Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-18T19:58:28.625Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reviewing the concept of design frames towards a cognitive model

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 December 2022

Nick Kelly*
Affiliation:
School of Design, Queensland University of Technology, Brisbane, QLD 4000, Australia
John S. Gero
Affiliation:
Computer Science and Architecture, University of North Carolina at Charlotte, Charlotte, NC 28223, USA
*
Corresponding author N. Kelly [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This paper critically reviews literature about design framing to clarify an understanding of what is meant by the construct of a design frame. It describes the origins of the term design frame and characterises three distinct definitions that can be found within the literature. It reviews empirical studies of design framing to highlight definitional confusion between studies. It discusses the significance of Dorst’s propositional model of design frames and juxtaposes design frames with other related constructs. It clarifies ways that the resolution of nomenclature for describing design framing might lead to a more coherent body of empirical research into this topic. It suggests that there is value in developing a better cognitive model of design framing and outlines potential steps towards such a model.

Type
Review Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - SA
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/4.0), which permits non-commercial re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the same Creative Commons licence is used to distribute the re-used or adapted article and the original article is properly cited. The written permission of Cambridge University Press must be obtained prior to any commercial use.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

A common adage in design is that solving the right problem matters. It has become a cliché to begin articles about design framing with Einstein’s quote, that ‘if I were given one hour to save the planet, I would spend 59 minutes understanding the problem and one minute resolving it’ (e.g., Spradlin Reference Spradlin2016; Henriques Reference Henriques2018; Münch, Trieflinger, & Heisler Reference Münch, Trieflinger and Heisler2020). The intimation is that once a useful understanding of a problem has been developed, then a solution – or a suitable design candidate – is often readily available. Articles use this quote from Einstein because it speaks to the importance of framing for problem-solving and design activity. Framing is understood to be the ‘core of design thinking’ (Dorst Reference Dorst2011) yet the essence of design frames – how to distinguish them, how to speak about them – remains ambiguous.

This review paper is motivated by a perceived mismatch between, on the one hand, the widespread usage and utility of the construct design frame and, on the other, the lack of definitional clarity currently available. The term framing has gained significant usage within design cognition literature. In a widely cited paper, Dorst (Reference Dorst2011) has argued that framing is the ‘core of design thinking’. Frames have been studied empirically for at least three decades (e.g., Schön & Wiggins Reference Schön and Wiggins1992; Valkenburg & Dorst Reference Valkenburg and Dorst1998; Kvan & Gao Reference Kvan, Gao and Gero2006; Hey, Joyce, & Beckman Reference Hey, Joyce and Beckman2007; Zahedi & Heaton Reference Zahedi and Heaton2017; Mcdonnell Reference Mcdonnell2018; Silk et al. Reference Silk, Rechkemmer, Daly, Jablokow and Mckilligan2021; Chandrasegaran, Lloyd, & Akdag Salah Reference Chandrasegaran, Lloyd, Akdag Salah, Lockton, Lenzi, Hekkert, Oak, Sádaba and Lloyd2022). The notion of framing has been applied to diverse areas of design such as social policy innovation (Van Der Bijl-Brouwer Reference Van Der Bijl-Brouwer2019), engineering design (Rodriguez & Benavides Reference Rodriguez and Benavides2021), and product design (Hey et al. Reference Hey, Joyce and Beckman2007) as well as to design research methods (Bailey et al. Reference Bailey, Spencer, Smith, Aftab, Knott and Sams2018) and design pedagogy in higher education (Gray Reference Gray2019). Yet the terms design framing and design frame still lack any consensus definition.

This paper is concerned with reviewing the term design frame and it takes the form of a critical review in that it considers the literature that is most salient to the topic, uses a conceptual mode of synthesis, and analyses the literature aiming for a conceptual or theoretical contribution (Grant & Booth Reference Grant and Booth2009); it is not an exhaustive review of the topic. It reviews the origins of the term frame to show that three different definitions can be found within the literature. It then reviews empirical studies of design framing to show that a range of these three definitions is utilised. It discusses the significance of the propositional model of design frames (Dorst Reference Dorst2011) and contrasts design frames with related constructs. It concludes with a discussion of pathways that might advance the study of design frames.

2. Definitions of design frames

2.1. The origins of the term frame

The origins of the term frame can be approached through the question: what is the relationship between a person’s ability to reason about the world and to have sensory experiences in the world? This question was salient in the 18th century in attempts to reconcile rationalist and empiricist notions of epistemology (Markie & Folescu Reference Markie and Folescu2004). On the one hand, new knowledge can be developed through the use of reason, such as through logical inference. On the other hand, sensory experiences within the world can also lead to new understandings. These two understandings are now recognised as complementary parts of an interdependent system of concepts and experiences.

The concepts that a person holds about the world influence the ways in which sensory experiences occur; what they think about the world changes what they attend to, what they sense, and the interpretations that they produce. Similarly, the experiences that someone has in the world can change those concepts to reflect reality in what is commonly referred to as learning. Early work exploring these notions looked at the nature of concepts and the existence of selective attention (James Reference James1890) as well as the constructive nature of memory (Dewey Reference Dewey1910; Bartlett Reference Bartlett1932). It was observed that problems (including but not limited to design problems) serve to trigger a ‘…survey and recall of the past to discover what the question means and how it may be dealt with’ (Dewey Reference Dewey1910, p. 207). Although neither James nor Dewey used the term frame, their work underpins the modern understanding of a frame as being an internal conceptual structure that guides the ways in which aspects of experience occur. Schön (who did use the term frame) explicitly refers to the influence of both James and Dewey on his thinking.

The word frame began to be used widely following the publication of Erving Goffman’s book Frame Analysis (Goffman Reference Goffman1974). Goffman drew upon these philosophical underpinnings from Dewey and James (Verhoeven Reference Verhoeven1993) as well as the phenomenological ideas of Bateson (Reference Bateson1972) and Schutz (Reference Schutz1962). He defined frames as follows:

I assume that definitions of a situation are built up in accordance with principles of organization which govern events—at least social ones—and our subjective involvement in them; frame is the word I use to refer to such of these basic elements as I am able to identify. This is my definition of frame. My phrase ‘frame analysis’ is a slogan to refer to examination in these terms of the organization of experience. (pp. 10–11)

For Goffman, people organise experiences through frames, and those frames can be analysed. Frames are the way that people make sense of circumstances, the story that they might tell you if you were to ask them ‘what is going on here?’

The origins of framing are further complicated (Borah Reference Borah2011) by parallel uses of the term – beyond Goffman’s sociological account – within artificial intelligence (Minsky Reference Minsky1974) and psychology (Kahneman & Tversky Reference Kahneman and Tversky1984). Recent reviews focus on framing in product innovation (Hey Reference Hey2008), framing as a reflective conversation (Dorst Reference Dorst2015), and a sociological review of framing (Snow Reference Snow and Ritzer2007). In later work on the subject, Rein and Schön (Reference Rein and Schön1996) discuss four ways of looking at frames as scaffolds (inner structures that support further building; a Minsky-like perspective), as boundaries (like picture frames; a Goffman-like perspective), as schemata that support interpretation (a Piagetian perspective), and as diagnostic/prescriptive stories (the view that Rein and Schön support).

