Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7fkt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-24T20:32:15.689Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - Introduction

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 September 2022

Alexandre K. Monro
Affiliation:
Royal Botanic Gardens, Kew
Simon J. Mayo
Affiliation:
Royal Botanic Gardens, Kew

Summary

This Systematics Association Special Volume is the result of a symposium entitled, ‘Cryptic taxa - artefact of classification or evolutionary phenomena?’ held on June 17 as part of the Association’s 10th Biennial Meeting 2019. I began to realise that the notion of cryptic species touches the heart of several major debates in biology, including, ‘what are species?’, ‘how should we recognize them?’, the notion of punctuated equilibria and that of morphological stasis in the fossil record. Also, in the midst of a biodiversity crisis the phenomenon of cryptic species suggests that there may be a greater diversity of evolutionary lineages in need of conservation than has been suggested. The chapters that emerged from the Symposium show clearly how the topic of 'species' remains central to biodiversity sciences and the subject of wide-ranging and lively debate. In almost every chapter there is a call for change, either of direction or for the inclusion of new developments and data, and their focus ranges from abandoning species altogether to highlighting the weaknesses in current taxonomic process suggesting that our representation of the biological universe is still a chaotic torso.

Type
Chapter
Information
Cryptic Species
Morphological Stasis, Circumscription, and Hidden Diversity
, pp. 1 - 13
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2022

Introduction

This Systematics Association Special Volume is the result of a symposium titled, ‘Cryptic Taxa – Artefact of Classification or Evolutionary Phenomena?’ held on 17 June as part of the association’s 10th Biennial Meeting in 2019. The symposium comprised five presentations, Torsten Struck, Paul Williams, Matt Lavin, Mark Wilkinson and Jim Labisko. For the purposes of this volume, we also invited contributions by Cene Fišer and Klemen Koselj, Alexander Martynov and Tatiana Korshunova, Simon Mayo, Richard Bateman, Marta Álvarez-Presas, and Pablo Muñoz, with the aim of providing a broader perspective on the subject, not only with respect to theory and practice but also with respect to the organisms that they work on.

My motivation for organising the meeting was scepticism. Scepticism that stemmed from the feeling that what was being observed were species whose evolutionary history had resulted in strong genetic partitioning, and that in the absence of a universally accepted species concept, it was arbitrary to designate the rank of species based on DNA alone for organisms where other sources of observations are available. Second, as a taxonomist tasked with producing field guides, identification keys, and identifying biological collections in herbaria, I did not welcome the prospect of taxa that are impossible to identify without access to a DNA laboratory and funds, the latter being difficult to access even in world-leading biological collections institutions.

The first time that I encountered the concept of cryptic species was in the mid-1990s, at which time they were novel and controversial. In the last decade, however, with the wide availability of DNA sequence observations and improved techniques for extracting DNA from biological collections, the description of cryptic species is becoming commonplace (Figure 1.1), including of hitherto well-known species: For example, the Tapanuli Orangutan (Pongo tapanuliensis, Nater et al. Reference Nater, Mattle-Greminger and Nurcahyo2017), the Baltic flounder (Platichthys solemdali, Momigliano et al. Reference Momigliano, Denys, Jokinen and Merilä2018), or the Kabomani Tapir (Tapirus kabomani, Cozzuol et al. Reference Cozzuol, Clozato and Holanda2013); but also amongst many less well-known groups of organisms, for example, sponges (Xavier et al. Reference Xavier, Rachello-Dolmen and Parra-Velandia2010), marine interstitial ghost-worms (Cerca et al. Reference Cerca, Meyer, Purschke and Struck2020), copepods (Fišer et al. Reference Fišer2015), roundworms (Armenteros et al. Reference Armenteros, Ruiz-Abierno and Decraemer2014), flatworms (Álvarez-Presas et al. Reference Álvarez-Presas, Amaral, Carbayo, Leal-Zanchet and Riutort2015; Leria et al. Reference Leria, Vila-Farré and Álvarez-Presas2020), malaria parasites (alveolates, Bensch et al. Reference Bensch, Péarez-Tris, Waldenströum and Hellgren2004), sea-slugs (Korshunova et al. Reference Korshunova, Fletcher and Picton2020), rotifers (Gabaldón et al. Reference Gabaldón, Serra, Carmona and Montero-Pau2015; Mills et al. Reference Mills, Alcántara-Rodríguez and Ciros-Pérez2017), cod icefish (Dornburg et al. Reference Dornburg, Federman, Eytan and Near2016), lizards (Leavitt et al. Reference Leavitt, Bezy and Crandall2007), ferns (Bauret et al. Reference Bauret, Gaudeul and Sundue2017), mosses (McDaniel and Shaw Reference McDaniel and Shaw2003), fungi (Muggia et al. Reference Muggia, Kocourkova and Knudsen2015), and bumblebees (Williams et al. Reference Williams, Cannings and Sheffield2016).

Figure 1.1 Frequency of papers with ‘cryptic’ and ‘species’ in the title (1990–2020).

Source: Scopus search ‘TITLE-ABS-KEY (cryptic AND & AND species)’, 2021 (undertaken 14 June 2021).

