102). The goal of the production process is not to produce products but to make money. ‘Money is exchanged against a commodity in order to exchange the very same commodity for more money’ (Marx, Reference Marx1859: 102).

In Das Kapital, Marx famously combined this theory on the circulation of capital with the labour theory of value in order to explain that the difference between Money’ and Money (the profit retained by the capitalists) amounts to an exploitation of the labour class. Non-socialist authors, however, adopted Marx's approach to capital without combining it with the labour theory of value and simply used it to explain the role of capital in capitalism.

For example, Zwiedineck-Südenhorst (Reference Zwiedineck-Südenhorst1930: 1,072), a member of the Historical School (Grimmer-Solem, Reference Grimmer-Solem2003a: 23), developed an institutional theory of capital as a clear and explicit attempt to add substance to Marx's rather abstract approach. He showed how the transformation of land, labour, and produced means of production into products through production is embedded in the circulation of capital.

Figure 1 can be used to explain how, in capitalism, the production process depends on numerous institutions. The production factors are combined, and output is produced within the enterprise. The enterprise must buy its inputs and sell its output for money on the market. In order to do so, it must be able to acquire and forego private property in commodities. Its profit is determined as the difference between revenues and expenses with the help of the institution of financial accounting or monetary calculation.

Figure 1. The circulation of capital as illustrated by von Zwiedineck-Südenhorst (Reference Zwiedineck-Südenhorst1930: 1,069).

Zwiedineck-Südenhorst (Reference Zwiedineck-Südenhorst1930: 1,070 ff.) argued that capital is relevant because it allows to check whether the means applied have served their purpose. According to Mises's calculation argument, which is presented in the next section, this is exactly what socialist planning boards cannot do.

The components of Mises's argument against the possibility of economic calculation under socialism

Mises (Reference Mises1920, [1932] Reference Mises1951) is famous for his argument that socialism runs into unsurmountable difficulties because a central planning board would not be able to calculate, assess, or compare the value productivity of alternative production processes and therefore could not allocate resources rationally in society:

The mind of one man alone – be it ever so cunning, is too weak to grasp the importance of any single one among the countlessly many goods of a higher order. No single man can ever master all the possibilities of production, innumerable as they are, as to be in a position to make straightway evident judgments of value without the aid of some system of computation. (Mises, Reference Mises1920: 15)

In other words, as Hayek (Reference Hayek1937, Reference Hayek1945) would stress later, socialism has a knowledge problem. The information available to a planning board would never suffice to allocate resources rationally. In contrast to Hayek, however, Mises did not confine himself to the knowledge problem. First and foremost, socialism had a calculation problem (Hülsmann, Reference Hülsmann1997: 24). His point was that socialist planning boards do not have a common yardstick at the ready that would help them to reduce the desirability of goods and services to a single dimension.

The decision-makers in capitalism, in contrast, and particularly the entrepreneurs, do have recourse to such a yardstick. In their calculations, they can rely on the market prices of the means of production. The market system transforms the ordinal preference rankings of different individuals, which are impossible to compare, into common, cardinal units – that is, money prices – and thus provides the basis for economic calculation (Hauwe, Reference Hauwe, Backhaus, Chaloupek and Frambach2019: 201).

Based on prices, entrepreneurs are able to assess whether they can employ a certain good or labour service usefully in a certain production process simply by calculating expected profits and losses. As long as they expect an input factor to generate profit – i.e., to increase a product's price enough to exceed the input's price – its employment is economically justified. Otherwise, they sell, abandon, or transfer the factor to another production process:

Anyone who wishes to make calculations in regard to a complicated process of production will immediately notice whether he has worked more economically than others or not; if he finds, from reference to the exchange relations obtaining in the market, that he will not be able to produce profitably, this shows that others understand how to make a better use of the goods of higher order in question. (Mises, Reference Mises1920: 10)

Socialism, Mises claimed, lacks a comparable common yardstick. As it abolishes private property rights in the means of production, these goods are not traded and therefore no market prices of them exist. Consequently, as a socialist central planning board does not have a yardstick to rationally compare inputs, outputs, and net results, they are not able to determine whether they have employed inputs economically in the production of output:

[I]t lies in the very nature of socialist production that the shares of the particular factors of production in the national dividend cannot be ascertained, and that it is impossible in fact to gauge the relationship between expenditure [production effort] and income [production proceeds]. (Mises, Reference Mises1920: 2; square brackets contain my translations of the original German)

Mises admitted that socialism could solve this problem if it found ‘an objectively recognizable unit of value’, a yardstick ‘which would permit of economic calculation in an economy where neither money nor exchange were present’ (Mises, Reference Mises1920: 30). Mises added, however, that the only item which could conceivably replace money prices and be considered such a yardstick – labour – would be ‘unworkable’ because labour is not homogeneous and of uniform quantity (6). His famous conclusion was that it is impossible for a planning board to economise:

Without economic calculation there can be no economy. Hence, in a socialist state wherein the pursuit of economic calculation is impossible, there can be – in our sense of the term – no economy whatsoever. (18)

For the following discussion, it is helpful to dissect Mises's argument into its individual components. Interestingly, Mises based his argument not only on the theoretical and deductive approach of the Austrian School of Economics but also on important elements of the Historical School of Economics, particularly the institutional theory of capital.

The first component of Mises's argument – an Austrian one – is his critique of the labour theory of value. This critique consists of two aspects:

  1. (a) Based on the subjective theory of value, Mises argued that the labour theory of value is utterly wrong. Objective values cannot be measured at all, he claimed, and relative values or prices depend on consumer choices, not on the amount of labour invested.

  2. (b) Even if we accepted the idea that value is somehow measurable, labour could not serve as a yardstick for economic calculation anyway because labour is not uniform or homogenous.