2.2. Frames in design

The notion of framing entered the field of design through the writing of Schön (Reference Schön1983).Footnote 1 For Schön, framing happens when we name the things that we are interested in (internally recognising them through selective attention) and frame the context in which we understand them:

When we set the problem, we select what we will treat as the ‘things’ of the situation, we set the boundaries of our attention to it, and we impose upon it a coherence which allows us to say what is wrong and in what directions the situation needs to be changed. Problem setting is a process in which, interactively, we name the things to which we will attend and frame the context in which we will attend to them. (p. 40)

He gives the example of a studio master, Quist, and a student, Petra, engaged in a reflective conversation. Schön describes the conversation as having ‘local experiments’ that contribute to the ‘global experiment’ in which master and student work together to reframe the problem. These common origins of frames – especially the work of Schön – are referenced throughout the literature that looks into empirical studies of framing in design (Schön & Wiggins Reference Schön and Wiggins1992; Valkenburg & Dorst Reference Valkenburg and Dorst1998; Kvan & Gao Reference Kvan, Gao and Gero2006; Zahedi & Heaton Reference Zahedi and Heaton2017; Van Der Bijl-Brouwer Reference Van Der Bijl-Brouwer2019).

The idea of a frame has been useful at least since the time of Schön as a way of resolving the interdependency of internal and external worlds of cognition and is a useful construct for the study of design. Frames have been used to provide narrative accounts of how designers change their conception of a design problem (Schön Reference Schön1983). They have been used in the analysis of design discourses to distinguish where designers are naming, framing, moving, and reflecting during episodes of design (Valkenburg & Dorst Reference Valkenburg and Dorst1998). They have, more recently, been used in an applied way to suggest a process for working towards better understandings of a problem (Dorst Reference Dorst2015).

2.3. Design framing

The activity that leads to the creation of a design frame is referred to as design framing. An understanding of how design framing is discussed in the literature provides a useful context for defining design frames. Designers face a well-recognised challenge, that they can only ever design within their own interpretation of the problem that is to be addressed (Schön Reference Schön1983; Gero Reference Gero1990; Dorst Reference Dorst2011, Reference Dorst2015) and design framing is the process of constructing an understanding of the problem that is to be solved. Design problems are not ‘out there’ waiting to be solved, and even a design brief requires interpretation (Sosa, Connor, & Corson Reference Sosa, Connor and Corson2017). The term framing was introduced to design by Schön (Reference Schön1983) with the observation that:

When ends are fixed and clear, then the decision to act can present itself as an instrumental problem. But when ends are confused and conflicting, there is as yet no ‘problem’ to solve. A conflict of ends cannot be resolved by the use of techniques derived from applied research. It is rather through the non-technical process of framing the problematic situation that we may organize and clarify both the ends to be achieved and the possible means of achieving them. (p. 41)

The goal, or the ‘ends’, for any design problem needs to be invented by each designer approaching that problem. Designers make moves in the context of their understanding of a design problem, where ‘the very invention of a move or hypothesis depends on a normative framing of the situation, a setting of some problems to be solved’ (Schön Reference Schön1984, p.132).

It is significant that the understanding of a design problem is rarely set in stone. Throughout designing, the designer’s understanding of the task is ongoingly revisited and the understanding of a problem evolves in parallel with the understanding of potential solutions (Poon & Maher Reference Poon and Maher1997; Dorst & Cross Reference Dorst and Cross2001). Framing is thus an ongoing activity throughout the design process and is sometimes referred to as reframing following an initial framing (Paton & Dorst Reference Paton and Dorst2011; Stompff, Smulders, & Henze Reference Stompff, Smulders and Henze2016).

2.4. Three definitions of design frames based on where they are found

A significant part of the ambiguity around frames is that definitions tend to focus on what frames do rather than what they are. A prerequisite for understanding what design frames are is understanding where they are located in relation to a designer. In reviewing the broader literature, three definitions of design frames can be described based on where frames are located. For some, frames as located within the internal world of cognition, while, for others, they are a type of representation and are external to cognition. For a third group, frames are tools for thinking that are defined by their ability to move between representation and cognition. This distinction relies upon the useful shorthand of ‘internal’ and ‘external’ (in relation to a designer) to avoid the philosophical arguments (which are ongoing) about where exactly this distinction lies (e.g., Williamson Reference Williamson2006).

First, a design frame can be thought of as internal to an individual designer and part of their cognitive structure. Multiple strands of design cognition literature posit this notion using a variety of different terms, such as mental models (Dong, Kleinsmann, & Deken Reference Dong, Kleinsmann and Deken2013), situations (Gero & Kannengiesser Reference Gero and Kannengiesser2004), design prototypes (Gero Reference Gero1990), and object worlds (Bucciarelli Reference Bucciarelli1994). The notion that design frames are conceptual structures is implicit in the literature on problem and solution spaces (Dorst & Cross Reference Dorst and Cross2001), the seeing-moving-seeing of reflection-in-action (Schön & Wiggins Reference Schön and Wiggins1992), and design metacognition (Ball & Christensen Reference Ball and Christensen2019). For Schön, the nature of these cognitive structures is as sensemaking narratives (Schön & Rein Reference Schön and Rein1994).

Second, a design frame can be understood as an external representation, such as when a designer uses speech, sketching, or diagrammatic representations to reveal aspects of their internal understanding (see examples in Dorst Reference Dorst2015, Sosa et al. Reference Sosa, Connor and Corson2017). Requirements in a design competition might be considered an external representation of a frame. A designer can describe what they are trying to do in a way that might be said to ‘capture the design frame’. Laursen and Haase (Reference Laursen and Haase2019) provide examples of this kind of ‘problem framing’. In the example cited earlier, Schön states that ‘Quist criticizes [Petra’s] framing of the problem’ based upon seeing her actions and hearing what she says, implying that frames are externalisable.

Finally, design frames can be understood as tools that exist within the liminal space between the internal and the external. An understanding of a design problem can be represented externally and can cross and re-cross the intrinsic-extrinsic divide. Dorst (Reference Dorst2015) adopts this third notion in defining frames as ‘…tools that exist within a world of actions and intentions’ and that ‘whether some metaphor or pattern of relationships can be called a ‘frame’ is completely defined by its use’ (p. 65). In this view, a frame that has been represented externally can be used as a ‘tool for thinking’ about the design problem. It is not just the internal structure held by an individual, nor is it a single explicit representation such as a set of statements. It exists in the relation between the two as a synthesis of an external representation and the way that this representation is interpreted and used. For example, design teams iteratively share and interpret representations of a design problem to develop shared mental models (Dong et al. Reference Dong, Kleinsmann and Deken2013), and this view of design frames is useful for understanding how teams of designers share norms (Hey Reference Hey2008; Zahedi & Heaton Reference Zahedi and Heaton2017).