Preparing for the symposium, I began to realise that the notion of – and process of discovery for – cryptic species touches the heart of several major debates in biology, including ‘what are species?’, ‘how should we recognise them?’, the notion of punctuated equilibria, and that of morphological stasis in the fossil record. In addition, in the midst of a biodiversity crisis (Koh et al. Reference Koh, Dunn and Sodhi2004) the phenomenon of cryptic species indicates that there may be a greater diversity of evolutionary lineages in need of conservation than has been suggested by morphology alone (Funk et al. Reference Funk, Caminer and Ron2012; Chapters 811), implying the need for a more nuanced approach to species conservation (Carroll et al. Reference Carroll, Jørgensen and Kinnison2014).

Rather than simply being a distracting artefact of new sequencing technologies, phylogenetic techniques, and opportunism, any consideration of the notion of cryptic species exposes a fundamental and well-documented weakness of contemporary systematic biology: that we do not yet have the conceptual framework or the quality and breadth of observations to be able to say what a species is, and, as a result, to assert crypsis in relation to one. Striving to resolve some of the debates around cryptic species might not only provide the tools and framework to answer some major questions in biology but also make taxon delimitation and the documentation of diversity a more rigorous and useful scientific undertaking.

This book is organised to present overviews of cryptic (sibling) species in the context of species delimitation and the taxonomic method (Chapters 24), followed by reviews of cryptic species concepts and their value to evolutionary biology (Chapters 58) and then some case examples from diverse groups of organisms (Chapters 3, 5, 911).

1.1 Were There Cryptic Species before Darwin?: Cryptic Species and the Concepts of Species

Cryptic species are, logically, by-products of the application of a species concept to group a set of individuals into units referred to as ‘species’. The notion of species as units of diversity predates classical Candollean, Linnean, and Aristotelian attempts to classify diversity and can be found in all human cultures (Atran Reference Atran1998; Berlin Reference Berlin1973, Reference Berlin1992; Berlin et al. Reference Berlin, Breedlove and Raven1974; Bulmer et al. Reference Bulmer, Menzies and Parker1968; Coyne Reference Coyne and Orr2004; Diamond Reference Diamond1966; Ludwig Reference Ludwig2017; Majnep and Bulmer Reference Majnep and Bulmer1977; Mayr Reference Mayr1963; Slater Reference Slater2015). It also likely occurs, at a biological level at least, amongst non-humans (Poelstra et al. Reference Poelstra, Vijay and Bossu2014; Robinson et al. Reference Robinson, Twiss and Hazon2015).

The term ‘species’ originated in the fourteenth century (Online Etymological Dictionary 1993). It denotes, ‘appearance, form, kind’ (Oxford University Press 1993) and as such is congruent with morphological species concepts. The notion of species as real entities (‘natural things’) that existed in nature rather than defined by humans dates back at least to Locke (Locke Reference Locke and Nidditch1689, see also Mayo (Chapter 2)). The notion that species are the product of an evolutionary process is most closely associated with Darwin, who emphasised such a relationship in the title of his epoch-defining work, The Origin of Species (Darwin Reference Darwin1859). Since Darwin first linked the phenomenon of species to that of evolution, most systematic biologists equate species with separately evolving lineages – equivalent to branches of the ‘Tree of Life’ (e.g. De Queiroz Reference De Queiroz2007; Padial and De la Riva Reference Padial and De la Riva2021), with the logical consequence that the basis and process of species delimitation centres on assigning individuals to a phylogenetic lineage (see Chapter 2 for context). Freudenstein et al. (Reference Freudenstein, Broe, Folk and Sinn2016) and Chapter 8 argue, however, that lineage divergence alone is not sufficient to delimit species. Templeton (Reference Templeton, Endler and Otte1989), under his ‘Cohesion Species Concept’, rather than focussing on isolation or divergence, applies explicitly evolutionary criteria to define species as, ‘the most inclusive group of organisms having the potential for genetic and/or demographic exchangeability’ (Templeton Reference Templeton, Endler and Otte1989: 181).

For practical and academic reasons (see Chapter 2), there are now probably as many ways to assign an individual to a species as there are taxonomists doing so, a situation referred to as the ‘species problem’ (Mayden Reference Mayden and Claridge1997). Compounding this, even if there was agreement on the criteria for delimiting species, we would rarely have the resources to do so confidently, either with respect to the number of populations sampled or with respect to the observations made from each. The reality is that the incidental evidence (Padial and De la Riva Reference Padial and De la Riva2021) or operational criteria (De Queiroz Reference De Queiroz2007) used in the delimitation of the vast majority of species comprise just two classes of observations, morphological and/or molecular (DNA sequence), from a very small sample of individuals (Chapters 3, 4, and 9). Morphological evidence formed the basis of species delimitation for all groups of organisms for over 250 years, albeit mostly from the very small, arbitrary, and biased sample of characters preserved in biological collections and mostly interpreted outside of any explicit hypothesis of homology or species. For the last 25 years, the sequence of nucleotides in DNA has provided an independent class of observations for which increasingly robust statistical analyses have been developed, incorporating complex mathematical inferences for evolutionary phenomena (e.g. coalescent, Bayesian, substitution models), to delimit putative evolutionary lineages. DNA sequence observation, however, also suffers from very small sample sizes, both with respect to the proportion of populations sampled and, to a lesser and varying extent, to the proportion of the genome sampled. As implied by allopatry, geography, sometimes in association with ecological niche, is also a source of observations for the delimitation of species and subspecies (Darwin Reference Darwin1859; Jordan Reference Jordan1905; Rensch Reference Rensch1938) across many species concepts and frequently underpins the decision to delimit new taxa. With the exception of the rank of subspecies, however, geographical observations are rarely applied formally for the purposes of species delimitation but are generally held to be confirming factors (Davis and Heywood Reference Davis and Heywood1963) or ‘soft characters’ (see Chapter 5).