It must be added that this critique had numerous predecessors. Streissler (Reference Streissler1990) pointed out that the subjective theory of value had been wide-spread in the German-language area before the neoclassical revolution of the 1870s. It is therefore unsurprising that, below, we will find it in the writings of several members of the Historical School.

The second component of his argument – a historical or institutional one – is his description of how capitalism solves the problem of economic calculation. Several capitalistic institutions are necessary to make this possible. They are the same as those that constitute the foundation of the institutional theory of capital. We need private property in the means of production; we need money so that there are money prices of all traded goods; and we need the enterprise and the institutions of monetary calculation, bookkeeping and financial accounting, so that we are able to calculate profits accurately.

Component 3 of his argument is that the market for the means of production guarantees that these means have market prices. This allows enterprises to extend their economic calculation to the higher stages of production – and hence the entire production process. Component 3 is historical as well. I separate it from component 2 because most predecessors of Mises missed it.

Component 4, the consequence of the other three components, is the point that socialist planning boards cannot solve the knowledge problem and are therefore unable to allocate resources and organise the production process rationally. This, of course, is the component that must be present or at least perceptible in any work dealt with in this paper; otherwise, an author cannot be understood as having anticipated Mises. As we have seen in ‘The historical school on the knowledge problem’ section, it is closely related to the approach of the Historical School as well.

Table 1 collects the components of the economic calculation argument. In the following sections, I refer to this table when characterising the arguments made by the predecessors of Mises and Hayek in the Historical School of Economics.

Table 1. Components of the economic calculation argument

It is no wonder that the connection between the historically specific notion of capital and the problem of economic calculation under socialism suggested itself to several members of the Historical School. Almost all of the scholars discussed in the following sections not only anticipated one or several components of Mises and Hayek's argument against socialism, but also employed a historically specific notion of capital or focused on one or several of the institutions behind this notion. Except perhaps for Schäffle (Reference Schäffle1870), they did not employ all components of Mises's argument. Nevertheless, their achievements are still remarkable given that real-world examples of socialism were still a long way off at their time.

Friedrich Julius Stahl on the impossibility of socialism

Chronologically, the first scholar that must be mentioned as a predecessor of Mises is Friedrich Julius Stahl (1802–1861). Stahl was a German legal philosopher associated with the Historical School of Law. In the preface of the first edition of his magnum opus on the philosophy of law, he spoke very positively of Friedrich Savigny, the founder of this school. Stahl (Reference Stahl1847: xix ff.) announced that he would apply, in his book, the historical method, proposed by Savigny, not only to civil law, as Savigny had done, but to law as such.

Stahl's contribution to the impossibility of socialism has been noticed only very recently (Braun and Wollboldt, Reference Braun and Wollboldt2022). This is surprising because Stahl is not at all an unknown figure. Born in 1802 near Würzburg (Germany), Stahl was and still is famous as a Christian and reactionary legal philosopher. Renowned management theoretician Drucker (Reference Drucker1933) even argued that Stahl shaped German thinking about the state up until the First World War. Some of Stahl's works have been translated into English, among them the lecture series that contains the most detailed version of his argument (Stahl, Reference Stahl1978). Unfortunately, copies of Stahl (Reference Stahl1978) are hard to come by, and then it contains numerous errors and confusing mistranslations.

Before I present Stahl's contribution, I have to say a few words about the origin of his ideas. In a footnote, he referred to Dönniges (Reference Dönniges1845), who ‘has illustrated the economic unfeasibility of the social theory [socialism] on the grounds that it removes the distinction between the value of labour and [the value of] its products’ (Stahl, Reference Stahl1846: 75).

Stahl exaggerated. Dönniges (Reference Dönniges1845) did not maintain the unfeasibility of socialism, and he did not go into a lot of detail on this issue. Dönniges criticised socialism mostly on the grounds of components 1a and 1b (see Table 1). The value of labour is not inherent to labour but derives from its products and the needs it satisfies (Dönniges, Reference Dönniges1845: 573). As talents and efforts differ, the value of labour is not the same for each labourer (574). From this, Dönniges (573) did not deduce the impossibility of socialism but claimed that ‘[i]t would be the highest arbitrariness and despotism to equalise the prices of goods or, what amounts to the same thing, to organise them according to principles of justice’.

Stahl, however, concluded from reading Dönniges (Reference Dönniges1845) that socialism was actually impossible. His own arguments are more sophisticated and contain mainly components 1a, 1b, and 4 (see Table 1). Component 2 features less prominently but can still be detected.

The first reference by Stahl to the argument in question that I can detect is in the second edition of the fourth volume of his book on the philosophy of law (Stahl, Reference Stahl1846). It contains a section labelled ‘The social theories [socialism] are indeed unfeasible’. Stahl (75) anticipated component 4 by saying:

Another error of the social theories [socialism], that makes them unfeasible, is the failure to recognise the limit of human intelligence. […] Even if the will of man were that pure as they [these theories] assume, they would still have to fail because of the inability of the human mind to calculate the entire demand and the produce of labour in advance and direct the industrial activities in all its circles accordingly.

Stahl (Reference Stahl1863) elaborated on this argument at length in a chapter entitled ‘Review of the socialist system and of Proudhon's doctrine of value from the economic point of view’. Stahl started the chapter with the blunt statement that ‘[f]rom the standpoint of economics, it [the socialist system] proves to be impossible and to be a system that does not enhance prosperity and enjoyment, but diminishes, even destroys them’ (Stahl, Reference Stahl1863: 240).