These three different locations of design frames, combined with prior understandings of what framing does, can be used to synthesise three definitions for an answer to the question of what are design frames? that are implicit within the literature:

  1. (i) Design frames are conceptual assemblages: Designers, when addressing a design problem, conduct some cognitive activity that leads them to develop a set of concepts (where, following Chandrasegaran et al. Reference Chandrasegaran, Lloyd, Akdag Salah, Lockton, Lenzi, Hekkert, Oak, Sádaba and Lloyd2022, that term includes values, beliefs, propositions, objects, symbols, etc.). A design frame is the singular name given to that conceptual structure, which is revealed through design moves/actions or utterances/representations.

  2. (ii) Design frames are externalised representations of an understanding: Designers, use their understanding of a design problem to develop externalised representations of that understanding, such as speech or sketching. These representations of ‘how this problem might be understood’ are design frames and can exist independently of any designer.

  3. (iii) Design frames are tools for thinking: Designers, use their understanding of a design problem to develop representations of that understanding, such as through speech or sketching. These representations of ‘how this problem might be understood’ do work in the world as tools for thinking (either for oneself or for other designers). It is the combination of the representation and the moves/actions in relation to it that constitute the design frame.

3. Design frames in empirical studies

These three definitions can be put to work in identifying confusion within the literature. Table 1 lists seven selected empirical studies of design framing, which cover over almost four decades. These studies all purport to be studying this same phenomenon – design framing – yet utilise different definitions of what are meant by frames and framing and use methods that demonstrate this confusion.

Table 1. Selected empirical studies of framing organised chronologically, with methods of identification and cognitive commitments

For Kvan and Gao (Reference Kvan, Gao and Gero2006), problem framing is ‘the act of problem definition’ (p. 246) and is ‘a developmental process involving systemic transformation’ (p. 247). They identify framing as a design process that involves activities of conjecture, setting rules, and planning. In their method, framing activity is inferred from a design protocol when a designer identifies a new design problem or interprets further from the design brief. They make an implicit commitment to the first definition of design framing.

In contrast, Silk et al. (Reference Silk, Rechkemmer, Daly, Jablokow and Mckilligan2021) state that ‘While a problem can be reframed in multiple ways, individuals’ interpretations of a framing can vary considerably’ (p. 6). For Silk et al. (Reference Silk, Rechkemmer, Daly, Jablokow and Mckilligan2021) frames are external and need to be interpreted by designers, much like a design statement. The method in their study is described with students being assigned to, or receiving, either innovative or adaptive frames. In this way, they adopt the second of our three definitions of framing.

The third definition of design frames is best characterised by Valkenburg and Dorst (Reference Valkenburg and Dorst1998), who pioneered the approach of identifying (within the discourse of a design protocol) the places where a team of designers are verbally naming the features of attention and creating a frame for action; then conducting design moves and reflecting upon those moves and their consequences. They recognise that ‘a designer is actively constructing a view of the world based on his/her experiences’ (p. 251), forming the frame internally; yet it is through sharing the frame with the team that it can be the basis for ‘move-testing experiments (involving action and reflection)’, what Schön (Reference Schön1984) refers to as frame experiments.

There is some recurring slippage between the second and third definitions of design frames. Valkenburg and Dorst (Reference Valkenburg and Dorst1998) go on to say that ‘When the team frames a (sub)problem or (partial) solution to explore further on, then we code the context as a “frame”’ (p. 255). This introduces some ambiguity: a ‘frame’ is something that a team holds, the (imputed) shared context for their actions, rather than an indication of the view of the world of any one designer.

Further confusion is found in the most recent studies. Chandrasegaran et al. (Reference Chandrasegaran, Lloyd, Akdag Salah, Lockton, Lenzi, Hekkert, Oak, Sádaba and Lloyd2022) refer to the notion of a design team having a ‘primary frame within a design conversation’ (Ibid, p. 13) and also to the ability to see ‘frames interacting’ within a protocol. This implies a view of a team as having multiple frames. Yet the nomenclature is lacking: there is discussion of multiple frames and a primary frame, but no recognition that individual team members might have different design frames. They define frames as ‘social or rhetorical constructions that allow different perspectives to be explored in designing. These perspectives include values, beliefs, propositions, objects, symbols, etc. and they are explored through a process of “moving” or “action”’ (Ibid, p. 4). Yet is this a definition of what it is that the team shares? Does the team’s ‘primary frame’ include beliefs and values, or are they held by individuals within the team, overlapping to differing degrees? Hey et al. (Reference Hey, Joyce and Beckman2007) grapple with this same issue:

Frames are cognitive and thus are held implicitly by individuals. Even though they are not readily observable by others, frames can be more or less shared as a team frame to the extent to which the individual members’ frames overlap or align… no single method has been able to reliably tease apart individual frames from team frames, or to examine the differences between individual members’ frames. (pp. 81–82)

In their view, frames are held by individuals (are internal) and can come to be shared by members of a design team (where those frames overlap or align). However, they are basing their analysis on the method employed by Valkenburg and Dorst (Reference Valkenburg and Dorst1998) which leads to methodological challenges that are explicitly recognised:

Even with this multitude of data, finding framing is challenging: frames are cognitive, often implicit, and reside in the minds of individuals. For teams to negotiate a shared frame, an individual’s frame must be shared explicitly or otherwise suggested through interactions and behaviours. Thus in our observations, we looked for activities and interactions that either: (a) revealed an individual’s implicit frame to others; (b) made discrepancies between individuals’ frames visible or salient; or (c) engaged the team in explicitly negotiating among individual frames and constructing a shared frame. (pp. 84–85)

This extract suggests a need for a more effective nomenclature for frames; a way to differentiate between internal design frames (‘frames are cognitive’), how they are represented externally (‘an individual’s frame must be shared explicitly…’), and the way that frames move around as tools for thinking and come to be shared by teams.

This brief review of selected empirical studies of design framing reveals the present state of confusion. There has been consensus about the phenomenon of framing in designers and in design teams since Schön’s work in 1983: it is that part of designing concerned with setting the context within which design activity takes place. However, it is not clear what frames themselves are: where they are found and how to research them in ways that lead to valuable insights.

4. Reviewing perspectives on design frames

This review of design frames has demonstrated that (a) there are at least three different definitions of design frames in the literature and (b) these definitions have led to a range of applications of the term in empirical studies. Yet the construct of a design frame is demonstrably useful for design research. This section reviews a propositional model of what design frames do that articulates the importance of design framing and discusses design frames in relation to the constructs of object worlds, situations, mental models, and problem spaces.