Morphological, DNA sequence, and geographical observations are just three out of an increasing number that could be available for taxon delimitation. For example, developmental (ontogenetic), physiological, transcriptomic, proteomic, behavioural, ecological niche, ecological network, immunological, biochemical, and holobiome could all provide observation useful in testing hypotheses of species, but they have been largely ignored for the process of species delimitation (Chapters 3 and 4). Both Bateman (Chapter 3) and Martynov and Korshunova (Chapter 4) suggest that no species would likely be considered cryptic were there adequate sampling of populations and morphology together with the inclusion of additional sources of observations, such as ontogenetic (Chapter 4), chemical, electrical, magnetic, sensory, ecological (Chapters 7 and 8), or were morphological characters to be observed and evaluated adequately (Chapter 3) from an effective sample of populations (Chapters 3 and 4).

Within the context of crypsis, discordance between DNA sequence and morphological estimates of divergence can result in two phenomena, (1) that of cryptic species, whereby DNA sequence observations suggest lineage divergence equivalent to a distinct species but morphological observations do not, or (2) of polymorphic species, where morphologically distinct species are suggested by DNA sequence observations to represent a single lineage (Chapter 8; Dexter et al. Reference Dexter, Pennington and Cunningham2010). This latter group of species has been the focus of far less research.

It is the lack of congruence between the, arguably superficial (Chapter 3) sampling of morphological and DNA sequence observations and their use as incidental evidence that has fuelled a renewed interest in and description of cryptic species. Basically, DNA sequence observations are suggesting greater or lesser lineage divergence than morphological observations and where greater, then this is being used to propose morphologically cryptic lineages at the rank of species. This lack of congruence could be attributed to the identification of early diverging lineages, equivalent to De Queiroz’s ‘gray zone’ of speciation (De Queiroz Reference De Queiroz2007: Fig. 1; Chapter 7). Struck and Cerca (Chapter 6) and Muñoz et al. (Chapter 5) suggest, however, that this is not the usual case, with crypsis being identified in lineages up to 140 million years old (Chapter 6). In order to prevent early-diverging lineages from being designated as cryptic species, Struck (Struck et al. Reference Struck, Feder and Bendiksby2018a, Reference Struck, Feder and Bendiksbyb; Chapter 6) proposes that one should explicitly show that the species are morphologically more similar to each other than would be expected given the time that has passed since their last common ancestor. This is something that is possible to establish, with some degree of error, using DNA sequence observations and/or fossils.

Given the limitations of sample size and bias in the taxonomic process, it could be argued that the current state of knowledge on species can best be described as superficial or tokenistic, as suggested by Bateman (Chapter 3). As a result, we do not have the necessary observations to formulate or apply universal species concepts. More useful is a less mechanistic definition such as Templeton’s Cohesion Species Concept (Templeton Reference Templeton, Endler and Otte1989), or the flexibility to delimit species which conspecific genetic samples resolve as paraphyletic (Freudenstein et al. Reference Freudenstein, Broe, Folk and Sinn2016; Muñoz-Rodríguez et al. Reference Muñoz-Rodríguez, Carruthers and Wood2019; Pennington and Lavin Reference Pennington and Lavin2016; Chapter 8) and a more rigorous circumscription (see Chapter 3), applied with the recognition of the limitations of our sampling and methods, may, therefore, be more useful for the purposes of exploring evolution, but also for the establishment of a stable classification of life on earth. Within such a context, cryptic species could be viewed as nodes (Chapters 3, 5–8) for which there is evidence of lineage divergence but not of morphological change.

1.2 Cryptic Species, Morphological Stasis: Artefacts of Taxonomic Method

The fact that the definition of cryptic species is problematic does not mean that the phenomena it highlights are not important. In fact, it may be that the use of the term ‘cryptic species’ within a jungle of problematic species concepts has prevented a key phenomenon, morphological stasis, from getting the research focus it should have. With hindsight, the great debate over the tempo of evolution (punctuated equilibria, gradualism) occurred prematurely, prior to the ‘molecular revolution’ that has enabled the pairing of the palaeontological perspective of morphology with evaluations of lineage divergence.

There are several reasons for the discordance between DNA sequences and morphological observations. Some of these can be considered experimental error, whereby prior to the application of DNA sequence observations, the delimitation of a species was based on too few morphological observations. For example, the bumblebee, Bombus kluanensis (Williams et al. Reference Williams, Cannings and Sheffield2016; Chapter 8), was initially recognised from a coalescent analysis of a small subsample of the mitochondrial genome (COX1, Williams et al. Reference Williams, Berezin and Cannings2019). This triggered a morphological re-evaluation of the biological collections that recovered diagnostic morphological character states. Another example is the Tapanuli Orangutan (Pongo tapanuliensis, Nater et al. Reference Nater, Mattle-Greminger and Nurcahyo2017), for which cranio-mandibular and dental characters (albeit from a single individual) were identified following analyses of whole mitochondrial genomes. In both cases, the species turned out not to be cryptic, as morphological differences were observable. They had just not been detected earlier.