Once again, component 4 loomed large in his discussion. He attacked socialists such as Charles Fourier who had claimed that it was possible to plan the production process from above and in advance and without recourse to any measure of value. Stahl (Reference Stahl1863: 245 f.) argued that these plans would fail due to the ‘limit of human intelligence’:

Socialism, however, ventures itself to take over nature's whole task, to achieve that balance between consumption and production solely through human intelligence. It undertakes to sketch out in advance the annual budget for the needs and funds of the entire human race, according to the needs of each individual family, and then to set up systematically the entire labour activity, assigning to everyone his daily business. Now this would not remotely be accurate even in the moment where the need is detected; but the uninterrupted change, the oscillation of wants would remain totally unsatisfied if it were no longer to assert itself through its own direct effect via demand and sales, but only through notification of the superiors and a commissarial investigation.

Stahl (Reference Stahl1863) dug deeper than Stahl (Reference Stahl1846). The quoted passage demonstrates that he was aware of the general role of the institutional framework of capitalism (component 2). He contrasted the market – demands and sales – with central planning and claimed that the latter could not at all accomplish the task of allocating resources satisfactorily. His position on these institutions remains unclear, however, as he appears to identify them with ‘nature’, here and elsewhere.

Stahl (Reference Stahl1863) also addressed other socialist proposals. Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, for example, had made the point that it was possible to introduce labour time as the measure of value of all goods and, consequently, to pay labourers according to their labour time. What needed to be done, Stahl wrote, was to demonstrate the unfeasibility of Proudhon's demand that it is the task of society to fix the price of all products and all services according to the standard of labour time and to achieve the corresponding equality of wages per hour (Stahl, Reference Stahl1863: 248).

In his response to Proudhon's challenge, Stahl employed components 1a and 1b. First of all, he wrote, goods are not valued according to the labour time that is necessary to produce them. It is the other way around: labour is valued because and insofar as its product is valuable to consumers: ‘All value is based on the product itself, i.e., the usefulness, the utility, the virtue that it has in itself’ (250). Stahl (249) ridiculed the labour theory with the following story:

A farmer has a tooth extracted by a surgeon; the operation is carried out beautifully and in no time at all and the surgeon demands the usual charge as payment. But then the farmer breaks out in indignation: What! Your predecessor also once extracted a tooth from me, he pulled and tore at me for a whole hour but did not charge me more than you, and you were finished in a moment and almost without me noticing it.

Stahl did not leave it at that. The classical economists had not been able to explain prices based on a subjective theory of value (use value) because they could not solve the diamond-water paradox of value. Stahl (Reference Stahl1863: 250) did not cite his influences, but like several German-language economists of his time (Streissler, Reference Streissler1990), he anticipated the neoclassical revolution of the 1870s by explaining how goods with objectively high use value (such as water) can end up having lower prices than goods with objectively low use value (such as diamonds):

This utility or virtue of the product (or service) […] depends on the need: in the French army during the retreat from Moscow, lemonade and ice may have been of low value and fur of high value, and vice versa during the campaign in Egypt. It [utility] is based on rarity; for it is a general law of nature, not that the rare is the best, but that the best is rare.

Stahl then went on to demonstrate that even if we grant the possibility of taking labour time as the measure of value, socialism is still ‘not achievable’ (Stahl, Reference Stahl1863: 251) because labour time is not homogenous (component 1b):

For if one takes the working time of the individual as a measure – the time that person A and person H have really spent – the consequences are that individual goods of the same kind have different prices, depending on the random expenditure of time by the workers, even that the goods that the slow beginner has made have everywhere to be paid dearer than those of the masters; and who dares to determine how much time the particular worker has spent each time! If one takes the general average amount of work as a yardstick, the inequality of wages becomes already reestablished in principle, since one person needs more than the average time and another one less.

The quality of Stahl's argument and the number of details he mentioned are astonishing given that the lectures printed in Stahl (Reference Stahl1863) stem from the 1850s. He was the first of a number of members of the Historical School who criticised socialists for their ignorance of the calculation and knowledge problems.

Bruno Hildebrand on economic calculation under socialism

Bruno Hildebrand (1812–1878) discussed the impossibility of socialism in his programmatic book Die Nationalökonomie der Gegenwart und Zukunft (The economics of the present and the future), one of the foundational treatises of the Historical School. The ‘fundamental errors’ of socialists and communists, Hildebrand stated, are their organisational plans for a socialist society: ‘[W]e will demonstrate that all socialist organisation plans are impossible’ (Hildebrand, [Reference Hildebrand1848] 1922: 213). In the subsequent chapter, entitled ‘All socialist organisation plans are unfeasible’, Hildebrand employed components 1b, 2, and 4 of Table 1. Component 2 in particular is much more prominent in Hildebrand than in Stahl. It must be added, however, that Hildebrand ([Reference Hildebrand1848] 1922: 213) referred to Stahl's treatment of socialism but did not give him credit for his attempt to demonstrate the unfeasibility of socialism a few years earlier.

We have seen in ‘The historical school on the knowledge problem’ section that Hildebrand applied Savigny's arguments against classical liberalism to socialism. He argued that socialists ‘break with the past’ and try to ‘form communal life […] by reason’ (Hildebrand, [Reference Hildebrand1848] 1922: 214). But, he did more. In the same way that Savigny had argued that law cannot be invented from scratch but must develop organically, Hildebrand argued that the economy cannot be re-organised from scratch as if it had no history. Accordingly, he defended the institutions of private property, money, and the market against the attacks of the socialists who wanted to abolish them and to organise the economy in a new and different way (Hildebrand, [Reference Hildebrand1848] 1922: 196–211).

The organisational plans of socialists are doomed, Hildebrand concluded, because the socialists do not have a method of rational allocation of resources in society. Socialists would have to come up with an alternative to the market economy. What they need is rules or laws that determine how the individual suppliers of goods and services are compensated in a way that consistently guarantees that the value of outputs surpasses that of inputs:

Any socialist economy which suppresses the individual private economy […] necessitates a law which regulates, first, the mutual ratio between the individual contributions of production and consumption and, second, the ratio between these individual contributions (of production and consumption) and the total of them. (Hildebrand, [Reference Hildebrand1848] 1922: 215)

There is no foundation for such a law, Hildebrand ([Reference Hildebrand1848] 1922: 215) added. First of all, ‘it presupposes the knowledge of the entire demand and the entire supply [Leistungen]’ (indication of component 4). Second, and more importantly for Hildebrand, outside a market economy it is impossible to find rules that indicate how the individual contributors should share in the consumption of the social product. Statements such as ‘From each according to his ability, to each according to his need’ (Hildebrand, [Reference Hildebrand1848] 1922: 216) are mere slogans that are of no help.