4.1. A propositional model of what design frames do

A widely adopted understanding of the importance of design framing is described by Dorst (Reference Dorst2011) as the ‘the core of design thinking’. This can be considered as a propositional model for what design frames do. This model involves three parts: there is a WHAT, those things that are being attended to by a designer, a HOW, as a hypothesis or working principle for designing, and a VALUE, which is the designerly goal of this WHAT and HOW. This leads to Dorst’s formulation that:

(1) $$ {\displaystyle \begin{array}{l}\mathbf{WHAT}\hskip0.36em +\hskip0.36em \mathbf{HOW}\hskip2.04em \mathrm{leads}\ \mathrm{to}\;\mathbf{VALUE}\\ {}\left(\mathrm{thing}\right)\hskip0.48em \left(\mathrm{working}\ \mathrm{principle}\right)\hskip1.68em \left(\mathrm{aspired}\right)\end{array}} $$

The crux of design problems is that neither the WHAT nor the HOW are given to a designer: designers have the goal that they are working towards, but an incomplete sense of what they need to attend to for achieving that goal (WHAT is unknown); and no hypothesis for how to realise this goal is inherent in the problem (HOW is unknown). This is what Dorst refers to as Abduction-2 or design reasoning, where both the WHAT and the HOW are unknown: in such situations, it is unclear how a designer is able to commence doing anything towards realising the value:

(2) $$ ???+???\hskip0.36em \mathrm{leads}\ \mathrm{to}\;\mathbf{VALUE} $$

This distinction between two types of abduction – Abduction-1 and Abduction-2 – is useful for understanding how designers escape this bind. In Abduction-2 both the HOW and the WHAT are unknown; as distinct from Abduction-1 in which just the WHAT is unknown. This notion of different types of abductive design reasoning has a history in the literature, as surveyed by Koskela, Paavola, and Kroll (Reference Koskela, Paavola and Kroll2018). Abductive reasoning was formulated in the philosophy of C. S. Pierce (1839–1914), and brought into the design literature by March (Reference March and March1976) through his discourse on design reasoning and by Coyne et al. (Reference Coyne, Rosenman, Radford, Balachandran and Gero1990). It was Roozenburg and Eekels (Reference Roozenburg and Eekels1995) who emphasised the distinction between exploratory abduction (Abduction-1) and innovative abduction (Abduction-2) as being of importance for design.

Designers escape the bind of Abduction-2 (Equation 2, with two unknowns) through adopting a design frame, following Schön (Reference Schön1983). A design frame, in propositional terms, is defined by Dorst as encompassing both the HOW and the VALUE:

Frames are… very complex sets of statements that include the specific perception of a problem situation, the (implicit) adoption of certain concepts to describe the situation, a ‘working principle’ that underpins a solution and the key thesis: IF we look at the problem situation from this viewpoint, and adopt the working principle associated with that position, THEN we will create the value we are striving for. (p. 525)

Often a designer knows what they are trying to achieve, and by adopting a particular way of understanding the problem – a frame that includes both HOW and VALUE – they are then able to work on the problem. By adopting a frame, a designer no longer requires Abduction-2; they are in a position of using Abduction-1, in which a working principle can be combined with a goal to start thinking about a WHAT. The challenge is to adopt the right design frame to permit useful design activity – something that expert designers seem to be good at, and a form of expertise that remains poorly understood.

Why the propositional model of framing matters

This propositional model of design frames does the work of uniting two threads within the design literature. First, Schön (Reference Schön1983) described frames in the context of design as a reflective practice: designers have a design frame and conduct moves as ‘experiments’ that are reflected upon, and the frame changed based on those experiments. Second, March (Reference March and March1976) and others have looked at the abductive logic inherent in design reasoning. Dorst’s propositional model combines the two and this understanding has been used to identify framing strategies that are used by expert designers (Dorst Reference Dorst2015). This in turn has led to articulation of a series of activities that are useful to undertake when wanting to refine a design frame (e.g., analysing the history of the problem owner and the initial formulation) (Dorst Reference Dorst2015). These can be understood as high-level strategies that are associated with what expert designers do. The propositional model is a clear explication of the well-recognised cognitive property of design: that designers are able to commence design activity without knowing either what they need to do or how they need to work.

The case studies described by Schön (Reference Schön1984), Schön and Wiggins (Reference Schön and Wiggins1992), Akin and Akin (Reference Akin and Akin1996), Valkenburg and Dorst (Reference Valkenburg and Dorst1998), Suwa, Gero, and Purcell (Reference Suwa, Gero and Purcell2000), and many others since have demonstrated explicit occurrences of phenomena in which changing the frame has a significant change to the space of possible designs. Returning to the Einstein quote that opened this paper, design problems often have clear solutions once a ‘satisfactory’ frame has been found.

4.2. Disambiguation from related constructs

The construct of design frames can be further understood by juxtaposition with other constructs within the design literature that are related. This section reviews the constructs of object worlds, situations, mental models, and problem spaces and describes how each relates to design frames.

Bucciarelli (Reference Bucciarelli1994) introduced the term object world to recognise that different designers have ‘different competencies, skills, responsibilities and interests, [and] inhabit different worlds’ (Bucciarelli Reference Bucciarelli2002, p. 220). Any two people have different internal worlds or umwelts (Von Uexküll Reference Von Uexküll and Schiller1957) based on their sensory experiences of the world. The object world is an extension of the umwelt, where each designer also has their own technical competencies, and their own internal language for design (Bucciarelli Reference Bucciarelli2002). This can be observed when studying a design team, where multiple designers might be working on the same object, yet each does so from within their own object world: ‘the ways of modeling, thinking about the design, the questions one raises, the way they are framed, the resources one has to call into play in response, all of this is in accord with the paradigmatic technique which provides the basis for thought and practice within that world and differs from that of another participant… There is one object of design, but different object worlds’ (Bucciarelli Reference Bucciarelli2003, p. 222). Design frames are, for Bucciarelli, one part of the totality that makes up the object world of a designer: a design frame is a part of an object world and is brought into being within an object world.

Situated cognition recognises that concepts are tied to the situation within which they are used: the environmental, social, and cognitive contexts for learning and knowledge use (Brown, Collins, & Duguid Reference Brown, Collins and Duguid1989; Clancey Reference Clancey1997; Barsalou Reference Barsalou, Coello and Fischer2016). The idea of design as a situated activity has been used to describe certain design phenomena (Gero Reference Gero, Grabowski, Rude and Green1998; Suwa et al. Reference Suwa, Gero and Purcell2000; Gero & Kannengiesser Reference Gero and Kannengiesser2004; Kelly & Gero Reference Kelly and Gero2017). A situation as taken to be an emergent cognitive construct, a conceptual assemblage that is composed of perception, proprioception, introspective states (e.g., emotions), and environmental settings (Barsalou Reference Barsalou, Coello and Fischer2016, p. 627). Design frames are, similarly, conceptual assemblages yet a design frame is just one part of a situation (which is in turn the present-moment construct of an object world): those parts concerned with the interpretation of the problem and conceptions for ways of working.