There are, however, many cases where morphological crypsis is confirmed and five evolutionary processes can be proposed to account for these (Chapters 6, 810): (I) recent lineage divergence that has not yet resulted in morphological divergence, (II) parallel or (III) convergent morphological evolution, (IV) morphological stasis, or (V) introgression. Evidence for all five has been observed for cryptic species (Chapters 6 and 7). These are all, however, distinct, testable, evolutionary phenomena that are not best served by being combined or obscured under the term ‘cryptic species’ (Chapter 6). Of these phenomena, recent lineage divergence and convergence have been the subject of substantial research effort by evolutionary and population biologists. Parallelism, effectively representing convergence within closely related lineages, has also been the subject of some research from speleo- (Gross Reference Gross2016; Khalik et al. Reference Khalik, Bozkurt and Schilthuizen2020; Powers et al. Reference Powers, Berning and Gross2020) and hydrothermal vent biologists (Yuan et al. Reference Yuan, Zhang and Gao2020).

Morphological stasis, however, remains relatively little studied outside palaeontology (Gingerich Reference Gingerich2019), despite being a major feature of the paleontological record (Gould Reference Gould2002; Stanley Reference Stanley1979) and presumably of evolution. In addition, the explanations for stasis have been controversial (Davis et al. Reference Davis, Schaefer and Xi2014), with both genetic-developmental constraints and stabilising selection being invoked (Charlesworth and Lande Reference Charlesworth and Lande1982; Davis et al. Reference Davis, Schaefer and Xi2014; Estes and Arnold Reference Estes and Arnold2007; Raff Reference Raff1996; Smith Reference Smith1981). Understanding the causes and implications of morphological stasis in evolution could therefore provide a productive research focus for which cryptic species would be key study organisms/scenarios. It is for this reason that the definition, terminology, and methods used in the recognition of such taxa are important.

Beyond morphological stasis, cryptic species are probably best referred to using terms that highlight the evolutionary phenomena more clearly, such as ‘convergence’, ‘parallelism’, or a term explicitly indicative of lineage divergence, such as ‘ochlospecies’ (Chapter 8). Struck’s proposal – that the term ‘cryptic species’ should be restricted to morphological stasis, defined as lineages morphologically more similar to each other than one would be expected given time since lineage divergence – is useful and pragmatic as highlighted earlier in the chapter.

Delimiting species solely on lineage divergence is pragmatic where there is an abundance of DNA sequence observations and a paucity of other observations. It does, however, invoke operational criteria as definitional concepts, a practice subject to substantial epistemological criticism (De Queiroz Reference De Queiroz2007). Perhaps more importantly, incongruence between morphological and lineage divergence, whilst identifying important evolutionary phenomena, should not automatically be translated into taxonomic actions. Rather, the identification of incongruence between DNA sequence and morphological observations should be the starting point for hypothesis-testing and the generation of observations from additional sources. For example, the use of geographical, ontogenetic, physiological, behavioural, ecological, and chemical observations. Where these observations corroborate the DNA sequence observations then there is sense in recognising the metapopulation or lineage using a taxonomic rank.

It could be argued that adopting such an approach effectively weights morphological observations over DNA sequence ones. This I think is the reality of a taxonomy designed by and for people, and for a multiplicity of uses.

1.3 Taxonomy Is Not Just About Documenting Evolution

Taxonomy concerns the construction of classifications in general. Here we refer to that long-term enterprise undertaken by biological scientists that results in a classification and identification system founded on species taxa, named according to international codes of nomenclature. This framework, which is intended to encompass all organic life, serves the needs of a range of audiences and applications. Biological classification takes place within a constrained resource, both with respect to observations but also to the number of people delivering it and the narrow window of time in which it is taking place. Scientific practitioners are heavily influenced by evolutionary theory and for many this demands an assumed link between species as units of both diversity and the evolutionary process, but for other users, classification serves as a tool and surrogate for predicting properties (traits) related to usefulness, for measuring biological diversity, for predicting and mitigating the impacts of human activities, and for developing and testing theories about the history of life on earth (evolutionary biology, biogeography) and a shared understanding of the living world (aesthetic).

Evolutionary relationships have provided a robust framework for doing so and they are largely reflected in the classification of life. The aim of taxonomy is not, however, to reveal the footprint of evolution, but rather to use evolutionary relationships to provide a robust and stable classification and so make the universe of biodiversity accessible to all. A classification needs to meet the requirements for a well-documented and wide range of uses and users. It is the diversity of these, from local farmers, pharmacists, amateur naturalists, archaeologists, anthropologists, ecologists, environmental scientists, physicists to systematic and evolutionary biologists, that places an emphasis on morphometrics, broad predictiveness, and ease of diagnosis and makes taxonomy a fundamentally pragmatic undertaking. It is because of this need for accessibility and ease of diagnosis, the fact that the foundations of post-Linnean, ‘Candollean’ (or ‘natural’, see Chapter 2) taxonomy were built on morphological observations, and the importance of integrating fossils, that morphology remains key to species recognition. Whilst DNA sequence observations enable the assigning of individuals to phylogenetic lineages and so provide a major tool for species identification and delimitation, they are limited in their accessibility to a relatively small and wealthy group of academics, and commercial and government agencies. They also still rely on referencing a nomenclatural system wedded to (and so do not function outside of) morphology-based classifications.