The reason he gave for the inability of socialism to find such rules clearly foreshadows component 1b of Mises's argument. For Hildebrand ([Reference Hildebrand1848] 1922: 215), the main deficiency of socialism is its lack of a yardstick for the value of production or consumption:

Furthermore, as individual labour capabilities, talents, and wants are different everywhere, any law of distribution and accommodation presupposes the existence of an absolute measure of individual contributions to production and consumption. Yet, such a measure has neither been discovered, nor is it possible because these contributions are individual, that is, infinitely various, not only quantitatively but also qualitatively, and therefore not objectively measurable.

Earlier in his book, Hildebrand ([Reference Hildebrand1848] 1922: 208) stated that money is necessary as a measure of value. Socialism, in short, is unfeasible for Hildebrand because it lacks the historically grown institutions of capitalism, where money prices serve as a yardstick in the economic calculations of entrepreneurs and where the distribution of the social product to the productive factors is oriented towards the contribution of each factor to the monetary profits of enterprises.

Karl Knies on the role of money in capitalism and socialism

Hildebrand hinted at the important role of money as a measure of value, but Karl Knies (1821–1898) dedicated large parts of his book on money to this issue. At the outset, Knies (Reference Knies1885: 6) stated that the institution of money is supposed to eliminate the ‘social evil’ that comes with the ‘so very difficult and so unsatisfying assessment and comparison’ of economic goods in a natural economy. Any plans for organising the production process without trade and money would bring along this social evil, especially in modern societies with their highly developed and complicated system of division of labour. It is no coincidence, Knies (Reference Knies1885: 5) wrote, that social reformers who demand the abolishment of money suggest that the organisation of the economy should depend on ‘the unlimited prevalence either of fatherly benevolence facing naive piety or of a supposedly highly prudent, highly just etc. supreme power facing blind obedience on the part of all people that are involved’.

Knies did not claim explicitly that socialism is unfeasible. Yet, he tried to demonstrate why Marx had not succeeded in his attempts to replace the monetary unit with the quantity of labour as the measuring rod for the value of goods and claimed that socialism would drift towards a despotic government if it were to abandon money and money prices. His argument built mainly on components 1b and 2 of Table 1.

It must be mentioned that when it comes to capitalistic institutions (component 2), Knies (Reference Knies1885: 72) was well aware that some economists claim that capital is historically specific – a ‘historical category’, as he expressed it. However, Knies was not ready to follow these economists. Knies (Reference Knies1885: 29) was of the opinion that it had not helped economic science that Adam Smith and many other economists tended to make apodictic pronouncements in favour of certain definitions of capital over others. Accordingly, Knies (Reference Knies1885: 24–83) himself, in his long discussion of capital, did not dare to come to a definite conclusion on the term capital but rather discussed the merits and demerits of existing definitions of the term. That is, he did not opt for capital as a historical category that is a part of the institutional framework of capitalism.

Still, his argument against socialism rests on his analysis of one capitalistic institution, namely money, and how it helps to solve the issue of valuating goods and services. Knies (Reference Knies1885: 151) mentioned that Karl Marx had wrestled with exactly this problem. His argument against Marx's solution runs as follows.

According to Marx, exchange value derives from the quantity of simple labour that is necessary, on average, to produce a certain good. Knies (Reference Knies1885: 156) objected that there are many cases where this is not true at all and where labour time cannot be the substance of value. The apprentice will never be able to replicate ‘the artwork of his master even in a multiple of the time that the master needs’. Knies (Reference Knies1885: 158) added that it is an illusion if Marx wants to measure the value of all products of labour by the quantity of simple labour (component 1b of Table 1). According to Knies, the problem is that different kinds of labour cannot be compared. They appear to be comparable only because in capitalistic societies they all have a money price. That the price of advanced labour can be expressed as the multiple of the price of simple labour, however, does not imply that simple labour could serve as a measuring unit for advanced labour (1885: 158). Knies's argument was that the existence of money may make it possible to express the price of any good as a multiple of the price of any other good, but that does not mean that it is possible to express the quantity of any good as a multiple of the quantity of any other good. Rather, what is needed is a tertium comparationis, a monetary unit that has a certain and predetermined amount of value itself that can be used to express the value of all other goods (1885: 163). The task of money is to ‘be the special tool by means of which the social fungibility of value, necessary because of the division of labour in the exchange economy, is realised in all valuable goods’ (1885: 164).

Although Knies (Reference Knies1885) did not explicitly deny the possibility of socialism, he came to the conclusion that a ‘socialistically organised society errs’ when it ‘determines the value substance and the measure of value’ (1885: 165) on the basis of labour and not on the basis of use value, which is present in all goods as well as the monetary unit.

To sum up, Knies tried to understand the role that the institution of money plays in capitalism. As part of his analysis, he demonstrated the problems that economic systems that abolish money would face. In doing so, he employed and combined components 1b and 2 of Mises's argument.