The term mental model refers to the conceptual constructs and relationships between them that model the world and permit deductive reasoning about it (Johnson-Laird Reference Johnson-Laird1983). Mental models have been used within the design literature to explore the way that members of design teams come to share the same understanding of a problem (Dong et al. Reference Dong, Kleinsmann and Deken2013; Xiang et al. Reference Xiang, Sun, Chen, Yang and Liu2015). Design frames can be talked about as mental models of a design problem, yet this latter view can be reductive in that it neglects a situated understanding of conceptualisation; the term often entails a commitment to a classical understanding of concepts as ungrounded, amodal representations.

The notion of problem spaces within the design literature (Poon & Maher Reference Poon and Maher1997; Dorst & Cross Reference Dorst and Cross2001), as distinct from solution spaces, is relevant to design framing. This is an understanding that ‘the problem space and the solution space co-evolve together, with interchange of information between the two spaces’ (Dorst & Cross Reference Dorst and Cross2001, p. 434). However, the bifurcation of the internal world of a designer into two distinct parts, although useful in discussing designing, is contrary to contemporary understandings of human cognition as single system of conceptualisation (e.g., Barsalou Reference Barsalou, Coello and Fischer2016). From a grounded cognition perspective, both problem and solution space are emergent features of a situation that includes a design frame.

5. Discussion

This review paper has described multiple origins of the term frame within sociology, artificial intelligence, psychology, and traced the path of the term design frame into design literature. It has described confusion around the location of design frames, where they are variously considered as being internal (to designers), external, or liminal tools that cross this internal/external divide. It has shown that this lack of clarity has resulted in a history of empirical studies that purport to be studying design frames yet that hold different accounts of what design frames are meant to be and where they are located. It has reviewed Dorst’s propositional model of design frames and shown how the term relates to relevant constructs within the literature. This section considers the nomenclature of design frames, suggests that it would be valuable to develop a cognitive model of design framing, and looks towards further research into design framing that may lead to the development of such a situated cognitive model.

5.1. Nomenclature for design frames

As has been noted, there is ambiguity around the location of design frames: whether they are internal, external, or liminal to a designer. There is a need for nomenclature to make it possible to speak precisely about design frames as occurring within a designer’s cognition (what we are referring to as ‘internal’) and design frames as externalised (‘external’). This is necessary for talking about teams framing design problems and coming to shared understandings (e.g., Zahedi & Heaton Reference Zahedi and Heaton2017) or tracing the development of design frames through time. Table 1 demonstrates some of the contortions that can arise without this clarity. Clear nomenclature could allow for delineation between design frame as ‘implicit within a designer’ and design frame as ‘explicit within design actions/utterances’.

One option for more precise nomenclature could be through developing a convention that a design frame is the implicit, conceptual assemblage that represents the frame within cognition; and that such frames are then made explicit (such as through speech) in what are representations of a design frame. An example of the utility for this nomenclature is to return to the idea of ‘individuals’ interpretations of a framing’ (Silk et al. Reference Silk, Rechkemmer, Daly, Jablokow and Mckilligan2021) which is an ambiguous construction when contrasted with the idea that ‘Frames are cognitive and thus are held implicitly by individuals’ (Hey, Joyce, & Beckman Reference Hey, Joyce and Beckman2007). The latter already fits within the proposed nomenclature while the former could perhaps be rewritten as ‘individuals within a design team each interpret the shared representation of a design frame’.

Further ambiguity is found in the verb design framing which is now taught in some places as a skill in which designers can gain expertise (Dorst Reference Dorst2015; Sterling et al. Reference Sterling, Bailey, Spencer, Lampitt Adey, Chatzakis and Hornby2018) and is also analysed as something naturally occurring within design protocols (e.g., Valkenburg & Dorst Reference Valkenburg and Dorst1998). This leads to confusion around the distinction between design framing as a conscious metacognitive strategy or as a phenomenon intrinsic to design activity. Many expert designers do not consciously ‘do’ design framing so much as intuitively change the frame in useful ways (based, perhaps, upon well-developed metacognitive skills).

One way to avoid such ambiguity may be by adopting nomenclature to distinguish these two different bases for a change of frame. One option would be to refer to design framing as the conscious deployment of metacognitive strategies associated with useful development/refinement of a design frame. This can be distinguished from changes to a design frame as a term that external observers use when identifying the phenomena when observing designers. If such nomenclature were to be used, then the term reframing becomes unnecessary, a construct that confuses rather than clarifies.

5.2. Formal and cognitive models of design framing

Models of design processes that aim to represent design framing can be grouped into formal and cognitive models of design framing. A limitation of formal models is that they do not claim to represent human design cognition. There is an absence of cognitive models of design framing within the literature.

The phenomenon of design framing can be explained by some formal models of design (e.g., those reviewed by Hatchuel et al. Reference Hatchuel, Le Masson, Reich and Weil2011, Rodriguez & Benavides Reference Rodriguez and Benavides2021). Formal models of design processes are those that describe a set of constructs and the functions through which those constructs result in design phenomena. For example, in C-K theory (Hatchuel & Weil Reference Hatchuel and Weil2009), design is modelled as the generative interaction between two kinds of expansion (Hatchuel et al. Reference Hatchuel, Le Masson, Reich and Subrahmanian2018), one relating to logical propositions and another relating to conceptual (nonlogical) propositions. Rodriguez and Benavides (Reference Rodriguez and Benavides2021) formally model design framing using C-K theory and provide a ‘preliminary model for ranking [engineering design theories and methods] for framing, according to three characteristics’ (p. 284) of a problem domain independence, generativity, and a formal definition of valuable outcome or process.

The constructs proposed within cognitive models of design processes have the added requirement of being plausible representations of how human cognition functions (Hay et al. Reference Hay, Duffy, Mcteague, Pidgeon, Vuletic and Grealy2017). Recent decades have seen widespread acceptance that human cognition is grounded, embodied, and situated both within cognitive science (Barsalou Reference Barsalou2008) as well as design cognition (Gero Reference Gero, Grabowski, Rude and Green1998; Hay, Cash, & Mckilligan Reference Hay, Cash and Mckilligan2020). Cognitive models of design processes are open to critique on the basis that they are often difficult to falsify. While the methods available to empirically investigate cognitive models of design processes remain limited, the methods available in future are expanding (Gero & Milovanovic Reference Gero and Milovanovic2020; Hay et al. Reference Hay, Cash and Mckilligan2020). Future combinations of design cognition and design neurocognition methods (e.g., Hu et al. Reference Hu, Shealy, Gero, Milovanovic and Ignacio2022; Manandhar et al. Reference Manandhar, Hu, Milovanovic, Shealy and Gero2022) may lead to the possibility of experiments that test detailed hypotheses about design framing phenomena using methods outlined by Gero and Milovanovic (Reference Gero and Milovanovic2020).