1.4 How Best to Document Cryptic Species/Morphological Stasis in Nomenclature

To summarise, the term cryptic species is problematic on two levels. (1) It assumes a lineage-dominated view of species definition and delimitation, which results from a decision to apply operational criteria as definitional concepts. (2) Depending on the definition used (e.g. Struck et al. Reference Struck, Feder and Bendiksby2018b; Reference Struck, Feder and Bendiksbya; Chapter 6), it conflates and obscures noteworthy evolutionary phenomena, the most important of which is probably morphological stasis. Those phenomena are not best served by the status quo, whereby ‘cryptic’ species are described under new binomials that offer no indication of the sister cryptic species(s) and which cannot be diagnosed without the infrastructure and resources to generate DNA sequence observations.

For multicellular and many unicellular organisms, trinomials may be a more useful vehicle for naming cryptic taxa as they flag the relationship between cryptic ‘sister’ species. In the case of the International Code of Nomenclature for algae, fungi, and plants (Turland et al. Reference Turland, Wiersema and Barrie2018), the International Code of Nomenclature of Prokaryotes (Anon 2019), and the International Code of Zoological Nomenclature (Ride et al. Reference Ride, Cogger and Dupuis1999) there is the availability of subspecies as a rank, which would fit well within a heuristic framework and cohesive species concept. Within lineage-focussed concepts this may be problematic as there may be a perceived implication of incomplete lineage divergence. In the case of viruses, while the International Code of Virus Classification and Nomenclature does not provide a framework for subspecific ranks, which are devolved to specialist groups (International Committee on Taxonomy of Viruses 2005), there are groups of organisms for which nomenclatural codes do not permit trinomials.

Other notations are possible. Hybrid plant species (nothotaxa) are indicated by placing a multiplication sign before the species epithet (ICBN H.3A.1. 2018). For example, Verbascum × schiedeanum W. D. J. Koch indicates that the taxon is a hybrid. It is conceivable that a similar notation could be used to indicate cryptic status, although the use of the letter ‘c’ would need to be spaced in a way to avoid orthographic confusion. This would also require the concerted modification of nomenclatural codes, which in turn would require broad consensus, expressed by the votes of the systematics communities.

In the absence of a universal species concept, and given the heuristic nature of species delimitation and recognition, the use of subspecific rank is probably the best way to document morphological stasis.

The symposium and the papers that emerged from it and are presented here show clearly how the topic of ‘species’ remains central to biodiversity sciences and the subject of wide-ranging and lively debate. In almost every paper there is a call for change, either of direction or for the inclusion of new developments, and their focus ranges from abandoning species altogether (Chapter 4) to highlighting the fact that there is still no accessible reference system for the 300 years-worth of accumulated knowledge of species’ delimitation (Chapter 2): our representation of the biological universe is still a chaotic torso. Other authors highlight the need for international cooperation as the only meaningful basis for generating such a representation – a collective effort that requires long-term institutional investment – and that the methodology of monograph production requires a favourable institutional (and political) framework.

Taxonomists need to remember that species, as well as being the products of an evolutionary process, are also conventions on which this language and scientific facts are built (Fleck Reference Fleck1935). The issue of species as units of biological diversity, therefore, goes well beyond the relatively simple problem of scientific definition (Lherminier Reference Lherminier2015), because at its root what is involved in the notion of species is a key part of our mental language that we all need for understanding our living world. Now, more than ever, this is a language in which everybody has a stake, as we experience the mass extinction of biodiversity and the loss of the ecosystem services that are, at least in part, derived from them (Haines-Young and Potschin Reference Haines-Young, Potschin, Raffaelli and Frid2010).

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank all those who contributed chapters to this book and to the Systematics Association for their Conference Organization Grant. I would especially like to thank my co-editor Simon Mayo for his hard work on the manuscripts, his invaluable comments and suggestions on this Introduction, and his stimulating conversations and encyclopaedic knowledge of the history of taxon delimitation and of the so-often overlooked relevant German literature of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. I would also like to thank Raquel Negrao for help with the indexing of the book and Simon Mayo, Richard Bateman, and Tom Wells for stimulating conversations on the subjects of species concepts and taxonomy.