Albert Schäffle on economic calculation under socialism and capitalism

Albert Schäffle (1831–1903) was a member of the German Historical School. He was a sociologist, economist, and politician and Menger's direct predecessor at the University of Vienna. Schäffle's contribution to the economic calculation argument against socialism is well established. Hodgson (Reference Hodgson and Vint2010) covers Schäffle's Quintessence of Social Democracy, and Braun (Reference Braun2016) focuses on his Kapitalismus und Socialismus. Schäffle (Reference Schäffle1878: 307 ff.) contains another discussion on economic calculation under socialism. However, Schäffle (Reference Schäffle1878) is less forceful than Schäffle (Reference Schäffle1870), probably because of some developing socialist tendencies in his thinking. That is why I concentrate on Schäffle (Reference Schäffle1870) and confine myself to categorising its contributions according to Table 1.

In 1870, Schäffle was still convinced that socialism would be impossible. He stated explicitly that it is ‘utopistic that the economy of a large people could be directed from a central point’ (Schäffle, Reference Schäffle1870: 192) and that it simply ‘cannot be done’ (Schäffle, Reference Schäffle1870: 205). His argument is reminiscent of component 4 of Table 1:

Communism completely ignores […] the difficulty of governing national and international societies from a single central point. You do not find any idea about how the millions and squillions of people who are separated from each other by hemispheres (locally) and by years, decades, even centuries (temporally) […] are supposed to be governed by a host of civil servants such that they perform the economic valuation process according to costs and utility (Schäffle, Reference Schäffle1870: 206).

Schäffle (Reference Schäffle1870) substantiated this claim with components 1a, 1b, 2, and 3. As Braun (Reference Braun2016) focused on the role of 1a and 1b in Schäffle's work (for component 1a see also Dekker, Reference Dekker2016: 55 f.), the present paper concentrates on component 2, the necessity of capitalistic institutions for rational economic calculation, and component 3, the necessity of money prices of the means of production.

At the outset, Schäffle (Reference Schäffle1870: 19 ff., 92) distinguished clearly between capital goods (Kapitalgüter) and capital (Kapitalvermögen). Whereas he defined capital goods as produced means of production, as technical or physical elements of the production process, capital is something entirely different. Capital ‘directs’ and ‘organises’ (Schäffle, Reference Schäffle1870: 21) the production process via monetary calculation:

The reduction of all cost and use values to exchange values and money implies that each invested particle of labour and each particle of already arranged product can become and actually does become subject to calculation. An exactly developed economic art of calculation – bookkeeping and cost accounting – records all cost elements and revenues in monetary terms, it records, in equal magnitudes of value, the entire process of the never-ending transformation of capital [goods] and labour. […] Only now it becomes and remains obvious where in the business and the household the conduct of affairs has been economical and where it has not been so. (Schäffle, Reference Schäffle1870: 109, emphasis in original)

According to Schäffle, the capitalistic institutions of money, financial accounting, and private property in the means of production make rational economic calculation possible. Capital, understood as a correlate of these institutions, plays the essential role in the production process. It ‘combines’ the different assets that are technically necessary for the production of specific goods. For example, the viticulturist combines, with his capital, all assets that are necessary for the production of wine (Schäffle, Reference Schäffle1870: 109).

Schäffle is the only one of the authors discussed in this paper who even included component 3 of Mises's argument. He wrote that there is, at the societal level, a division of capital, a coordination of the individual business assets of the numerous entrepreneurs in the different stages of production. Schäffle (Reference Schäffle1870: 109–110) explained that the division and specialisation of capital is made possible because the assets of all the individual enterprises together constitute a large, intertwined production apparatus. The organic relationship of all capital goods in this apparatus is created by the striving of the capital of each enterprise for the highest profit. In this way, enterprises put checks and balances in place for each other. Their ‘competitive seeking for profit has become the organising power of the economy’ (Schäffle, Reference Schäffle1870: 114). Schäffle (Reference Schäffle1870: 114) included the means of production in the higher stages of production in his analysis of how capitalism is organised:

Each subsequent entrepreneur in the production chain takes vengeance for the inefficiency of his suppliers by refunding them less than they have disbursed. Competition between all enterprises is objectively and imperatively inducing the highest efficiency of the modern capitalistic structure of production.

In other words, Schäffle is aware of the role that the prices of the means of production play in capitalistic societies. Schäffle's discussion of the way enterprises organise the capitalistic economy by orienting their actions towards monetary profits therefore foreshadows Mises's discussion in his magnum opus Human Action.

Schäffle's Kapitalismus und Socialismus indeed does more than allude to the economic problem of socialism. It contains all components of Mises's later argument against socialism and demonstrates that what Mises did years later is closely connected to the research programme of the Historical School. It was his analysis of capitalistic institutions – money, financial accounting, private property, and the market – that led Schäffle to claim that socialism was unfeasible.

I must add that Schäffle's book is more than seven hundred pages long and is based on public lectures. His arguments are scattered throughout the book and accompany treatments of philosophical, sociological, and historical issues. Still, Schäffle had a very good sense of the role of monetary calculation in capitalism and the problem any economic system would face if it were to forgo capitalistic institutions.

Further members of the German Historical School on the impossibility of socialism

Lorenz von Stein (1815–1890) was a lawyer and economist who wrote extensively on the role of capital and enterprises in capitalism. He is important in the history of economics and socialism because he brought the first important debates on socialism in France to the attention of the German public (Pasquino, Reference Pasquino1981: 1). Stein (Reference Stein1887: 370) did not focus on the role of economic calculation, but it appears that he was aware of the problem. He declared that ‘50% of all socialists believe in the promises of communism because they do not have an idea of even the simplest accounting procedures’. He even claimed that ‘nobody who has learned to calculate and to account could ever become a socialist’.

The German agronomist Georg Calberla (1845–1904) was not a direct member of the Historical School. In his critique of Marx, however, he referred to Gustav Schmoller and especially Albert Schäffle as his two role models who had directed analysis of socialism to the right channels (Calberla, Reference Calberla1877: 11).

