Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7fkt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-24T08:27:44.714Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Measure equivalence rigidity via s-malleable deformations

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 August 2023

Daniel Drimbe*
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematics, KU Leuven, Celestijnenlaan 200b, B-3001 Leuven, Belgium [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We single out a large class of groups ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$ for which the following unique prime factorization result holds: if $\Gamma _1,\ldots,\Gamma _n\in {\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$ and $\Gamma _1\times \cdots \times \Gamma _n$ is measure equivalent to a product $\Lambda _1\times \cdots \times \Lambda _m$ of infinite icc groups, then $n \ge m$, and if $n = m$, then, after permutation of the indices, $\Gamma _i$ is measure equivalent to $\Lambda _i$, for all $1\leq i\leq n$. This provides an analogue of Monod and Shalom's theorem [Orbit equivalence rigidity and bounded cohomology, Ann. of Math. 164 (2006), 825–878] for groups that belong to ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$. Class ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$ is constructed using groups whose von Neumann algebras admit an s-malleable deformation in the sense of Sorin Popa and it contains all icc non-amenable groups $\Gamma$ for which either (i) $\Gamma$ is an arbitrary wreath product group with amenable base or (ii) $\Gamma$ admits an unbounded 1-cocycle into its left regular representation. Consequently, we derive several orbit equivalence rigidity results for actions of product groups that belong to ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$. Finally, for groups $\Gamma$ satisfying condition (ii), we show that all embeddings of group von Neumann algebras of non-amenable inner amenable groups into $L(\Gamma )$ are ‘rigid’. In particular, we provide an alternative solution to a question of Popa that was recently answered by Ding, Kunnawalkam Elayavalli, and Peterson [Properly Proximal von Neumann Algebras, Preprint (2022), arXiv:2204.00517].

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© 2023 The Author(s). The publishing rights in this article are licensed to Foundation Compositio Mathematica under an exclusive licence

1. Introduction

Classifying countable groups up to measure equivalence is a central topic in measured group theory that has witnessed an explosion of activity for the last 25 years, see the surveys [Reference ShalomSha05, Reference FurmanFur11, Reference GaboriauGab10] and the introduction of [Reference Horbez, Huang and IoanaHHI21]. The notion of measure equivalence has been introduced by Gromov [Reference GromovGro93] as a measurable analogue to the geometric notion of quasi-isometry between finitely generated groups. Specifically, two countable groups $\Gamma$ and $\Lambda$ are called measure equivalent if there exist commuting free measure-preserving actions of $\Gamma$ and $\Lambda$ on a standard measure space $(\Omega,m)$ such that the actions of $\Gamma$ and $\Lambda$ on $(\Omega,m)$ each admit a finite measure fundamental domain. Natural examples of measure equivalent groups are two lattices in a locally compact second countable group.

Measure equivalence can be studied through the lenses of orbit equivalence due to the fundamental result that two countable groups are measure equivalent if and only if they admit free ergodic probability measure-preserving (pmp) actions that are stably orbit equivalent [Reference FurmanFur99]. Recall that two pmp actions $\Gamma \curvearrowright (X,\mu )$ and $\Lambda \curvearrowright (Y,\nu )$ are called stably orbit equivalent if there exist non-null subsets $A\subset X, B\subset Y$ and a measure space isomorphism $\theta : A\to B$ such that $\theta (\Gamma x \cap A)= \Lambda \theta (x)\cap B$, for almost every $x\in A$. If $\mu (A)=\nu (B)=1$, then the two actions are called orbit equivalent (OE).

The celebrated work of Ornstein and Weiss [Reference Ornstein and WeissOW80] (see also [Reference DyeDye59, Reference Connes, Feldman and WeissCFW81]) proves that any two free ergodic pmp actions of infinite amenable groups are OE and, consequently, any two infinite amenable groups are measure equivalent. In sharp contrast, classifying non-amenable groups up to measure equivalence is a much more challenging task and it reveals a very strong rigidity phenomenon. By building on Zimmer's work [Reference ZimmerZim84], Furman showed that any countable group which is measure equivalent to a lattice in a higher rank simple Lie group is essentially a lattice in the same Lie group [Reference FurmanFur99]. Then Kida showed that most mapping class groups ${\rm Mod}(S)$ are measure-equivalent superrigid which means that any countable group that is measure equivalent to ${\rm Mod}(S)$, must be virtually isomorphic to it [Reference KidaKid10]. Subsequently, other such measure-equivalent superrigid groups have been found and we refer the reader to the introduction of [Reference Horbez and HuangHH22] for more details.

There have been discovered several other remarkable instances where various aspects of the group $\Gamma$ can be recovered from its measure equivalence class or certain properties of the group action $\Gamma \curvearrowright (X,\mu )$ are remembered by its associated orbit equivalence relation. We only highlight the following developments in this direction and refer the reader to the surveys [Reference ShalomSha05, Reference FurmanFur11] for more information. Gaboriau used the notion of cost to show that the rank of a free group $\mathbb {F}_n$ is an invariant of the orbit equivalence relation of any of its free, ergodic, pmp actions [Reference GaboriauGab00]. Then his discovery that measure equivalent groups have proportional $\ell ^2$-Betti numbers [Reference GaboriauGab02] led to significant new progress in the classification problem of pmp actions up to OE, see the survey [Reference GaboriauGab10]. Using a completely different conceptual framework, Popa's deformation rigidity/theory [Reference PopaPop07a] led to an unprecedented development in the theory of von Neumann algebras and provided many other spectacular rigidity results in orbit equivalence, see the surveys [Reference VaesVae10, Reference IoanaIoa14, Reference IoanaIoa18].

In their breakthrough work [Reference Monod and ShalomMS06], Monod and Shalom employed techniques from bounded cohomology theory to obtain a series of OE rigidity results, including the following unique prime factorization result: if $\Gamma _1\times \cdots \times \Gamma _n$ is a product of non-elementary torsion-free hyperbolic groups (more generally, of groups belonging to class $\mathcal {C}_{\rm reg}$; see [Reference Monod and ShalomMS06, Notation 1.2]) that is measure equivalent to a product $\Lambda _1\times \cdots \times \Lambda _m$ of torsion-free groups, then $n \ge m$, and if $n = m$, then, after permutation of the indices, $\Gamma _i$ is measure equivalent to $\Lambda _i$, for all $1\leq i\leq n$. By building upon C$^*$-algebraic methods from [Reference OzawaOza04, Reference Brown and OzawaBO08], the above unique prime factorization result has been extended by Sako [Reference SakoSak09] to products of non-amenable bi-exact groups (see also [Reference Chifan and SinclairCS13]).

In our first main result of the paper, we use the powerful framework of Popa's deformation/rigidity theory to establish a general analogue of Monod and Shalom's unique prime factorization theorem, which applies, in particular, to product of groups with positive first $\ell ^2$-Betti number. More generally, we obtain such a result for product of groups for which their von Neumann algebras belong to a certain class ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$ of II$_1$ factors that admit an s-malleable deformation in the sense of Popa [Reference PopaPop06a, Reference PopaPop06b] (see Definition 3.1). For simplicity, we say that a countable group $\Gamma$ belongs to ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$ if its associated von Neumann algebra $L(\Gamma )$ belongs to ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$. We refer the reader to Definition 3.3 for the description of class ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$ and to Example 1.1 for more concrete examples of groups that belong to this class.