References

Álvarez-Presas, M., Amaral, S. V., Carbayo, F., Leal-Zanchet, A. M., and Riutort, M. (2015) Focus on the details: Morphological evidence supports new cryptic land flatworm (Platyhelminthes) species revealed with molecules. Organisms Diversity & Evolution 15: 379403. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13127–014-0197-zCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anon (2019) International Code of Nomenclature of Prokaryotes. International Journal of Systematic and Evolutionary Microbiology 69: S1S111. https://doi.org/10.1099/ijsem.0.000778CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armenteros, M., Ruiz-Abierno, A., and Decraemer, W. (2014) Taxonomy of Stilbonematinae (Nematoda: Desmodoridae): Description of two new and three known species and phylogenetic relationships within the family. Zoological Journal of the Linnean Society 171: 121. https://doi.org/10.1111/zoj.12126CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Atran, S. (1998) Folk biology and the anthropology of science: Cognitive universals and cultural particulars. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21: 547569. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X98001277Google Scholar
Bauret, L., Gaudeul, M., Sundue, M. A. A. et al. (2017) Madagascar sheds new light on the molecular systematics and biogeography of grammitid ferns: New unexpected lineages and numerous long-distance dispersal events. Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution 111: 117. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ympev.2017.03.005CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bensch, S., Péarez-Tris, J., Waldenströum, J., and Hellgren, O. (2004) Linkage between nuclear and mitochondrial DNA sequences in avian malaria parasites: Multiple cases of cryptic speciation? Evolution 58: 16171621. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.0014-3820.2004.tb01742.xGoogle Scholar
Berlin, B. (1973) Folk systematics in relation to biological classification and nomenclature. Annual Reviews 4: 259271.Google Scholar
Berlin, B. (1992) Ethnobiological Classification: Principles of Categorization of Plants and Animals in Traditional Societies. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berlin, B., Breedlove, D. E., and Raven, P. H. (1974) Principles of Tzeltal Plant Classification. Academic Press, New York and London.Google Scholar
Bulmer, R. N. H., Menzies, J. I., and Parker, F. (1968) Kalam classification of birds and reptiles. Journal of the Polynesian Society 84: 267308.Google Scholar
Carroll, S. P., Jørgensen, S. P., Kinnison, M. T. et al. (2014) Applying evolutionary biology to address global challenges. Science 346: 313323. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1245993CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cerca, J. Meyer, C., Purschke, G., and Struck, T. H. (2020) Delimitation of cryptic species drastically reduces the geographical ranges of marine interstitial ghost-worms (Stygocapitella; Annelida, Sedentaria). Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution 143: 106663. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ympev.2019.106663Google Scholar
Charlesworth, B. and Lande, R. (1982) Morphological stasis and developmental constraint: No problem for Neo-Darwinism. Nature 296: 610610. https://doi.org/10.1038/296610a0Google Scholar
Coyne, J. A. and Orr, O. H. (2004) Speciation. Sinauer Associates, Sunderland, MA.Google Scholar
Cozzuol, M. A., Clozato, C. L., Holanda, E. C. et al. (2013) A new species of tapir from the Amazon. Journal of Mammalogy 94: 13311345. https://doi.org/10.1644/12-MAMM-A-169.1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwin, C. (1859) On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life. John Murray, London.Google Scholar
Davis, C. C., Schaefer, H., Xi, Z. et al. (2014) Long-term morphological stasis maintained by a plant-pollinator mutualism. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 111: 59145919. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1403157111Google Scholar
Davis, P. H. and Heywood, V. H. (1963) Principles of Angiosperm Taxonomy. Oliver & Boyd, Edinburgh.Google Scholar
Dexter, K. G., Pennington, T. D., and Cunningham, C. W. (2010) Using DNA to assess errors in tropical tree identifications: How often are ecologists wrong and when does it matter? Ecological Monographs 80: 267286. https://doi.org/10.1890/09-0267.1Google Scholar
Diamond, J. M. (1966) Zoological classification system of a primitive people. Science 151: 11021104. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.151.3714.1102Google Scholar
Dornburg, A., Federman, S., Eytan, R. I., and Near, T.J. (2016) Cryptic species diversity in sub-Antarctic islands: A case study of Lepidonotothen. Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution 104: 3243. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ympev.2016.07.013Google Scholar
Estes, S. and Arnold, S. J. (2007) Resolving the paradox of stasis: Models with stabilizing selection explain evolutionary divergence on all timescales. The American Naturalist 169: 227244. https://doi.org/10.1086/510633Google Scholar
Fišer, Ž. et al. (2015) Morphologically cryptic Amphipod species are “ecological clones” at regional but not at local scale: A case study of four Niphargus species. PLoS ONE 10: e0134384. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0134384CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fleck, L. (1980 [1935]) Enstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache: Einführung in die Lehre vom Denkstil und Denkkollektiv. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main.Google Scholar
Freudenstein, J. V., Broe, M. B., Folk, R. A., and Sinn, B. T. (2016) Biodiversity and the species concept: Lineages are not enough. Systematic Biology 66: 644656. https://doi.org/10.1093/sysbio/syw098Google Scholar