Calberla (Reference Calberla1877: 46) stated that ‘a socialist system absolutely needs a measure of value in order to distribute the social product’. However, Marx had made the ‘fateful error’ of constructing ‘equal undifferentiated abstract human labour as the actual essence of value’. In his book, Calberla (Reference Calberla1877: 46) demonstrated ‘how wrong this is’.

According to Calberla (Reference Calberla1877: 25), it is the ‘fundamental theorem of the entire socialist doctrine’ that ‘the sole basis of [exchange] value is the human labour embodied in each commodity’. Calberla argued against this that labour cannot serve as a measure of value. He employs elements 1a and 1b (see Table 1) in order to demonstrate this point. It is ‘not the intensity of human effort, not the duration of labour’ that determines the value of the product of labour but ‘the degree of urgency of the needs that the product can satisfy’ (Calberla, Reference Calberla1877: 30). Therefore, different kinds of labour have different values, depending on the needs they can satisfy. From a ‘subjective standpoint’, human labour is ‘not of equal value, not equally useful, not equal’ (Calberla, Reference Calberla1877: 34).

As the fundamental theorem of socialism is wrong, Calberla (Reference Calberla1877: 59) concludes that socialism is impossible:

[T]he most important foundations and necessary conditions of a social organisation according to the recipe of present-day socialists are entirely called into question and are not present if – as we have demonstrated – from a subjective standpoint human labour is not equal and undifferentiated but profoundly diverse; and if the measure of its value is not its duration but the degree of its social utility.

Calberla (Reference Calberla1877) is a work of criticism. It deals with the problems of socialist systems. Therefore, it does not contain an analysis of capitalistic institutions (component 2 of Table 1). But Calberla was well aware of the role that these institutions play. In a short passage, he stated: ‘Everyone has to admit that production on the basis of free, individual property and the exchange of value by means of general signs of value [money] are the preconditions of the present-day degree of material emancipation of humanity’ (Calberla, Reference Calberla1877: 58). Private property and money appear to be necessary for the division of labour in modern societies.

A brief comment is warranted on the so-called younger Historical School around Gustav Schmoller and Adolph Wagner. This school is sometimes referred to as ‘socialism of the chair.’ However, as Bunyk and Krasnozhon (Reference Bunyk and Krasnozhon2022: 180 f.) explain, while the younger Historical School was arguing for an interventionist state and social policy, it could hardly be called socialistic. On the contrary, an important impulse for the social reform activities Schmoller organised and directed since the early 1870s was his fear of socialist revolution (Grimmer-Solem, Reference Grimmer-Solem, Eley and Retallack2003b: 107). And even though I was not able to trace the calculation argument in the literature of the younger Historical School, Wagner (Reference Wagner1907: 692) at least echoed Bruno Hildebrand's point briefly. Despite his sympathy for some socialist ideas, he stated explicitly that the ‘realisation of the Socialistic system of economy makes demands upon the intellectual and moral qualities of men […] which all that we know of men […] shows to be pitched far too high.’

The continuing importance of the institutional theory of capital

In the socialist calculation debate, Oskar Lange and Abba Lerner opposed the idea, propagated by Mises, that socialism would fail without a market in which the prices for the means and factors of production could be determined. They backed their position with mathematical standard models. As Boettke et al. (Reference Boettke, Coyne, Leeson, Garrison and Barry2014: 283) explain, the Lange–Lerner theorem basically applied neoclassical economics to a socialist system. These authors and their followers maintained that a central planning board could act as a Walrasian auctioneer by announcing and adjusting prices until equilibrium is achieved. The neoclassical general equilibrium model was supposed to describe not only capitalist market economies but also socialist economies (Hodgson, Reference Hodgson2016: 37). The applicability of the model was thought to be independent of the actual institutional context.

In contrast, Mises position was that the rational allocation of resources, described by the neoclassical equilibrium model, is contingent on a certain institutional and historical background. Only in a market economy where private property rights in the means of production are upheld and the institutions of monetary calculation exist can societal resources be reasonably evaluated according to their utility for the final consumer. Socialism, which does not have or even actively rejects these institutions, is therefore not able to evaluate and economise its resources.

One basic element of Mises's argument – the institutional theory to capital – has since been abandoned by large parts of the economics profession (Hodgson, Reference Hodgson2014: 1,077). Tellingly, the three-volume collection of seminal papers on capital theory published by Edward Elgar in 2005 contains only two (out of a total of 71) contributions that are associated with this theory: Schumpeter (Reference Schumpeter, Bliss, Cohen and Harcourt2005) and a few, mainly polemical pages in Veblen (Reference Veblen, Bliss, Cohen and Harcourt2005: 161–167).

We must not overlook the fact that the adherents of the institutional approach to capital are at least partly to blame for its neglect. Apart from Veblen's contribution, the three major controversies on capital in the history of economics took place without notable interference by advocates of the institutional approach. Neither the Austrians Menger and Mises nor the respective generations of Historical School economists entered the debate. Furthermore, what may have been the most extensive attempt to develop the institutional theory of capital, Mises (Reference Mises1966), has been neglected not only by his intellectual opponents but also by most of his followers in the Austrian School, who preferred and still prefer the standard Austrian theory of capital, which defines capital as a physical factor of production.

From a current perspective, this must be considered a loss for economic science. The institutional theory of capital does not exhaust itself in the critique of socialism. Its purpose is to describe important processes within the market economy and how they depend on certain institutional preconditions. These processes are at risk of being jeopardised not only by the outright socialisation of the means of production. Any reform of these institutions may have important, possibly undesirable consequences for the creation and distribution of wealth in market societies.

To give an important example, by abandoning the institutional theory of capital, economists have deported themselves of the ability to comment profoundly on the implications of the far-reaching reforms of financial accounting and corporate governance witnessed in recent decades. This is not the place to comment on the viability of these reforms. The point is that they concern activities of capitalistic enterprises, particularly monetary calculation and profit-making, which are described and explained by the institutional theory of capital. Therefore, this theory is not only important for demonstrating certain problems of socialism; it may also serve as a basis for explaining and commenting on somewhat related problems that have haunted capitalistic economies since at least the 1980s, especially the increasing macroeconomic instability and the supposed or actual tendency of managers toward short-termism.