Theorem A Let $\Gamma _1,\ldots,\Gamma _n$ be groups that belong to ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$. If $\Gamma _1\times \cdots \times \Gamma _n$ is measure equivalent to a product $\Lambda _1\times \cdots \times \Lambda _m$ of infinite icc groups, then $n\ge m$, and if $n=m$, then after permutation of indices, $\Gamma _i$ is measure equivalent to $\Lambda _i$, for any $1\leq i\leq n$.

Example 1.1 A countable group $\Gamma$ belongs to ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$ whenever $\Gamma$ is a non-amenable icc group that satisfies one of the following conditions (see Proposition 3.5):

  1. (1) $\Gamma =\Sigma \wr _{G/H} G$ is a generalized wreath product group with $\Sigma$ amenable, $G$ non-amenable and $H< G$ is an amenable almost malnormal subgroup;

  2. (2) $\Gamma$ admits an unbounded cocycle for some mixing representation $\pi :\Gamma \to \mathcal {O}( H_{\mathbb {R}})$ such that $\pi$ is weakly contained in the left regular representation of $\Gamma$;

  3. (3) $\Gamma =\Gamma _1*_\Sigma \Gamma _2$ is an amalgamated free product group satisfying $[\Gamma _1:\Sigma ]\ge 2$ and $[\Gamma _2:\Sigma ]\ge 3$, where $\Sigma <\Gamma$ is an amenable almost malnormalFootnote 1 subgroup.

We continue by making several remarks about Theorem A. First, note that the class $\mathcal {C}_{\rm reg}$ considered by Monod and Shalom in their unique prime factorization result [Reference Monod and ShalomMS06, Theorem 1.16] does not contain groups that have infinite amenable normal subgroups [Reference Monod and ShalomMS06, Corollary 1.19] and, hence, the subclass of wreath product groups considered in Example 1.1(1) is disjoint from $\mathcal {C}_{\rm reg}$. Moreover, Example 1.1 provides a large class of groups that are not bi-exact [Reference SakoSak09] since any bi-exact group cannot contain an infinite subgroup with non-amenable centralizer.

Next, we contrast our result with the following corollary of Gaboriau's work [Reference GaboriauGab02]: if a product $\Gamma =\Gamma _1\times \cdots \times \Gamma _n$ of $n$ groups with positive first $\ell ^2$-Betti number is measure equivalent to a product $\Lambda =\Lambda _1\times \cdots \times \Lambda _m$ of $m$ infinite groups, then $n\ge m$. Indeed, by [Reference GaboriauGab02, Théorème 6.3.] we have that the $n$th $\ell ^2$-Betti number of $\Gamma$ vanishes if and only if the $n$th $\ell ^2$-Betti number of $\Lambda$ vanishes. On the other hand, the Künneth formula [Reference GaboriauGab02, Propriétés 1.5] implies that the $n$th $\ell ^2$-Betti number of $\Gamma$ is positive, while if $n< m$, then the $n$th $\ell ^2$-Betti number of $\Lambda$ equals to $0$. Theorem B strengthens this conclusion in two ways in the case $\Gamma,\Lambda$ are icc. First, if $n=m$ we are able to recover the measure equivalence class of each $\Gamma _i$. Second, since the groups with positive first $\ell ^2$-Betti number are precisely the non-amenable groups that admit an unbounded cocycle into the left regular representation [Reference Peterson and ThomPT11], Example 1.1(2) extends the previous result of Gaboriau to the larger class of groups that admit an unbounded cocycle for some mixing representation that is weakly contained in the left regular representation.

Remark 1.2 Popa's deformation/rigidity theory gave rise to a plethora of striking rigidity results for von Neumann algebras of wreath product groups. Popa's pioneering work [Reference PopaPop06b, Reference PopaPop06c] allowed one to distinguish between the group von Neumann algebras of $\mathbb {Z}/2\mathbb {Z}\wr \Gamma$, as $\Gamma$ is an infinite property (T) group, while Ioana, Popa, and Vaes used a wreath product construction to obtain the first class of groups that are entirely remembered by their von Neumann algebras [Reference Ioana, Popa and VaesIPV13]. Subsequently, several other rigidity results have been obtained for von Neumann algebras of wreath products including primeness, relative solidity, and product rigidity, see [Reference IoanaIoa07, Reference PopaPop08, Reference Chifan and IoanaCI10, Reference IoanaIoa11, Reference Ioana, Popa and VaesIPV13, Reference Sizemore and WinchesterSW13, Reference Chifan, Popa and SizemoreCPS12, Reference Berbec and VaesBV14, Reference Isono and MarrakchiIM19, Reference DrimbeDri21, Reference Chifan, Diaz-Arias and DrimbeCDD21]. Theorem A establishes a new general rigidity result for wreath product groups by showing that products of arbitrary non-amenable wreath product groups with amenable base satisfy an analogue of Monod and Shalom's unique prime factorization result.

Theorem A follows from the following more general result in which we classify all tensor product decompositions of $L(\Lambda )$, whenever $\Lambda$ is an icc group that is measure equivalent to a finite product of groups that belong to ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$.

Theorem B Let $\Gamma =\Gamma _1\times \cdots \times \Gamma _n$ be a product of groups that belong to ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$ and let $\Lambda$ be an icc group that is measure equivalent to $\Gamma$. Assume $L(\Lambda )=P_1\bar \otimes \cdots \bar \otimes P_m$ admits a tensor product decompositions into II$_1$ factors. Then $n\ge m$ and there exists a decomposition $\Lambda =\Lambda _1\times \cdots \times \Lambda _m$ into infinite groups.

Moreover, there exist a partition $S_1\sqcup \cdots \sqcup S_m=\{1,\ldots,n\}$, a decomposition $L(\Lambda )=P_1^{t_1}\bar \otimes \cdots \bar \otimes P_m^{t_m}$, for some $t_1,\ldots,t_m>0$ with $t_1\ldots t_m=1$, and a unitary $u\in L(\Lambda )$ such that for any $1\leq j\leq m$:

  1. (1) $\times _{k\in S_j} \Gamma _k$ is measure equivalent to $\Lambda _j$;

  2. (2) $P_j^{t_j}=uL(\Lambda _j)u^*$.

In particular, if $n=m$, then after permutation of indices, $\Gamma _i$ is measure equivalent to $\Lambda _i$, for any $1\leq i\leq n$.

We note that Theorem B provides a complement to [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Theorem C] where such a classification result has been obtained by Hoff, Ioana, and the present author in the case the groups $\Gamma _i$ are hyperbolic. Although the proof of Theorem B is inspired by the strategy of the proof of [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Theorem C], we implement quite differently some of the steps. In order to effectively work with groups from ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$, which are defined by a property of their von Neumann algebras, we are making use in an essential way of newer techniques from [Reference Bannon, Marrakchi and OzawaBMO20, Reference Isono and MarrakchiIM19, Reference DrimbeDri21]. In particular, our proof uses a relative version of the flip automorphism method introduced by Isono and Marrakchi in [Reference Isono and MarrakchiIM19].