Funk, W. C., Caminer, M., and Ron, S. R. (2012) High levels of cryptic species diversity uncovered in Amazonian frogs. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 279: 18061814. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2011.1653Google Scholar
Gabaldón, C., Serra, M., Carmona, M. J., and Montero-Pau, J. (2015) Life-history traits, abiotic environment and coexistence: The case of two cryptic rotifer species. Journal of Experimental Marine Biology and Ecology 465: 142152. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jembe.2015.01.016CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gingerich, P. D. (2019) Rates of Evolution: A Quantitative Synthesis. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Gould, S. J. (2002) The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Gross, J. B. (2016) Convergence and Parallelism in Astyanax Cave-Dwelling Fish: Evolutionary Biology. Springer, Cham, IL.Google Scholar
Haines-Young, R. and Potschin, M. (2010) The links between biodiversity, ecosystem services and human well-being. In: Raffaelli, D. G. and Frid, C. L. J. (eds.) Ecosystem Ecology: A New Synthesis. BES Ecological Reviews Series, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 110139.Google Scholar
International Committee on Taxonomy of Viruses (2005) The international code of virus classification and nomenclature of ICTV. Virus Taxonomy: Eighth Report of the International Committee on Taxonomy of Viruses: 1209–1214. Available from: https://talk.ictvonline.org/information/w/ictv-information/383/ictv-codeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jordan, K. (1905) Der Gegensatz zwischen geographischer und nichtgeogeographischer Variation. Zeitschrift für wissenschaftliche Zoologie 83: 15210.Google Scholar
Khalik, M. Z., Bozkurt, E., and Schilthuizen, M. (2020) Morphological parallelism of sympatric cave‐dwelling microsnails of the genus Georissa at Mount Silabur, Borneo (Gastropoda, Neritimorpha, Hydrocenidae). Journal of Zoological Systematics and Evolutionary Research 58: 648661. https://doi.org/10.1111/jzs.12352CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koh, L. P., Dunn, R. R., Sodhi, N. S. et al. (2004) Species coextinctions and the biodiversity crisis. Science 305: 16321634. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1101101CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Korshunova, T., Fletcher, K., Picton, B. et al. (2020) The Emperor’s Cadlina, hidden diversity and gill cavity evolution: New insights for the taxonomy and phylogeny of dorid nudibranchs (Mollusca: Gastropoda). Zoological Journal of the Linnean Society 189: 762827. https://doi.org/10.1093/zoolinnean/zlz126CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leavitt, D. H., Bezy, R. L., Crandall, K. A. et al. (2007) Multi-locus DNA sequence data reveal a history of deep cryptic vicariance and habitat-driven convergence in the desert night lizard Xantusia vigilis species complex (Squamata: Xantusiidae). Molecular Ecology 16: 44554481. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1365-294X.2007.03496.xCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Leria, L., Vila-Farré, M., Álvarez-Presas, M. et al. (2020) Cryptic species delineation in freshwater planarians of the genus Dugesia (Platyhelminthes, Tricladida): Extreme intraindividual genetic diversity, morphological stasis, and karyological variability. Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution 143: 106496. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ympev.2019.05.010CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lherminier, P. (2015) La valeur de l’espèce. La Pensée N° 383: 7585. https://doi.org/10.3917/lp.383.0075Google Scholar
Locke, J. (1689) An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. 1975 ed. Nidditch, P. H. (ed.) Clarendon Press, Oxford.Google Scholar
Ludwig, D. (2017) Indigenous and scientific kinds. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 68: 187212. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axv031Google Scholar
Majnep, I. S. and Bulmer, R. N. H. (1977) Birds of My Kalam Country. Auckland University Press, Oxford University Press, Auckland and Oxford.Google Scholar
Mayden, R. L. (1997) A hierarchy of species concepts: The denouement in the saga of the species problem. In: , H. A. D. and Claridge, M. R. W. M. F. (ed.) The Systematics Association Special Volume Series, Species: The Units of Diversity. Chapman & Hall, London, pp. 381423.Google Scholar
Mayr, E. (1963) Animal Species and Evolution. Belknap Press, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
McDaniel, S. F. and Shaw, A. J. (2003) Phylogeographic structure and cryptic speciation in the trans-Antarctic moss Pyrrhobryum minioides. Evolution 57: 205215. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.0014-3820.2003.tb00256.xGoogle Scholar
Mills, S., Alcántara-Rodríguez, J. A., Ciros-Pérez, J. et al. (2017) Fifteen species in one: Deciphering the Brachionus plicatilis species complex (Rotifera, Monogononta) through DNA taxonomy. Hydrobiologia 796: 3958. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10750–016-2725-7Google Scholar
Momigliano, P., Denys, G. P. J., Jokinen, H., and Merilä, J. (2018) Platichthys solemdali sp. nov. (Actinopterygii, Pleuronectiformes): A New flounder species from the Baltic Sea. Frontiers in Marine Science 5. https://doi.org/10.3389/fmars.2018.00225Google Scholar
Muggia, L., Kocourkova, J., and Knudsen, K. (2015) Disentangling the complex of Lichenothelia species from rock communities in the desert. Mycologia 107: 12331253. https://doi.org/10.3852/15-021Google Scholar
Muñoz-Rodríguez, P., Carruthers, T., Wood, J. R. I. et al. (2019) A taxonomic monograph of Ipomoea integrated across phylogenetic scales. Nature Plants 5: 11361144. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41477–019-0535-4Google Scholar