Conclusion

Mises's argument against the feasibility of socialism is based on the institutional setting peculiar to a certain economic system in a specific period of time. According to Mises, it is the institutions of private property, money, markets, and monetary calculation of the capitalistic enterprise that make possible rational economic calculation in capitalism. In socialism these institutions do not exist, or at least exist only in a crippled form, and therefore no rational economic calculation is possible.

This paper has demonstrated two points. First, Mises's argument was foreshadowed by several members of the Historical School: Friedrich Julius Stahl, Bruno Hildebrand, Karl Knies, Albert Schäffle, and Georg Calberla. Second, these contributions should not be viewed with surprise. The members of the German Historical School of Economics were interested in the historically specific institutions of capitalism. They wanted to understand how and why capitalism works – that is, how the international division of labour was made possible in the market economy. By doing so, they came to the institutions that Mises would employ in his argument against socialism. Their institutional theory of capital explains the role of these institutions in the production process.

Starting from their interest in these institutions, some members of the Historical School not only anticipated Mises's argument but developed an approach to capital that incorporated these institutions. Menger (Reference Menger1888) adopted this approach, and it is highly probable that the contributions of the Historical School influenced Mises's thinking indirectly via Menger's essay. In my opinion, backed up throughout this paper, the Historical School deserves some credit for Mises's contribution on the possibilities and preconditions of economic calculation in different economic systems. Further, economists should revive its institutional theory of capital, as it could serve as a tool for understanding the current reforms in financial accounting and corporate governance.