Another application of Theorem B is to the study of tensor product decompositions of von Neumann algebras by providing new classes of prime II$_1$ factors. Recall that a II$_1$ factor is called prime if it does not admit a tensor product decomposition into II$_1$ factors. Popa discovered in [Reference PopaPop83] the first examples of prime II$_1$ factors by showing that the free group factors $L(\mathbb {F}_S)$, with $S$ uncountable, are prime. Then Ge showed in [Reference GeGe98] that the free group factors $L(\mathbb {F}_n), 2\leq n\leq \infty$, are prime, thus providing the first examples of separable prime II$_1$ factors. Subsequently, a large number of prime II$_1$ factors have been discovered; see, for instance, the introduction of [Reference Chifan, Drimbe and IoanaCDI22]. As a corollary of Theorem B, we obtain that if $\Gamma$ is a countable group that belongs to ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$ and $G=(\times _{i=1}^n \Gamma )\rtimes \mathbb {Z}/ n\mathbb {Z}$ is the semidirect product group of the natural translation action $\mathbb {Z}/n\mathbb {Z} \curvearrowright \times _{i=1}^n \Gamma$, then $L(G)$ is a prime II$_1$ factor. In fact, a more general result holds and for properly formulating it, we give the following notation. Let $n$ be a positive integer, denote by $S_n$ the group of permutations of $\{1,\ldots, n\}$ and consider the permutation action of $S_n$ on $\{1,\ldots,n\}$. For any subset $J\subset \{1,\ldots,n\}$ and subgroup $K< S_n$, we denote ${\rm Fix}_K(J)=\{g\in K\mid g\cdot j=j, \text { for any } j\in J \}$.

Corollary C Let $\Gamma$ be a countable group that belongs to ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$. Let $n$ be a positive integer and let $K$ be any subgroup of $S_n$. Consider the permutation action $K\curvearrowright \times _{i=1}^n\Gamma$ and denote $G=(\times _{i=1}^n\Gamma )\rtimes K$.

Then $L(G)$ is a prime II$_1$ factor if and only if there exists no partition $J_1\sqcup J_2=\{1,\ldots,n\}$ for which $K={\rm Fix}_K(J_1)\times {\rm Fix}_K(J_2)$.

Note that Corollary C provides a large class of prime II$_1$ factors which admit finite index subfactors that are not prime. Additional such prime II$_1$ factors have been obtained previously in [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Reference Chifan and DasCD19] by replacing $\Gamma$ in the statement of Corollary C by any non-elementary hyperbolic group, see also [Reference Chifan, Drimbe and IoanaCDI22, § 5].

We continue by discussing some OE rigidity results for actions of product groups that belong to class ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$. Furman discovered in [Reference FurmanFur99] the first class of group action $\Gamma \curvearrowright (X,\mu )$ that are OE superrigid, that is, any free, ergodic, pmp action that is OE to $\Gamma \curvearrowright (X,\mu )$ must be virtually conjugateFootnote 2 to it. Subsequently, a large number of OE superrigidity results have been obtained, see the introduction of [Reference Drimbe, Ioana and PetersonDIP19]. By using part of the proof of Theorem B together with results from measured group theory [Reference Horbez, Huang and IoanaHHI21], we derive the following OE superrigidity result within the class of mildly mixing actions. Before stating the result, we recall some notions. A pmp action $\Gamma _1\times \ldots \times \Gamma _n\curvearrowright (X,\mu )$ is called irreducible if its restriction to any subgroup $\Gamma _i$ is ergodic. A pmp action $\Lambda \curvearrowright (Y,\nu )$ is called mildly mixing if whenever $A\subset Y$ is measurable subset satisfying $\liminf _{g\to \infty } \nu (gA\Delta A)=0$, then $\nu (A)\in \{0,1\}.$

Theorem D Let $\Gamma =\Gamma _1\times \cdots \times \Gamma _n$ be a product of $n\ge 2$ groups that belong to ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$. Let $\Gamma \curvearrowright (X,\mu )$ be a free, irreducible, pmp action that is OE to a free, mildly mixing, pmp action $\Lambda \curvearrowright (Y,\nu )$.

Then $\Gamma \curvearrowright (X,\mu )$ and $\Lambda \curvearrowright (Y,\nu )$ are virtually conjugate.

Note that this type of superrigidity has been obtained by Monod and Shalom [Reference Monod and ShalomMS06, Theorem 1.9] for groups $\Gamma _i$ that are torsion-free hyperbolic groups (more generally, groups that belong to $\mathcal {C}_{\rm reg}$). In Theorem D we extend this result to groups from ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$ which are purely defined by a property of their von Neumann algebra.

Finally, in the last part of this paper we discuss some structural results for II$_1$ factors that belong to a subclass of ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$. We say that a non-amenable tracial von Neumann algebra $M$ belongs to class $\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}_0}$ if there exists an s-malleable deformation $(\tilde M, (\alpha _t)_{t\in \mathbb {R}})$ of $M$ satisfying:

  • $L^2(\tilde M)\ominus L^2(M)$ is a mixing $M$-$M$-bimodule relative to $\mathbb {C}1$;

  • $L^2(\tilde M)\ominus L^2(M)$ is weakly contained in the coarse bimodule $L^2(M)\otimes L^2(M)$ as $M$-$M$-bimodules.

We refer the reader to §§ 2.3 and 3.1 for the terminology used in defining the class $\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}_0}$ and we note that any II$_1$ factor from $\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}_0}$ belongs to ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$, see Definition 3.3.

In Theorem E we show that all embeddings of group von Neumann algebras of non-amenable inner amenable groups in any II$_1$ factor that belongs to $\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}_0}$ are rigid. A countable group $\Gamma$ is inner amenable if there exists an atomless mean on $\Gamma$ which is invariant by the action of $\Gamma$ on itself by conjugation. Effros made in [Reference EffrosEff75] a connection of this group theoretic notion to von Neumann algebras by showing that an icc group $\Gamma$ is inner amenable whenever its group von Neumann algebra has property Gamma. The converse is false as was shown by Vaes [Reference VaesVae12].

Theorem E Let $M$ be a von Neumann algebra in $\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}_0}$ and let $(\tilde M, (\alpha _t)_{t\in \mathbb {R}})$ be the associated s-malleable deformation of $M$. Let $\Gamma$ be a non-amenable inner amenable group satisfying $L(\Gamma )\subset M$.

Then $L(\Gamma )$ is $\alpha$-rigid, i.e. $\alpha _t\to {\rm id}$ uniformly on the unit ball of $L(\Gamma )$.

Note that von Neumann algebras with property Gamma exhibit strong structural results (see, for instance, [Reference PetersonPet09, Reference Houdayer and UedaHU16, Reference Ioana and SpaasIS19]) that are enough for obtaining various rigidity results via Popa's deformation/rigidity theory. In order to work with the more general class of inner amenable groups, we use an idea from [Reference Tucker-DrobTuc14, Theorem 11] on how to use Popa's spectral gap principle. An additional obstacle that arises here is the fact that $E_{L(\Gamma )}(\alpha _t(u_g))$ is not necessarily a scalar multiple of $u_g$, where $g\in \Gamma$; here, we denoted by $\{u_g\}_{g\in \Gamma }$ the canonical unitaries that generate $L(\Gamma )$ and by $E_{L(\Gamma )}:\tilde M\to L(\Gamma )$ the canonical conditional expectation. We overcome this difficulty by using an augmentation technique based on the comultiplication map associated to $L(\Gamma )$ (see [Reference Popa and VaesPV10]).