Nater, A., Mattle-Greminger, M. P., Nurcahyo, A. et al. (2017) Morphometric, behavioral, and genomic evidence for a new orangutan species. Current Biology 27: 34873498.e10. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cub.2017.09.047CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Online Etymological Dictionary (1993) species. Online Etymological Dictionary. www.etymonline.com/Google Scholar
Oxford University Press (1993) The New Shorter Oxford English Dictionary. Oxford University Press, Oxford.Google Scholar
Padial, J. M. and De la Riva, I. (2021) A paradigm shift in our view of species drives current trends in biological classification. Biological Reviews 96: 731751. https://doi.org/10.1111/brv.12676Google Scholar
Pennington, R. T. and Lavin, M. (2016) The contrasting nature of woody plant species in different neotropical forest biomes reflects differences in ecological stability. New Phytologist 210: 2537. https://doi.org/10.1111/nph.13724Google Scholar
Poelstra, J. W., Vijay, N., Bossu, C. M. et al. (2014) The genomic landscape underlying phenotypic integrity in the face of gene flow in crows. Science 344: 14101414. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1253226CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Powers, A. K., Berning, D. J., and Gross, J. B. (2020) Parallel evolution of regressive and constructive craniofacial traits across distinct populations of Astyanax mexicanus cavefish. Journal of Experimental Zoology Part B: Molecular and Developmental Evolution 334: 450462. https://doi.org/10.1002/jez.b.22932CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
De Queiroz, K. (1989) The general lineage concept of species, species criteria, and the process of speciation: A conceptual unification and terminological recommendations. In: Howard, S. H. B. D. J. (ed.) Endless Forms: Species and Speciation. Oxford University Press, New York, pp. 5775.Google Scholar
De Queiroz, K. (1999) The general lineage concept of species and the defining properties of the species category. In: Wilson, R. A. (ed.) New Interdisciplinary Essays. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp. 4989.Google Scholar
De Queiroz, K. (2007) Species concepts and species delimitation. Systematic Biology 56: 879886. https://doi.org/10.1080/10635150701701083Google Scholar
Raff, R. A. (1996) The Shape of Life: Genes, Development, and the Evolution of Animal Form. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.Google Scholar
Rensch, B. (1938) Some problems of geographical variation and species‐formation. Proceedings of the Linnean Society of London 150: 275285. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1095-8312.1938.tb00182k.xGoogle Scholar
Ride, W. D. L., Cogger, H. G., Dupuis, C. K. O. et al. (1999) International Code of Zoological Nomenclature. Fourth. The Natural History Museum, London, London.Google Scholar
Robinson, K. J., Twiss, S. D., Hazon, N. et al. (2015) Conspecific recognition and aggression reduction to familiars in newly weaned, socially plastic mammals. Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology 69: 13831394. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00265–015-1952-7Google Scholar
Slater, M. H. (2015) Natural kindness. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 66: 375411. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axt033Google Scholar
Smith, J. M. (1981) Macroevolution. Nature 289: 1314. https://doi.org/10.1038/289013a0Google Scholar
Stanley, S. M. (1979) Macroevolution, Pattern and Process. W. H. Freeman, San Francisco, 332 pp.Google Scholar
Struck, T. H., Feder, J. L., Bendiksby, M. et al. (2018a) Cryptic species – more than terminological chaos: A reply to Heethoff. Trends in Ecology & Evolution 33: 310312. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tree.2018.02.008Google Scholar
Struck, T. H., Feder, J. L., Bendiksby, M. (2018b) Finding evolutionary processes hidden in cryptic species. Trends in Ecology & Evolution 33: 153163. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tree.2017.11.007Google Scholar
Templeton, A. R. (1989) The meaning of species and speciation title. In: Endler, D. and Otte, J. A. (eds.) Speciation and Its Consequences. Sinauer Associates, Sunderland, MA, pp. 327.Google Scholar
Turland, N., Wiersema, J., Barrie, F. et al. eds. (2018) International Code of Nomenclature for Algae, Fungi, and Plants. Koeltz Botanical Books, Oberreifenberg, Germany.Google Scholar
Williams, P. H., Berezin, M. V., Cannings, S. G. et al. (2019) The arctic and alpine bumblebees of the subgenus Alpinobombus revised from integrative assessment of species’ gene coalescents and morphology (Hymenoptera, Apidae, Bombus). Zootaxa 4625: 168. https://doi.org/10.11646/zootaxa.4625.1.1Google Scholar
Williams, P. H., Cannings, S. G., and Sheffield, C. S. (2016) Cryptic subarctic diversity: A new bumblebee species from the Yukon and Alaska (Hymenoptera: Apidae). Journal of Natural History 50: 28812893. https://doi.org/10.1080/00222933.2016.1214294Google Scholar
Xavier, J. R., Rachello-Dolmen, P. G., Parra-Velandia, F. et al. (2010) Molecular evidence of cryptic speciation in the “cosmopolitan” excavating sponge Cliona celata (Porifera, Clionaidae). Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution 56: 1320. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ympev.2010.03.030Google Scholar
Yuan, J., Zhang, X., Gao, Y. et al. (2020) Adaptation and molecular evidence for convergence in decapod crustaceans from deep‐sea hydrothermal vent environments. Molecular Ecology 29: 39543969. https://doi.org/10.1111/mec.15610Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1.1 Frequency of papers with ‘cryptic’ and ‘species’ in the title (1990–2020).

Source: Scopus search ‘TITLE-ABS-KEY (cryptic AND & AND species)’, 2021 (undertaken 14 June 2021).

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×