5.3. Towards a cognitive model of design frames

There remains an absence of detailed, contemporary cognitive models for design framing; this is surprising given the importance of the phenomenon. There is a rich vein of cognitive theorising about design framing at a high level of abstraction, from Schön (Reference Schön1983) through to Dorst (Reference Dorst2015). Yet attempts to understand how conceptual co-ordination within a contemporary understanding of cognition leads to design framing phenomena cannot be found within the literature. A cognitive model of design framing would include a commitment to what is meant by the construct of a design frame. This section reviews some ideas within the literature that we believe would be useful in developing such a cognitive model of design frames.

A situated understanding

The understanding of cognition as situated conceptualisation has some explanatory power for the phenomenon of design frames. There is a shift from traditional 20th century understandings of cognition in that ‘cognition doesn’t exist as an independent symbolic module in the brain, but critically depends on the modalities, body, and environment… cognition emerges as the brain, body, and environment coordinate situated action’ (Barsalou Reference Barsalou2017). The contribution of situated cognition is to recognise that concepts are always used within a situation, which is to say in the presence of other concepts, perceptual information from an environment, and influence of emotions.

The situation within which a concept is used changes how that concept is used. Concepts should not be thought of as discrete atoms of knowledge that can be ‘used’; the computational analogy of ‘retrieving something from memory’ is misleading. A more useful analogy is of a good architect who knows how to design houses; each time they respond to a brief, the house that they produce will be site-specific and inhabitant-specific – they have no ability to design some ‘canonical house’ which embodies their house-designing ability. So it is with concepts, which are used within situations. This situated nature of concepts is supported by empirical studies that showing a range of phenomena relating to priming effects and the constructive nature of memory (Barsalou Reference Barsalou, Coello and Fischer2016).

Concepts for conceptual development

For Dorst (Reference Dorst2015) a design frame is a ‘very complex sets of statements that include the specific perception of a problem situation, the (implicit) adoption of certain concepts to describe the situation, a ‘working principle’ that underpins a solution and the key thesis’ (p. 525). What is the cognitive model of processes that are able to generate these very complex sets of statements?

One cognitive component of design frames may be that they include some conceptual representation of a goal state. As this is design activity, the goal state relates to a concept that does not presently exist in the world of the designer. This goal state also needs to have some kind of perceived value for the designer, following March (Reference March and March1976), Coyne et al. (Reference Coyne, Rosenman, Radford, Balachandran and Gero1990), and Dorst (Reference Dorst2011), as a definitional part of design activity – this is the motivation for design activity that persists even as the conception of the goal state changes.

A second component of design frames may be that they include a recursive conception of plans for how to test the design frame, which Schön refers to as frame experiments. This might be concepts for actions that aim to develop the goal state (e.g., ideation activities), actions that develop the conception of value (e.g., design research), or actions that aim to understand future actions (e.g., a design process).

How design frames change

It is clear that design frames change as a part of design activity. A grounded cognitive model of design frames could be useful for hypothesising different reasons why and how changes to design frames occur. Four examples of how this may occur can be hypothesised as follows:

  1. (i) Endogenous, to the design frame: The design frame may, as a part of the frame for action, require changes to the situation.

  2. (ii) Endogenous, to the situation: The situation, as a complex conceptual structure, may become incoherent in some way (e.g., self-contradictory), leading the conceptual system to change its structure.

  3. (iii) Endogenous, to the person: Some form of hedonic reward for a certain level of novelty may make static situations an unlikely prospect due to innate pleasure in a changing situation (e.g., Saunders & Gero Reference Saunders and Gero2004). Other emotional/embodied responses to a situation (e.g., disgust) might lead to a changing situation.

  4. (iv) Exogenous: Perceived changes in the environment may introduce new concepts into the situation. This may include interactions with other beings, interpretation of representations, or any other environmental trigger.

Conceptual distance and framing

There are moments where a designer – to an external observer – appears to have radically changed their understanding of a problem (Akin & Akin Reference Akin and Akin1996; Suwa et al. Reference Suwa, Gero and Purcell2000). Yet there are also many moments where a designer may only be subtly changing the design frame in ways that are tangential to the problem. It may be useful to the study of designers to distinguish between the two.

The notion of conceptual space has been posited by Gärdenfors (Reference Gärdenfors2004) as a way that concepts might be represented in such a way that the notion of distance becomes applicable. Examples have been given in prior work of ways in which conceptual spaces may be brought together within situations in a way that makes distance a situational phenomenon (Kelly & Gero Reference Kelly and Gero2017; Perišić, Štorga, & Gero Reference Perišić, Štorga and Gero2019; Gero & Milovanovic Reference Gero, Milovanovic, Lockton, Lenzi, Hekkert, Oak, Sádaba and Lloyd2022). It follows that there may be a way of comparing the design frames of a designer at different points in time and being able to calculate some meaningful measure of distance between design frames, expressed as a unit within conceptual space.

Current research using natural language processing techniques (NLP) to analyse design protocols can be understood through this lens. Such work starts with externalisations of design frames (utterances) and creates statistical models from these words (using models of natural language) that can be seen to change over time. The distance between statistical models at different points of time then becomes a proxy for changes to a design frame.

Design frames within a team

Each member in a design team can be considered to have their own situation, and (in designing) their own design frame(s). It follows that it may be possible to speak of some degree of coherence between design frames of the members in a design team. This idea has been discussed at length within the literature. Bucciarelli (Reference Bucciarelli2002) observed that ‘engineers designing…are faced with the task of frequently bringing the results of their object world efforts, which no doubt will conflict, into coherence if design is to proceed – and they must do this without a shared proper language’ (p. 228). There is a thread in the literature exploring how this coherence is achieved, such as the work by Dong et al. (Reference Dong, Kleinsmann and Deken2013) combining latent semantic analysis and reflective practice analysis to show how team mental models come to be shared over time. The definition of design frames in this paper may contribute to this thread by providing a more precise way of investigating coherence in design frames within a team over time – perhaps through application of graph analysis of conceptual maps and/or through distance measures within conceptual space.

6. Conclusion

This paper has reviewed some of the ambiguity around the concept of design frames. It has discussed the origins of the term frame and how it came to be used in design studies. It has clarified three different definitions of design frames within the literature and has reviewed empirical studies of design framing to demonstrate contradictions between studies. It has reviewed Dorst’s propositional model of design frames and the value that it serves and positioned design frames in terms of related concepts within the design literature. It has discussed the value of having a grounded cognitive model of design frames and provided some directions that may be fruitful to achieve this.

Acknowledgments

This research is supported in part by a grant to the second author from the US National Science Foundation, Grant No. EEC-1929896. Any opinions, findings, and conclusions or recommendations expressed in this material are those of the authors and do not necessarily reflect the views of the National Science Foundation.

Footnotes

1 Schön cites James and Dewey in his notes, in The Reflective Practitioner, writing ‘Dewey proposed that problems are constructed from situations of indeterminacy, problematic situations, that we apprehend through the experience of worry, trouble, or doubt’ (p. 357).