We continue by discussing several applications of Theorem E. Chifan and Sinclair proved in [Reference Chifan and SinclairCS13] that any countable group $\Gamma$ for which $\beta ^{(2)}_1(\Gamma )>0$ is not inner amenable. Theorem E recovers and strengthens this fact in the following way. While it is unknown that the non-vanishing of the first $\ell ^2$-Betti number is a group von Neumann algebra invariant, we derive from Theorem E that any group that has isomorphic von Neumann algebra to $L(\Gamma )$ is not inner amenable as well.

Corollary F Let $\Gamma$ be any countable group for which $\beta ^{(2)}_1(\Gamma )>0$. If $\Lambda$ is any countable group for which $L(\Gamma )\cong L(\Lambda )$, then $\Lambda$ is not inner amenable.

To put Theorem E into a better perspective, we note that it provides an alternative solution to a question of Popa. Since any non-amenable property Gamma von Neumann algebra cannot embed into the free group factor $L(\mathbb {F}_n)$ (see [Reference OzawaOza04]), Popa asked in [Reference PopaPop21] if it still true that the group von Neumann algebra of a non-amenable inner amenable group cannot embed into $L(\mathbb {F}_n)$. Recently, inspired by the notion of properly proximal groups [Reference Boutonnet, Ioana and PetersonBIP21] (see also [Reference Ishan, Peterson and RuthIPR19]), Ding, Kunnawalkam Elayavalli, and Peterson developed in [Reference Ding, Kunnawalkam Elayavalli and PetersonDKP22] subtle boundary techniques to define a notion of proper proximality for tracial von Neumann algebras, and as a consequence, they answered Popa's question in a positive way. As a particular case of Theorem E, we give a new proof for Popa's question by using methods from Popa's deformation/rigidity theory.

Moreover, as a corollary of Theorem E we completely classify all embeddings of group von Neumann algebras $L(G)$ of non-amenable inner amenable groups in any free product $M=M_1*M_2$ of tracial von Neumann algebras by showing that $L(G)\prec _{M} M_i$, for some $i$. Here, $\prec _M$ refers to Popa's intertwining-by-bimodules technique, see § 2.2. Consequently, we obtain a new class of examples for which the Kurosh-type rigidity results discovered in [Reference OzawaOza06] for free products von Neumann algebras hold. Namely, Ozawa proved using C$^*$-algebraic techniques that if there is an isomorphism $\theta : M_1*\cdots * M_m\to N_1*\cdots * N_n$, where all von Neumann algebras $M_i$ and $N_j$ are non-amenable, semiexact, non-prime II$_1$ factors, then $m=n$, and after a permutation of indices, $\theta (M_i)$ is unitarily conjugate to $N_i$, for any $i\in \overline {1,n}$. By using Popa's deformation/rigidity theory, Ioana, Popa, and Peterson obtained the previous Kurosh-type rigidity result for property (T) II$_1$ factors [Reference Ioana, Peterson and PopaIPP08]. Shortly after, by developing a new approach rooted on closable derivations, Peterson unified and generalized these Kurosh-type rigidity results by covering $L^2$-rigid II$_1$ factors, which include all non-amenable non-prime, property (T), and property Gamma II$_1$ factors [Reference PetersonPet09]. By classifying certain amenable subalgebras of amalgamated free product von Neumann algebras, Ioana then extended the previous Kurosh-type rigidity result by covering non-amenable II$_1$ factors that admit a Cartan subalgebra [Reference IoanaIoa15]. We also refer the reader to [Reference Houdayer and UedaHU16] for certain Kurosh-type rigidity results for type III factors. As a corollary of Theorem E, we extend the previous Kurosh-type rigidity results to the class of II$_ 1$ factors of non-amenable inner amenable groups, see Corollary 8.1.

2. Preliminaries

2.1 Terminology

Throughout the paper we consider tracial von Neumann algebras $(M,\tau )$, i.e. von Neumann algebras $M$ equipped with a faithful normal tracial state $\tau : M\to \mathbb {C}.$ This induces a norm on $M$ by the formula $\|x\|_2=\tau (x^*x)^{1/2},$ for any $x\in M$. We will always assume that $M$ is separable, i.e. the $\|\cdot \|_2$-completion of $M$ denoted by $L^2(M)$ is separable as a Hilbert space. We denote by $\mathcal {Z}(M)$ the center of $M$ and by $\mathcal {U}(M)$ its unitary group. For two von Neumann subalgebras $P_1,P_2\subset M$, we denote by $P_1\vee P_2=W^*(P_1\cup P_2)$ the von Neumann algebra generated by $P_1$ and $P_2$.

All inclusions $P\subset M$ of von Neumann algebras are assumed unital. We denote by $E_{P}:M\to P$ the unique $\tau$-preserving conditional expectation from $M$ onto $P$, by $e_P:L^2(M)\to L^2(P)$ the orthogonal projection onto $L^2(P)$ and by $\langle M,e_P\rangle$ the Jones’ basic construction of $P\subset M$. We also denote by $P'\cap M=\{x\in M \mid xy=yx, \text { for all } y\in P\}$ the relative commutant of $P$ in $M$ and by $\mathcal {N}_{M}(P)=\{u\in \mathcal {U}(M) \mid uPu^*=P\}$ the normalizer of $P$ in $M$.

The amplification of a II$_1$ factor $(M,\tau )$ by a number $t>0$ is defined to be $M^t=p(\mathbb {B}(\ell ^2(\mathbb {Z}))\bar \otimes M)p$, for a projection $p\in \mathbb {B}(\ell ^2(\mathbb {Z}))\bar \otimes M$ satisfying $($Tr$\otimes \tau )(p)=t$. Here Tr denotes the usual trace on $\mathbb {B}(\ell ^2(\mathbb {Z}))$. Since $M$ is a II$_1$ factor, $M^t$ is well defined. Note that if $M=P_1\bar \otimes P_2$, for some II$_1$ factors $P_1$ and $P_2$, then there is a natural isomorphism $M=P_1^t\bar \otimes P_2^{1/t}$, for any $t>0.$

Finally, for a positive integer $n$, we denote by $\overline {1,n}$ the set $\{1,\ldots, n\}$. If $S\subset \overline {1,n}$ we denote its complement by $\widehat S=\overline {1,n}\setminus S$. In the case that $S=\{i\},$ we will simply write $\hat i$ instead of $\widehat {\{i\}}$. In addition, given any product group $\Gamma =\Gamma _1\times \cdots \times \Gamma _n$, we will denote their subproduct supported on $S$ by $\Gamma _S=\times _{i\in S}\Gamma _i$.

2.2 Intertwining-by-bimodules

We next recall from [Reference PopaPop06b, Theorem 2.1 and Corollary 2.3] the powerful intertwining-by-bimodules technique of Popa.

Theorem 2.1 [Reference PopaPop06b]

Let $(M,\tau )$ be a tracial von Neumann algebra and $P\subset pMp, Q\subset qMq$ be von Neumann subalgebras. Let $\mathcal {U}\subset \mathcal {U}(P)$ be a subgroup such that $\mathcal {U}''=P$.

