Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dlnhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T20:41:44.700Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

(B.) FOLIT-WEINBERG Homer, Parmenides, and the Road to Demonstration. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2022. Pp. xvi + 367, illus. £90. 9781316517819.

Review products

(B.) FOLIT-WEINBERG Homer, Parmenides, and the Road to Demonstration. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2022. Pp. xvi + 367, illus. £90. 9781316517819.

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 October 2023

A.G. Long*
Affiliation:
University of St Andrews
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Reviews of Books: Philosophy
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Society for the Promotion of Hellenic Studies

In the Odyssey, Odysseus receives instructions from Circe after he returns from Hades. When she starts to describe the Planctae and then Scylla and Charybdis (12.55–126), she first invites Odysseus to think over how to navigate past them, but then explains that it would be disastrous to sail close to Charybdis and futile to fight Scylla. In the 1950s Eric Havelock argued that this episode influenced Parmenides’ presentation of a choice, given to him by a goddess, between ways only one of which is rational (‘Parmenides and Odysseus’, HSCP 63 (1958), 133–43). Alexander Mourelatos then argued briefly, in his wide-ranging study of epic form in Parmenides, that the structural parallel between Parmenides’ poem and Circe’s speech, with a choice between routes, explanations and instructions, is ‘even more exact’ than Havelock realized (The Route of Parmenides (New Haven 1970; Las Vegas 2008), 24 n.38). Now a new book on Homer and Parmenides, claiming to draw inspiration from Mourelatos, says to him what he had said to Havelock: the parallel ‘may be even more precise than Mourelatos spells out’ (217 n.1).

Benjamin Folit-Weinberg’s treatment is, however, distinctive. First, there is a much narrower focus on Circe’s instructions in Odyssey 12. The author insists that this passage, rather than other parts of Homeric epic, Hesiod or later poetry, is the primary intertext for Parmenides. Folit-Weinberg protests that he is not defending a ‘single-mindedly Homeric reading of Parmenides’ (185), but this rings hollow. He denies comparable significance to Hesiod, Xenophanes and other poets, and argues that, in respects in which Parmenides resembles Homer, Homer is ‘entirely unlike’ Hesiod and others (216 n.69). Secondly, Folit-Weinberg develops an elaborate and sophisticated account of hodos (path) as a way of organizing discourse into description, narrative, instructions and explanation, or, in his words, a ‘rhetorical schema’. The application of this to Parmenides is the most successful aspect of the book. Early epic and didactic poems offer several ways of presenting information or instructions in a comprehensive and systematic manner (theogony, catalogues, hodos), and Parmenides found the last of them most suitable for his own poem (or, we should say, for some parts of it, but not the Doxa). Folit-Weinberg provides a chapter that is ostensibly about the Doxa, but in fact about further connections between the Odyssey and the Way of Persuasion. I was disappointed to see that it does not ask why Parmenides uses an alternative to the hodos schema in the Doxa: theogony.

Thirdly, Folit-Weinberg presents the connection between Parmenides and Odyssey 12 as the solution to a question of origins: how did Parmenides invent ‘extended deductive argumentation’ (a phrase repeated very often)? Answer: by treating Circe’s instructions to Odysseus as a ‘blueprint’ that shows how to structure a combination of argument, guidance and description. Logical deduction thus becomes a descendant of Homeric narrative sequence. Here I was puzzled by Folit-Weinberg’s disinclination to look beyond Odyssey 12 to other examples of early argumentation, Homeric and otherwise, and to grant that less ‘extended’ arguments, in earlier literature and philosophy, made some contribution to the design of Parmenides B8. Homeric poetry is full of characters reasoning with and trying to persuade one another, and Circe’s attempt to guide Odysseus is just one example. Why not explore other Homeric scenes of debate and speech-giving when looking for antecedents to the Way of Persuasion? Xenophanes is mentioned but given short shrift, even though Aristotle attributes to him arguments that sound like pre-echoes of Parmenides: for example, it is as impious to say that gods were generated as to say that they die, as either way there is a time when they do not exist (Rhetoric 2.23 1399b6–9, cf. the choice in 1400b5–8). It would have been better to combine the suggestion that the large-scale architecture of Parmenides’ poem was modelled on parts of Odyssey 12 with more inclusive consideration of early arguments.

Finally, in the first part of the book Folit-Weinberg considers archaeological evidence for the ancient rut roads whose grooves ‘locked’ a wagon or chariot into a route. He argues that these roads provided Parmenides with a powerful resource for expressing directedness and logical coercion. This part of the book is especially likely to intrigue specialists on early Greek philosophy, most of whom are already familiar with comparisons between Parmenides and Homer but unsure where to find good archaeological work on physical roads. As readers pass from the material on rut roads to the comparison with Odyssey 12, many, I expect, will ask themselves how one and the same intellectual enterprise can resemble both the ‘locking in’ of a rut road and an Odyssean voyage, where a detour is always possible, and what the relative importance of the two motifs is. Folit-Weinberg eventually answers that question, but tucks away the answer in a detour of his own (section 6.3.1, 258): the motifs are not combined, but rather the journey is transferred from sea to land, or from ship to chariot. There is a mismatch between this view of their relation and the book’s design: across the book as a whole, discussion of Odyssey 12 predominates, but, according to this section, it is the rut road that more accurately represents Parmenides’ journey.