References

Akin, Ö. & Akin, C. 1996 Frames of reference in architectural design: analysing the hyperacclamation (Aha-!). Design Studies 17, 341361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bailey, M., Spencer, N., Smith, N., Aftab, M., Knott, C. & Sams, P. 2018 Framing strategic value through design-led innovation practice. In DS 92: Proceedings of the DESIGN 2018 15th International Design Conference, pp. 17811792. Design Society.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ball, L. J. & Christensen, B. T. 2019 Advancing an understanding of design cognition and design metacognition: Progress and prospects. Design Studies 65, 3559; doi:10.1016/j.destud.2019.10.003.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barsalou, L. W. 2008 Grounded cognition. Annual Review of Psychology 59, 617645; doi:10.1146/annurev.psych.59.103006.093639.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Barsalou, L. W. 2016 Situated conceptualization: Theory and applications. In Foundations of Embodied Cognition: Perceptual and Emotional Embodiment (ed. Coello, Y. & Fischer, M. H.). Routledge/Taylor & Francis Group.Google Scholar
Barsalou, L. W. 2017 Define design thinking. She Ji: The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation 3, 102105; doi:10.1016/j.sheji.2017.10.007.Google Scholar
Bartlett, F. C. 1932 Remembering: A Study in Experimental and Social Psychology. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bateson, G. 1972 Steps to an Ecology of Mind: Collected Essays in Anthropology, Psychiatry, Evolution, and Epistemology. University of Chicago Press; doi:10.7208/chicago/9780226924601.001.0001.Google Scholar
Borah, P. 2011 Conceptual issues in framing theory: A systematic examination of a decade’s literature. Journal of Communication 61, 246263; doi:10.1111/j.1460-2466.2011.01539.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, J. S., Collins, A. & Duguid, P. 1989 Situated cognition and the culture of learning. Educational Researcher 18, 3242.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bucciarelli, L. L. 1994 Designing Engineers. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Bucciarelli, L. L. 2002 Between thought and object in engineering design. Design Studies 23, 219231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bucciarelli, L. L. 2003 Designing and learning: A disjunction in contexts. Design Studies 24, 295311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chandrasegaran, S., Lloyd, P. & Akdag Salah, A. 2022 Identifying problem frames in design conversation. In Proceedings of DRS2022 Bilbao (ed. Lockton, D., Lenzi, S., Hekkert, P., Oak, A., Sádaba, J. & Lloyd, P.), Design Research Society.; https://doi.org/10.21606/drs.2022.623Google Scholar
Clancey, W. J. 1997 Situated Cognition: On Human Knowledge and Computer Representations. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Coyne, R. D., Rosenman, M. A., Radford, A. D., Balachandran, M. & Gero, J. S. 1990 Knowledge Based Design Systems. Addison-Wesley Reading.Google Scholar
Dewey, J. 1910. How We Think. Courier Corporation; doi:10.1037/10903-000.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dong, A., Kleinsmann, M. S. & Deken, F. 2013 Investigating design cognition in the construction and enactment of team mental models. Design Studies 34, 133; doi:10.1016/j.destud.2012.05.003.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dorst, K. 2011 The core of ‘design thinking’ and its application. Design Studies 32, 521532; doi:10.1016/j.destud.2011.07.006.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dorst, K. 2015 Framing Innovation. The MIT Press; doi:10.7551/mitpress/10096.001.0001.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dorst, K. & Cross, N. 2001 Creativity in the design process: Co-evolution of problem–solution. Design Studies 22, 425437; doi:10.1016/S0142-694X(01)00009-6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gärdenfors, P. 2004 Conceptual Spaces: The Geometry of Thought. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gero, J. S. 1990 Design prototypes: A knowledge representation schema for design. AI Magazine 11, 2626.Google Scholar
Gero, J. S. 1998 Towards a model of designing which includes its situatedness. In Universal Design Theory (ed. Grabowski, H., Rude, S. & Green, G.). Shaker Verlag.Google Scholar
Gero, J. S. & Kannengiesser, U. 2004 The situated function–behaviour–structure framework. Design Studies 25, 373391; doi:10.1016/j.destud.2003.10.010.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gero, J. S. & Milovanovic, J. 2020. A framework for studying design thinking through measuring designers’ minds, bodies and brains. Design Science 6, E19; doi:10.1017/dsj.2020.15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gero, J. S. & Milovanovic, J. 2022 Creation and characterization of design spaces. In Proceedings of the DRS 2022 (ed. Lockton, D., Lenzi, S., Hekkert, P., Oak, A., Sádaba, J. & Lloyd, P.), Design Research Society; doi:10.21606/drs.2022.265.Google Scholar
Goffman, E. 1974 Frame Analysis: An Essay on the Organization of Experience. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Grant, M. J. & Booth, A. 2009 A typology of reviews: An analysis of 14 review types and associated methodologies. Health Information & Libraries Journal 26, 91108.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gray, C. M. 2019 Revealing students’ ethical awareness during problem framing. International Journal of Art & Design Education 38, 299313.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hatchuel, A., Le Masson, P., Reich, Y. & Subrahmanian, E. 2018 Design theory: A foundation of a new paradigm for design science and engineering. Research in Engineering Design 29, 521.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hatchuel, A., Le Masson, P., Reich, Y. & Weil, B. 2011. A systematic approach of design theories using generativeness and robustness. In DS 68–2: Proceedings of the 18th International Conference on Engineering Design (ICED 11), Impacting Society through Engineering Design (Vol. 2): Design Theory and Research Methodology, Lyngby/Copenhagen, Denmark, Technical University of Denmark. pp. 8797.Google Scholar
Hatchuel, A. & Weil, B. 2009 CK design theory: An advanced formulation. Research in Engineering Design 19, 181192.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hay, L., Cash, P. & Mckilligan, S. 2020 The future of design cognition analysis. Design Science 6, e20; doi:10.1017/dsj.2020.20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hay, L., Duffy, A. H., Mcteague, C., Pidgeon, L. M., Vuletic, T. & Grealy, M. 2017 Towards a shared ontology: A generic classification of cognitive processes in conceptual design. Design Science 3, E7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henriques, I. 2018 Addressing wicked problems using new business models. Economic Alternatives 4, 463466.Google Scholar
Hey, J. H. G. 2008 Effective Framing in Design. ProQuest Dissertations Publishing.Google Scholar
Hey, J. H., Joyce, C. K. & Beckman, S. L. 2007 Framing innovation: Negotiating shared frames during early design phases. Journal of Design Research 6, 7999.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hu, M., Shealy, T., Gero, J. S., Milovanovic, J. & Ignacio, P. 2022 Brain and behavior in engineering design: An exploratory study on concept mapping. In Design Computing and Cognition ’22, University of Strathclyde, Glasgow.Google Scholar
James, W. 1890. The Principles of Psychology, Cosimo, Inc.; doi:10.1037/10538-000.Google Scholar