Then the following are equivalent.

  1. (1) There exist projections $p_0\in P, q_0\in Q$, a $*$-homomorphism $\theta :p_0Pp_0\rightarrow q_0Qq_0$ and a non-zero partial isometry $v\in q_0Mp_0$ such that $\theta (x)v=vx$, for all $x\in p_0Pp_0$.

  2. (2) There is no sequence $(u_n)_n\subset \mathcal {U}$ satisfying $\|E_Q(xu_ny)\|_2\rightarrow 0$, for all $x,y\in M$.

If one of the equivalent conditions of Theorem 2.1 holds true, we write $P\prec _{M}Q$, and say that a corner of $P$ embeds into $Q$ inside $M$. If $Pp'\prec _{M}Q$ for any non-zero projection $p'\in P'\cap pMp$, then we write $P\prec ^{s}_{M}Q$.

Lemma 2.2 Let $\Lambda \curvearrowright B$ be a trace-preserving action and denote $M=B\rtimes \Lambda$. Let $p\in B$ be a non-zero projection and let $A\subset pBp$ be a von Neumann subalgebra such that $A'\cap pMp\subset A$.

Let $\Lambda _0<\Lambda$ be a subgroup and $\mathcal {G}\subset \mathcal {N}_{pMp}(A)$ a group of unitaries. If there is a projection $e\in \mathcal {G}'\cap pMp$ satisfying $\mathcal {G}''e\prec _M^s B\times \Lambda _0$, then there is a projection $f\in (A\cup \mathcal {G})'\cap pMp$ with $e\leq f$ satisfying $(A\cup \mathcal {G})''f\prec _M^s B\rtimes \Lambda _0$.

Proof. Throughout the proof we use the terminology that a set $F\subset \Lambda$ is said to be small relative to $\{\Lambda _0\}$ if it is contained into a finite union of $s\Lambda _0 t$, where $s,t\in \Lambda$. For any $F\subset \Lambda$, let $\mathcal {H}_F\subset L^2(M)$ be the $\|\cdot \|_2$-closed linear span of $\{B v_{\lambda }\mid \lambda \in F\}$ and denote by $P_F:L^2(M)\to \mathcal {H}_F$ the orthogonal projection onto $\mathcal {H}_F$. Let $\epsilon >0$ and denote $T=E_{A'\cap pMp}(e)$. Note that $T\in (A\cup \mathcal {G})'\cap pMp\subset A$ and that $T$ belongs to the $\|\cdot \|_2$-closed convex hull of $\{aea^* \mid a\in \mathcal {U}(A)\}$. Thus, we can take $a_1,\ldots,a_n\in \mathcal {U}(A)$ and $\alpha _1,\ldots,\alpha _n\in [0,1]$ such that if we denote $T_0=\sum _{i=1}^n \alpha _i a_i ea_i^*$, then $\|T-T_0\|_2\leq \epsilon$.

Since $\mathcal {G}''e\prec _M^s B\times \Lambda _0$, it follows from [Reference VaesVae13, Lemma 2.5] that there exists $F\subset \Lambda$ that is small relative to $\{\Lambda _0\}$ such that $\|we-P_{F}(we)\|_2\leq \epsilon /n$, for all $w\in \mathcal {G}$. Hence, for all $a\in \mathcal {U}(A), w\in \mathcal {G}$, we have

(2.1)\begin{equation} \biggl\|awT - \alpha_i\sum_{i=1}^n a (wa_iw^*)P_F(we)a_i^* \biggr\|_2\leq \epsilon + \sum_{i=1}^n \alpha_i\| aw(a_iea_i^*) - a(wa_iw^*)P_F(we) a_i^* \|_2\leq 2\epsilon. \end{equation}

Since $A\subset pBp$, we have $a (wa_iw^*)P_F(we)a_i^* \in \mathcal {H}_F$ and, hence, $\|awT-P_F(awT)\|_2\leq 2\epsilon$, for all $a\in \mathcal {U}(A),w\in \mathcal {G}$. Therefore, there exists a sequence $\{F_n\}_{n\ge 1}$ of subsets of $\Lambda$ that are small relative to $\{\Lambda _0\}$ such that $\|awT-P_{F_n}(awT)\|_2\to 0$ uniformly in $a\in \mathcal {U}(A),w\in \mathcal {G}$.

For every $\delta >0$ define the spectral projection $q_\delta =\chi _{(\delta,\infty )}(T)\in A$ and let $T_\delta \in A$ satisfying $TT_\delta =q_\delta.$ If we denote by $q_0$ the support projection of $T$, then $\|q_\delta -q_0\|_2\to 0$ as $\delta \to 0$. These altogether imply that $\|awq_\delta -P_{F_n}(awq_\delta )\|_2\to 0$ uniformly in $a\in \mathcal {U}(A),w\in \mathcal {G}$ and, hence, $\|awq_0-P_{F_n}(awq_0)\|_2\to 0$ uniformly in $a\in \mathcal {U}(A),\ w\in \mathcal {G}$. Finally, note that $q_0\in (A\cup \mathcal {G})'\cap pMp$ and $q_0\ge e$. This concludes the proof.

The following proposition follows from [Reference Bannon, Marrakchi and OzawaBMO20, Reference Isono and MarrakchiIM19] and it is essentially contained in the proof of [Reference DrimbeDri21, Theorem 4.2]. We record it here for the convenience of the reader.

Proposition 2.3 Let $M=P\bar \otimes Q$ be a tensor product of II$_1$ factors. Let $Q_n,n\ge 1$, be a decreasing sequence of von Neumann subalgebras such that $P\prec _M \bigvee _{n\ge 1}(Q_n'\cap M)$.

If $P$ does not have property Gamma, then there exists $m\ge 1$ such that $P\prec _{M} Q_m'\cap M.$

Recall that a II$_1$ factor $(M,\tau )$ has property Gamma if it admits a central sequence $(x_n)_n\subset {\mathcal {U}}(M)$ for which ${\rm inf}_{n} \|x_n- \tau (x_n)1\|_2>0$.

2.3 Bimodules

Let $M, N$ be tracial von Neumann algebras. An $M$-$N$ bimodule $_M \mathcal {H}_N$ is a Hilbert space $\mathcal {H}$ together with a $*$-homomorphism $\pi _{\mathcal {H}}: M\odot N^{\text {op}}\to \mathbb {B}(\mathcal {H})$ that is normal on $M$ and $N^{\text {op}}$, where $M\odot N^{\text {op}}$ is the algebraic tensor product between $M$ and the opposite von Neumann algebra $N^{\text {op}}$ of $N$. Examples of bimodules include the trivial $M$-bimodule $_M L^2(M)_M$ and the coarse $M$-$N$-bimodule $_M L^2(M)\otimes L^2(N)_N.$ For two $M$-$N$-bimodules $_M \mathcal {H}_N$ and $_M \mathcal {K}_N$, we say that $_M \mathcal {H}_N$ is weakly contained in $_M \mathcal {K}_N$ if $\|\pi _{\mathcal {H}}(x)\|\leq \|\pi _{\mathcal {K}}(x)\|$, for any $x\in M\odot N^{\text {op}}$.