Footnotes

1 Throughout the paper, all foreign language quotations have been translated by the author.

References

Boettke, P.J., Coyne, C.J. and Leeson, P.T. (2014) Hayek versus the neoclassicists: lessons from the socialist calculation debate. In Garrison, RW and Barry, N (eds), Elgar Companion to Hayekian Economics. Cheltenham et al.: Elgar, 278293.Google Scholar
Braun, E. (2015 a) Carl Menger's contribution to capital theory. History of Economic Ideas 23(1), 7799.Google Scholar
Braun, E. (2015 b) Unsuspected origins of modern Austrian economics: the historical school of economics on capital and economic calculation. In Bylund, P and Howden, D (eds), The Next Generation of Austrian Economics. Auburn, AL: Mises Institue, 7587.Google Scholar
Braun, E. (2016) The German historical school on the impossibility of economic calculation under socialism. Betriebswirtschaftliche Forschung und Praxis 68(2), 126135.Google Scholar
Braun, E. (2017) The theory of capital as a theory of capitalism. Journal of Institutional Economics 13(2), 305325.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Braun, E. (2020) Carl Menger: Contribution to the theory of Capital (1888), Section V. Journal of Institutional Economics 16(4), 557568.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Braun, E. and Wollboldt, M. (2022) Friedrich Julius Stahl (1802–1861) on the impossibility of socialism. Available at https://www.researchgate.net/publication/365704347_Friedrich_Julius_Stahl_1802-1861_on_the_impossibility_of_socialism.Google Scholar
Braun, E., Lewin, P. and Cachanosky, N. (2016) Ludwig von Mises's approach to capital as a bridge between Austrian and Institutional Economics. Journal of Institutional Economics 12(4), 847866.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bunyk, M. and Krasnozhon, L. (2022) Young Mr. Mises and younger historicists: Origins of Mises's liberalism. Review of Austrian Economics 35(2), 177191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Calberla, G.M. (1877) Karl Marx, “Das Kapital” und der heutige Sozialismus. Kritik einiger ihrer Fundamentalsätze. Dresden: Schönfeld.Google Scholar
Dekker, E. (2016), The Viennese students of Civilization: Humility, Culture and Economics in Interwar Vienna and Beyond. Doctoral thesis, Erasmus University Rotterdam.Google Scholar
Dönniges, W.V. (1845) Ueber die wissenschaftliche und praktische Bedeutung des Socialismus und Communismus. Allgemeine Zeitung 1845(69), 545547, (70): 554–57; (71): 563–65; (72): 572–74.Google Scholar
Drucker, P.F. (1933) Friedrich Julius Stahl: konservative Staatslehre und geschichtliche Entwicklung. Tübingen: Mohr.Google Scholar
Ebeling, R.M. (2003) Economic calculation under socialism: Ludwig von Mises and his predecessors. In Ebeling, RM (ed.), Austrian Economics and the Political Economy of Freedom. Cheltenham and Northampton: Edward Elgar, 101135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grimmer-Solem, E (2003 a) The Rise of Historical Economics and Social Reform in Germany 1864–1894. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grimmer-Solem, E. (2003 b) Imperialist socialism of the chair. Gustav Schmoller and German Weltpolitik, 1897–1905. In Eley, G and Retallack, J (eds), Wilhelminism and Its Legacies. New York and Oxford: Berghahn Books, 106121.Google Scholar
Hauwe, L.V.D. (2019) Ludwig von Mises’ argument against the possibility of socialism: early concepts and contemporary relevance. In Backhaus, J, Chaloupek, G, and Frambach, HA (eds), The First Socialization Debate (1918) and Early Efforts Towards Socialization. Cham: Springer, 191222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hayek, F.A. (1937) Economics and knowledge. Economica (New Series) 4(13), 3354.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hayek, F.A. (1945) The use of knowledge in society. American Economic Review 35(4), 519530.Google Scholar
Hayek, F.A. (2014) The Collected Works of F. A. Hayek, Vol. XV, edited by B. Caldwell, Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hildebrand, B. ([1848] (1922)) Die Nationalökonomie der Gegenwart und Zukunft und andere gesammelte Schriften. Jena: Fischer.Google Scholar
Hodgson, G.M. (2010) Albert Schäffle's critique of socialism. In Vint, J. (ed.), Economic Theory and Economic Thought, London et al.: Routledge, 296315.Google Scholar
Hodgson, G.M. (2014) What is capital? Economists and sociologists have changed its meaning: Should it be changed back? Cambridge Journal of Economics 38(5), 10631086.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodgson, G.M. (2015) Much of the ‘economics of property rights’ devalues property and legal rights. Journal of Institutional Economics 11(4), 683709.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodgson, G.M. (2016) Some limitations of the socialist calculation debate. Schmollers Jahrbuch 136(1), 3358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hülsmann, J.G. (1997) Knowledge, judgment, and the use of property. Review of Austrian Economics 10(1), 2348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knies, K. (1885) Geld und Credit. Vol I: Das Geld. Darlegung der Grundlehren von dem Gelde, 2nd edn. Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung.Google Scholar
Kolev, S. and Dekker, E. (2023) Carl Menger's Smithian contributions to German political economy. Review of Austrian Economics, 36(3): 247269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewin, P. and Cachanosky, N. (2018) Substance and semantics: The question of capital. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 150, 423431.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marx, K. (1859) Zur Kritik der Politischen Oekonomie. Berlin: Duncker.Google Scholar
Menger, C. (1888) Zur Theorie des Kapitals. Jahrbücher für Nationalökonomie und Statistik 17, 149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mises, L.V. ([1920] (2012)). Economic Calculation in the Socialist Commonwealth, translated from German by S. Adler, Auburn, AL: Mises Institute.Google Scholar
Mises, L.V. ([1932] (1951)). Socialism. An Economic and Sociological Analysis, translated by J. Kahane, New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Mises, L.V. (1966) Human Action: A Treatise on Economics, 3rd edn. Chicago: Henry Regnery.Google Scholar
Pasquino, P. (1981) Introduction to Lorenz von Stein. Economy and Society 10(1), 16.Google Scholar
Raico, R. (1995) The Austrian school and classical liberalism. Advances in Austrian Economics 2A, 338.Google Scholar
Roos, N.H.M. (1994) Hayek's Kantian heritage and natural law. In Birner, J and Zijp, RV (eds), Hayek, Co-Ordination and Evolution. London and New York: Routledge, 287307.Google Scholar
Roscher, W. (1864) System der Volkswirthschaft. Vol. 1, 5th edn. Stuttgart: Cotta.Google Scholar
Savigny, F.C.V. ([1814] (1973)) Vom Beruf unsrer Zeit für Gesetzgebung und Rechtswissenschaft. In Hattenhauer, H (ed.), Thibaut und Savigny. Ihre programmatischen Schriften. München: Franz Vahlen, 95192.Google Scholar
Savigny, F.C.V. ([1815] (1973)) Über den Zweck dieser Zeitschrift. In Hattenhauer, H (ed.), Thibaut und Savigny. Ihre programmatischen Schriften. München: Franz Vahlen, 261268.Google Scholar
Schäffle, A.E.F. (1870) Kapitalismus und Socialismus mit besonderer Rücksicht auf Geschäfts- und Vermögensformen. Tübingen: Laupp.Google Scholar
Schäffle, A.E.F. (1878), Bau und Leben des socialen Körpers. Vol. 3, Tübingen: Laupp.Google Scholar
Schumpeter, J.A. (2005) Interest on Capital. In Bliss, C, Cohen, AJ and Harcourt, GC (eds), Capital Theory. Vol. 1. Cheltenham, UK and Northampton, MA: Elgar, 350404.Google Scholar
Sombart, W. (1919) Der moderne Kapitalismus, Volume 2.1. München and Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot.Google Scholar
Sombart, W. (1927) Der moderne Kapitalismus, Volume 3.1. München and Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot.Google Scholar
Stahl, F.J. (1846) Die Philosophie des Rechts. Vol. 2: Rechts- und Staatslehre auf der Grundlage christlicher Weltanschauung. Sect. 2: Die Lehre vom Staat und die Principien des deutschen Staatsrechts, 2nd edn. Heidelberg: Mohr.Google Scholar
Stahl, F.J. (1847) Die Philosophie des Rechts. Vol. 1: Geschichte der Rechtsphilosophie, 2nd edn. Heidelberg: Mohr.Google Scholar
Stahl, F.J. (1863) Die gegenwärtigen Parteien in Staat und Kirche. Berlin: Verlag von Wilhelm Hertz.Google Scholar
Stahl, F.J. (1978) The present-day parties in the state and church: twenty-nine academic lectures. State College, PA: Blenheim Publishing House.Google Scholar
Stein, L.V. (1887) Lehrbuch der Nationalökonomie. Wien: Manz.Google Scholar
Streissler, E.W. (1990) The influence of German economics on the work of Menger and Marshall. History of Political Economy 22(S1), 3168.Google Scholar
Veblen, T. (2005) Professor Clark's economics. In Bliss, C, Cohen, AJ and Harcourt, GC (eds), Capital Theory. Vol. 1, Cheltenham, UK and Northampton, MA: Elgar, 445493.Google Scholar
Wagner, A. (1907) The rights and wrongs of socialism. Fortnightly Review 81(484), 682694.Google Scholar
Witt, U. (1997) The Hayekian Puzzle: Spontaneous order and the business cycle. Scottish Journal of Political Economy 44(1), 4458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zwiedineck-Südenhorst, O.V. (1930) Kapital und Kapitalismus. Schmollers Jahrbuch 54(2), 10591092.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1. The circulation of capital as illustrated by von Zwiedineck-Südenhorst (1930: 1,069).

Figure 1

Table 1. Components of the economic calculation argument