Johnson-Laird, P. N. 1983 Mental Models: Towards a Cognitive Science of Language, Inference, and Consciousness. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D. & Tversky, A. 1984 Choices, Values, and Frames. Handbook of the Fundamentals of Financial Decision Making: Part I. World Scientific; doi:10.1142/9789814417358_0016.Google Scholar
Kelly, N. & Gero, J. S. 2017 Generate and situated transformation as a paradigm for models of computational creativity. International Journal of Design Creativity and Innovation 5, 149167; doi:10.1080/21650349.2016.1203821.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koskela, L., Paavola, S. & Kroll, E. 2018. The role of abduction in production of new ideas in design. In Advancements in the Philosophy of Design. Springer; doi:10.1007/978-3-319-73302-9_8.Google Scholar
Kvan, T. & Gao, S. 2006 A comparative study of problem framing in multiple settings. In Proceedings of Design Computing and Cognition ‘06 (ed. Gero, J. S.). Springer.Google Scholar
Laursen, L. N. & Haase, L. M. 2019 The shortcomings of design thinking when compared to designerly thinking. The Design Journal 22, 813832; doi:10.1080/14606925.2019.1652531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manandhar, U., Hu, M., Milovanovic, J., Shealy, T. & Gero, J. S. 2022 Concept maps decrease neurocognitive demand on students when thinking about engineering problems. In ASCE Construction Research Congress, American Society of Civil Engineers.Google Scholar
March, L. 1976 The logic of design and the question of value. In The Architecture of Form (ed. March, L.). Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Markie, P. & Folescu, M. 2004. Rationalism vs. empiricism. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy [Online], online document https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rationalism-empiricism. Last accessed: 1st September, 2022.Google Scholar
Mcdonnell, J. 2018 Design roulette: A close examination of collaborative decision-making in design from the perspective of framing. Design Studies 57, 7592.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Minsky, M. 1974. A Framework for Representing Knowledge. Tech. Report, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.Google Scholar
Münch, J., Trieflinger, S. & Heisler, B. 2020. Product discovery–building the right things: Insights from a grey literature review. In 2020 IEEE International Conference on Engineering, Technology and Innovation (ICE/ITMC), Cardiff, UK, pp. 18. IEEE; doi:10.1109/ICE/ITMC49519.2020.9198328.Google Scholar
Paton, B. & Dorst, K. 2011 Briefing and reframing: A situated practice. Design Studies 32, 573587.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perišić, M. M., Štorga, M. & Gero, J. 2019. Situated novelty in computational creativity studies. In 10th International Conference on Computational Creativity ICCC19. Association for Computational Creativity, pp. 268290.Google Scholar
Poon, J. & Maher, M. L. 1997 Co-evolution and emergence in design. Artificial Intelligence in Engineering 11, 319327; doi:10.1016/S0954-1810(96)00047-7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rein, M. & Schön, D. 1996 Frame-critical policy analysis and frame-reflective policy practice. Knowledge and Policy 9, 85104; doi:10.1007/BF02832235.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rodriguez, J. B. & Benavides, E. M. 2021 Engineering design principles as patterns of relationships in frame creation. Research in Engineering Design 32, 271288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roozenburg, N. F. & Eekels, J. 1995 Product Design: Fundamentals and Methods. Wiley.Google Scholar
Saunders, R. & Gero, J. S. 2004 Curious agents and situated design evaluations. AI EDAM 18, 153161.Google Scholar
Schön, D. A. 1983 The Reflective Practitioner: How Professionals Think in Action. Routledge; doi:10.4324/9781315237473.Google Scholar
Schön, D. A. 1984 Problems, frames and perspectives on designing. Design Studies 5, 132136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schön, D. A. & Rein, M. 1994 Frame Reflection: Toward the Resolution of Intractable Policy Controversies. Basic Books.Google Scholar
Schön, D. A. & Wiggins, G. 1992 Kinds of seeing and their functions in designing. Design Studies 13, 135156; doi:10.1016/0142-694X(92)90268-F.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schutz, A. 1962 The Problem of Social Reality. Collected Papers. Springer; doi:10.1007/978-94-017-1077-0.Google Scholar
Silk, E. M., Rechkemmer, A. E., Daly, S. R., Jablokow, K. W. & Mckilligan, S. 2021 Problem framing and cognitive style: Impacts on design ideation perceptions. Design Studies 74, 101015.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Snow, D. A. 2007 Frame. In The Blackwell Encyclopedia of Sociology (ed. Ritzer, G.). Wiley; doi:10.1002/9781405165518.wbeosf064.Google Scholar
Sosa, R., Connor, A. M. & Corson, B. 2017. Framing creative problems. In Handbook of Research on Creative Problem-Solving Skill Development in Higher Education. IGI Global; doi:10.4018/978-1-5225-0643-0.ch021.Google Scholar
Spradlin, D. 2016 Are you solving the right problem? IEEE Engineering Management Review 44, 4754; doi:10.1109/EMR.2016.7792409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterling, N., Bailey, M., Spencer, N., Lampitt Adey, K., Chatzakis, M. & Hornby, J. 2018. From conflict to catalyst: Using critical conflict as a creative device in design-led innovation practice. In The 21st DMI: Academic Design Management Conference Proceedings; ADMC18: Next Wave. The Design Management Institute.Google Scholar
Stompff, G., Smulders, F. & Henze, L. 2016 Surprises are the benefits: Reframing in multidisciplinary design teams. Design Studies 47, 187214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suwa, M., Gero, J. & Purcell, T. 2000 Unexpected discoveries and S-invention of design requirements: Important vehicles for a design process. Design Studies 21, 539567; doi:10.1016/S0142-694X(99)00034-4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Valkenburg, R. & Dorst, K. 1998 The reflective practice of design teams. Design Studies 19, 249271; doi:10.1016/S0142-694X(98)00011-8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Der Bijl-Brouwer, M. 2019 Problem framing expertise in public and social innovation. She Ji: The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation 5, 2943; doi:10.1016/j.sheji.2019.01.003.Google Scholar
Verhoeven, J. 1993 An interview with Erving Goffman, 1980. Research on Language and Social Interaction 26, 317348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Von Uexküll, J. 1957 A stroll through the worlds of animals and men. In Instinctive Behaviour: The Development of a Modern Concept (ed. Schiller, C. H.). International Universities Press.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. 2006. Can cognition be factorised into internal and external components. In Contemporary Debates in Cognitive Science, pp. 291306. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Xiang, W., Sun, L., Chen, S., Yang, Z. & Liu, Z. 2015 The role of mental models in collaborative sketching. International Journal of Technology and Design Education 25, 121136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zahedi, M. & Heaton, L. 2017. A model of framing in design teams. Design and Technology Education, 22, n2.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1. Selected empirical studies of framing organised chronologically, with methods of identification and cognitive commitments