Let $A\subset M$ be an inclusion of tracial von Neumann algebras and let $_M\mathcal {H}_M$ be an $M$-bimodule. We say that $_M\mathcal {H}_M$ is mixing relative to $A$ if for any sequence $(x_n)_n\subset (M)_1$ satisfying $\|E_{A}(xu_n y)\|_2\to 0$, for all $x,y\in M$, we have

\[ \lim_{n\to\infty} \sup_{y\in (M)_1} \langle x_n\xi y,\eta \rangle, \quad \text{for all }\xi,\eta\in\mathcal{H}. \]

2.4 Relative amenability

A tracial von Neumann algebra $(M,\tau )$ is amenable if there is a positive linear functional $\Phi :\mathbb {B}(L^2(M))\to \mathbb {C}$ such that $\Phi _{|M}=\tau$ and $\Phi$ is $M$-central, meaning $\Phi (xT)=\Phi (Tx),$ for all $x\in M$ and $T\in \mathbb {B}(L^2(M))$. By Connes’ classification of amenable factors [Reference ConnesCon76], it follows that $M$ is amenable if and only if $M$ is approximately finite dimensional.

We continue by recalling the notion of relative amenability which is due to Ozawa and Popa [Reference Ozawa and PopaOP10]. Fix a tracial von Neumann algebra $(M,\tau )$. Let $p\in M$ be a projection and $P\subset pMp,Q\subset M$ be von Neumann subalgebras. Following [Reference Ozawa and PopaOP10, Definition 2.2], we say that $P$ is amenable relative to $Q$ inside $M$ if there is a positive linear functional $\Phi :p\langle M,e_Q\rangle p\to \mathbb {C}$ such that $\Phi _{|pMp}=\tau$ and $\Phi$ is $P$-central. We say that $P$ is strongly non-amenable relative to $Q$ if $Pp'$ is non-amenable relative to $Q$ for any non-zero projection $p'\in P'\cap pMp$ (equivalently, for any non-zero projection $p'\in \mathcal {N}_M(P)'\cap pMp$ by [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Lemma 2.6]).

Note that if $P\subset pMp$ and $Q\subset M$ are tracial von Neumann algebras, then $P\subset pMp$ is amenable relative to $Q$ if and only if $_P L^2(pM)_M$ is weakly contained in $_P L^2(p\langle M,e_{Q} \rangle )_M$. We also recall that $_M L^2(\langle M,e_{Q} \rangle )_M\cong _M( L^2(M)\otimes _Q L^2(M))_M$. It is clear that $P$ is amenable relative to $\mathbb {C} 1$ inside $M$ if and only if $P$ is amenable. The following lemma generalizes this fact and it is inspired by the proof of [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Lemma 5.6]. For completeness, we provide all the details.

Lemma 2.4 Let $M_0$ and $M\subset \tilde M$ be some tracial von Neumann algebras and let $Q\subset q(M_0\bar \otimes M)q$ be a von Neumann subalgebra. The following hold.

  1. (1) Assume that $Q\tilde z$ is amenable relative to $M_0$ inside $M_0\bar \otimes \tilde M$, for a non-zero projection $\tilde z\in Q'\cap q(M_0\bar \otimes \tilde M)q$. Then $Qz$ is amenable relative to $M_0$ inside $M_0\bar \otimes M$, where $z\in Q'\cap q(M_0\bar \otimes M)q$ is the support projection of $E_{\mathcal {M}}(\tilde z).$

  2. (2) If $Q\prec _{M_0\bar \otimes \tilde M} M_0,$ then $Q\prec _{M_0\bar \otimes M} M_0.$

Proof. (1) Let $\mathcal {M}=M_0\bar \otimes M$ and $\tilde {\mathcal {M}}=M_0\bar \otimes \tilde M.$ The assumption implies that the bimodule $_{Q\tilde z} L^2(\tilde z\tilde {\mathcal {M}})_{\tilde {\mathcal {M}}}$ is weakly contained in $_{Q\tilde z} L^2(\tilde z \langle \tilde {\mathcal {M}},e_{M_0}\rangle )_{\tilde {\mathcal {M}}}$. If we denote by $z\in Q'\cap q(M_0\bar \otimes M)q)$ the support projection of $E_{\mathcal {M}}(\tilde z),$ we obtain that

(2.2)\begin{equation} {}_{Qz} L^2(z{\mathcal{M}})_{\mathcal{M}} \text{ is weakly contained in }_{Qz} L^2(z \langle \tilde{\mathcal{M}},e_{M_0}\rangle)_{{\mathcal{M}}}. \end{equation}

Note that $_{\mathcal {M}} L^2(\langle \tilde {\mathcal {M}},e_{M_0}\rangle )_\mathcal {M}\cong _{\mathcal {M}} L^2(\tilde {\mathcal {M}})\otimes L^2(\tilde M) _{\mathcal {M}}$. Note also that $_{\mathcal {M}} L^2(\tilde {\mathcal {M}})_{M_0}$ is weakly contained in $_{\mathcal {M}} L^2({\mathcal {M}})_{M_0}$ and $_{\mathbb {C}} L^2(\tilde M)_M$ is weakly contained in $_{\mathbb {C}}L^2(M)_M.$

These altogether imply that $_{Qz} L^2(\langle \tilde {\mathcal {M}},e_{M_0}\rangle )_\mathcal {M}$ is weakly contained in $_{Qz} L^2(\langle {\mathcal {M}},e_{M_0}\rangle )_\mathcal {M}$. Using (2.2) we deduce that $_{Qz} L^2(z{\mathcal {M}})_{{\mathcal {M}}}$ is weakly contained in $_{Qz} L^2(z \langle {\mathcal {M}},e_{M_0}\rangle )_{{\mathcal {M}}}$, which shows that $Qz$ is amenable relative to $M_0$ inside $\mathcal {M}.$

(2) By assuming the contrary, there exists a sequence $u_n\in \mathcal {U} (Q)$ such that

(2.3)\begin{equation} \|E_{M_0}(xu_ny)\|_2\to 0, \quad \text{for all } x,y\in M_0\bar\otimes M. \end{equation}

We want to show that (2.3) holds for all $x,y\in M_0\bar \otimes \tilde M,$ which will contradict the assumption. Note that it is enough to consider $x=1$ and $y\in \tilde M$. In this case, by using (2.3) we obtain $E_{M_0}(u_ny)=E_{M_0}(E_{M_0\bar \otimes M}(u_ny))=E_{M_0}(u_nE_{M_0\bar \otimes M}(y))$, which goes to $0$ in the $\|\cdot \|_2$-norm. This finishes the proof.

3. Malleable deformations for von Neumann algebras: class $\mathscr {M}$

3.1 Malleable deformations

Popa introduced in [Reference PopaPop06a, Reference PopaPop06b] the notion of an s-malleable deformation of a von Neumann algebra. This notion has been successfully used in the framework of his deformation/rigidity theory and led to a plethora of remarkable results in the theory of von Neumann algebras, see the surveys [Reference PopaPop07a, Reference VaesVae10, Reference IoanaIoa14, Reference IoanaIoa18]. We also refer the reader to [Reference de Santiago, Hayes, Hoff and SinclairdSHHS20] for recent developments on s-malleable deformations.

Definition 3.1 Let $(M,\tau )$ be a tracial von Neumannn algebra. A pair $(\tilde M, (\alpha _t)_{t\in \mathbb {R}})$ is called an s-malleable deformation of $M$ if the following conditions hold:

  • $(\tilde M,\tilde \tau )$ is a tracial von Neumann algebra such that $M\subset \tilde M$ and $\tau =\tilde \tau _{|M}$;

  • $(\alpha _t)_{t\in \mathbb {R}}\subset {\text Aut}(\tilde M,\tilde \tau )$ is a $1$-parameter group with $\lim _{t\to 0}\|\alpha _t(x)-x\|_2=0$, for any $x\in \tilde M$;

  • there is $\beta \in {\text Aut}(\tilde M,\tilde \tau )$ satisfying $\beta _{|M}=\text {Id}_M$, $\beta ^2=\text {Id}_{\tilde M}$ and $\beta \alpha _t=\alpha _{-t}\beta$, for any $t\in \mathbb {R}$;

  • $\alpha _t$ does not converge uniformly to the identity on $(M)_1$ as $t\to 0$.

For a subalgebra $Q\subset qMq$, we say that $Q$ is $\alpha$-rigid if $\alpha _t$ converges uniformly to the identity on $(Q)_1$ as $t\to 0$. We will repeatedly use the following stability result for s-malleable deformations.

Proposition 3.2 [Reference VaesVae13, Proposition 3.4]

Let $(\tilde M, (\alpha _t)_{t\in \mathbb {R}})$ be an s-malleable deformation of a tracial von Neumann algebra $M$. Let $P\subset pMp$ be a subalgebra that is generated by a group of unitaries $\mathcal {G}\subset \mathcal {U}(P)$. Assume that $\alpha _t\to {\rm id}$ uniformly on $r\mathcal {G} r$ for a projection $r\in pMp$.

Then there is a projection $z\in \mathcal {N}_{pMp}(P)'\cap pMp$ with $r\leq z$ such that $Pz$ is $\alpha$-rigid.

3.2 Definition of class $\mathscr {M}$

We are now ready to define the class of II$_1$ factors that is used in our main results stated in the introduction.

Definition 3.3 We say that a non-amenable II$_1$ factor $M$ belongs to class ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$ if there exists an s-malleable deformation $(\tilde M, (\alpha _t)_{t\in \mathbb {R}})$ of $M$ and an amenable subalgebra $A\subset M$ satisfying $L^2(\tilde M)\ominus L^2(M)$ is a mixing $M$-$M$-bimodule relative to $A$, $L^2(\tilde M)\ominus L^2(M)$ is weakly contained in the coarse bimodule $L^2(M)\otimes L^2(M)$ as $M$-$M$-bimodules and one of the following holds:

  1. (1) $A=\mathbb {C}1$;

  2. (2) if $N$ is a tracial von Neumann algebra and $P\subset p(M\bar \otimes N)p$ a subalgebra such that $P\prec _{M\otimes N} A\otimes N$ and $P'\cap p(M\bar \otimes N)p$ is strongly non-amenable relative to $1\otimes N$, then $P\prec _{M\otimes N} 1 \otimes N.$

As a consequence of Popa's spectral gap principle [Reference PopaPop07b], we continue with the following remark.

Remark 3.4 Let $M\in {\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$ be a II$_1$ factor, denote by $(\tilde M, (\alpha _t)_{t\in \mathbb {R}})$ the associated s-malleable deformation of $M$ and let $N$ be any tracial von Neumann algebra. If $Q\subset q(M\bar \otimes N)q$ is a von Neumann subalgebra which is strongly non-amenable relative to $N$, then $Q'\cap q(M\bar \otimes N)q$ is $(\alpha \otimes {\rm id})$-rigid. This essentially follows from [Reference PopaPop07b] (see, for instance, the proofs of [Reference IoanaIoa12, Lemma 2.2] or [Reference DrimbeDri21, Lemma 3.5]).

The following proposition provides concrete examples of group von Neumann algebras that belong to ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$. The result is a consequence of Remark 3.4 and [Reference DrimbeDri21, Proposition 3.4]).

Proposition 3.5 If $\Gamma$ belongs to one of the three classes of groups mentioned in Example 1.1, then $L(\Gamma )$ belongs to ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$.

Next, we present a useful result for group von Neumann algebras $L(\Gamma )$ that belong to $\boldsymbol {\mathscr M}$ in order to understand structural results of trace-preserving actions of $\Gamma$. In fact, this is a direct consequence of Popa's spectral gap principle [Reference PopaPop07b].

Lemma 3.6 Let $\Gamma \curvearrowright B$ be a trace-preserving action and denote $\mathcal {M}=B\rtimes \Gamma$. We denote by $\Psi :\mathcal {M}\to \mathcal {M} \bar \otimes L(\Gamma )$ the $*$-homomorphism given by $\Psi (bu_g)=bu_g\otimes u_g$, for all $b\in B$ and $g\in \Gamma$. Assume that $L(\Gamma )$ belongs to ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$ and let $(\tilde M, (\alpha _t)_{t\in \mathbb {R}})$ be the associated s-malleable deformation.

If $P\subset p \mathcal {M} p$ is a von Neumann subalgebra that is strongly non-amenable relative to $B$ inside $\mathcal {M}$, then $\Psi (P'\cap p\mathcal {M} p)$ is ${\rm (id}\otimes \alpha )$-rigid. Moreover, if we also assume that $P'\cap p\mathcal {M} p\nprec _{\mathcal {M}} B$, then $\Psi (P\vee (P'\cap p\mathcal {M} p))$ is ${\rm (id}\otimes \alpha )$-rigid.

Proof. Denote $M=L(\Gamma )$. By applying [Reference DrimbeDri20a, Lemma 2.10], we get that $\Psi (P)$ is strongly non-amenable relative to $\mathcal {M}\bar \otimes 1$ inside $\mathcal {M}\bar \otimes M$. Then Remark 3.4 implies that $\Psi (P'\cap p\mathcal {M} p)$ is ${\rm (id}\otimes \alpha )$-rigid. For proving the second part, assume in addition that $P'\cap p\mathcal {M} p\nprec _{\mathcal {M}} B$ and let $A\subset M$ be an amenable subalgebra as given by the assumption that $M$ belongs to $\boldsymbol {\mathscr M}$. By using [Reference IoanaIoa12, Lemma 9.2(1)] we get $\Psi (P'\cap p\mathcal {M} p)\nprec _{\mathcal {M}\bar \otimes M} \mathcal {M}\otimes 1$, and by assumption we must have $\Psi (P'\cap p\mathcal {M} p)\nprec _{\mathcal {M}\bar \otimes M} \mathcal {M}\otimes A$. Hence, in combination with $\Psi (P'\cap p\mathcal {M} p)$ being ${\rm (id}\otimes \alpha )$-rigid and the fact that $L^2(\mathcal {M}\bar \otimes \tilde M)\ominus L^2(\mathcal {M}\bar \otimes M)$ is a mixing $\mathcal {M}\bar \otimes M$-bimodule relative to $\mathcal {M}\bar \otimes A$, we get from [Reference de Santiago, Hayes, Hoff and SinclairdSHHS20, Corollary 6.7] that $\Psi (P\vee (P'\cap p\mathcal {M} p))$ is ${\rm (id}\otimes \alpha )$-rigid.

3.3 Measure equivalence and non-property Gamma for class $\mathscr {M}$

In this subsection we show that the lack of property Gamma is preserved under measure equivalence for finite products of groups whose von Neumann algebras belong to $\boldsymbol {\mathscr M}$, see Proposition 3.8. For proving this result, we first establish the following notation that will be assumed for Proposition 3.8, but will also be useful for the following sections.

Notation 3.7 Let $\Lambda$ be a countable icc group that is measure equivalent to a product $\Gamma =\Gamma _1\times \cdots \times \Gamma _n$ of $n\ge 1$ groups. By using [Reference FurmanFur99, Lemma 3.2], there exist $d\ge 1$, free ergodic pmp actions $\Gamma \curvearrowright (X,\mu )$ and $\Lambda \curvearrowright (Y,\nu )$ such that

\[ \mathcal{R}(\Lambda\curvearrowright Y)=\mathcal{R}(\Gamma\times \mathbb{Z}/d\mathbb{Z} \curvearrowright X \times \mathbb{Z}/d\mathbb{Z})\cap (Y\times Y). \]

Here, we considered that $\mathbb {Z}/d\mathbb {Z} \curvearrowright (\mathbb {Z}/d\mathbb {Z},c)$ acts by addition and $c$ is the counting measure. We also identified $Y$ as a measurable subset of $X\times \mathbb {Z}/d\mathbb {Z}$ and denote $p=1_Y \in L^\infty (X\times \mathbb {Z}/d\mathbb {Z})$. Note that $L^\infty (\mathbb {Z}/d\mathbb {Z})\rtimes \mathbb {Z}/d\mathbb {Z}=\mathbb {M}_d(\mathbb {C})$. Hence, by letting $B=L^\infty (Y)$, $A=L^\infty (X)\otimes M_d(\mathbb {C})$, and $M=A\rtimes \Gamma$, we have $pMp=B\rtimes \Lambda$ and $B\subset pAp$. Denote by $\{u_g\}_{g\in \Gamma }$ and $\{v_\lambda \}_{\lambda \in \Lambda }$ the canonical unitaries implementing the actions $\Gamma \curvearrowright A$ and $\Lambda \curvearrowright B$, respectively.

Following [Reference Popa and VaesPV10] we define the $*$-homomorphism $\Delta : pMp\to pMp \bar \otimes L(\Lambda )$ by $\Delta (bv_\lambda )=bv_\lambda \otimes v_\lambda$, for all $b\in B,\lambda \in \Lambda$. One can extend $\Delta$ to a $*$-homomorphism $\Delta :M\to M\bar \otimes L(\Lambda )$ and verify that $\Delta (M)'\cap M\bar \otimes L(\Lambda )=\mathbb {C} 1$ since $\Lambda$ is icc (see the first part of [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, § 5] for more details).

For any $i\in \overline {1,n}$, let $\Psi ^i: M\to M\bar \otimes L(\Gamma _i)$ be the $*$-homomorphism given by $\Psi ^i(xu_g)=xu_g\otimes u_g$, for all $x\in A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat i} ,g\in \Gamma _i$.

Proposition 3.8 Assume that $L(\Gamma _i)$ belongs to $\boldsymbol {\mathscr M}$, for any $1\leq i\leq n$.

Then $L(\Lambda )$ does not have property Gamma.

Proof. Let $(\tilde M_i, (\alpha ^i_t)_{t\in \mathbb {R}})$ be the associated s-malleable deformation of $L(\Gamma _i) \in {\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$. By assuming that $L(\Lambda )$ has property Gamma, we can use [Reference Houdayer and UedaHU16, Theorem 3.1] to obtain a decreasing sequence of diffuse abelian von Neumann subalgebras $Q_n\subset L(\Lambda )$ with $n\ge 1$ such that $L(\Lambda )=\bigvee _{n\ge 1} (Q_n'\cap L(\Lambda )$). Since $Q_1$ is abelian, it follows that $(Q_1'\cap pMp)'\cap pMp\subset Q_1'\cap pMp$. Hence, for all $k, n\ge 1$, we have

(3.1)\begin{equation} \mathcal{Z}(Q_n'\cap pMp)\subset Q_1'\cap pMp\subset Q_k'\cap pMp. \end{equation}

Using Zorn's lemma and a maximality argument, one can show that for any $m\ge 1$, there exist maximal projections $r_m^1,\ldots, r_m^n\in Q_m'\cap pMp$ satisfying $Q_mr_m^i\nprec _{M}A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat i}$, for any $i\in \overline {1,n}$. One can check that $r_m^i\in \mathcal {Z}(Q_m'\cap pMp)$ and $Q_m (p-r_m^i)\prec _M^s A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat i}$, for any $i\in \overline {1,n}$ (see the proof of [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Lemma 2.4]).

Since $Q_{m}\nprec _{M} A$, [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Lemma 2.8(2)] implies that $\bigwedge _{i=1}^n (p-r_m^i)=0$, which proves that $\bigvee _{i=1}^n r_m^i =p$. Hence, for any $m\ge 1$ there is $i_m\in \overline {1,n}$ such that $\tau (r_m^{i_m})\ge {\tau (p)}/{n}$. Up to passing to a subsequence, we can assume that there is $j\in \overline {1,n}$ such that $i_m=j$, for all $m\ge 1$. Next, note that (3.1) gives that $r_{m}^j\in \mathcal {Z}(Q_m'\cap pMp)\subset Q_{m-1}'\cap pMp$. Since $Q_{m-1} r_m^j \nprec _M A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat j}$, it follows from the choice of all the $r_m^j$'s that $\{r_{m}^j\}_{m\ge 1}$ is a decreasing sequence of projections. If we let $r^j=\bigwedge _{m\ge 1} r_{m}^j$, we deduce that $r^j$ is a non-zero projection since $\tau (r^j)\ge {\tau (p)}/{n}$. For all $m\ge k\ge 1$, since $Q_m\subset Q_k$ we have that $r_m^j \in (Q_k'\cap pMp)'\cap pMp$. Consequently, by letting $m\to \infty$, we deduce that $r^j \in (Q_k'\cap pMp)'\cap pMp$, for all $k\ge 1$, which implies that $r^j\in L(\Lambda )'\cap pMp=\mathbb {C} p$. Since $r^j\neq 0$, we derive that $r^j=p$ and, therefore, we must have $r_m^j=p$, for any $m\ge 1$. This implies that $Q_m\nprec _M A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat j}$, for any $m\ge 1$.

Since $\Gamma _j$ is non-amenable, it follows from [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Lemma 2.9] that $L(\Lambda )$ is non-amenable relative to $A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat j}$ inside $M$. Since relative amenability is closed under inductive limits (see [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Lemma 2.7]), there exists $k\ge 1$ such that $Q_k'\cap pMp$ is non-amenable relative to $A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat j}$ inside $M$. Using [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Lemma 2.6] there is a non-zero projection $z^j\in \mathcal {Z}(Q_k'\cap pMp)$ such that

(3.2)\begin{equation} (Q_k'\cap pMp)z^j \text{ is strongly non-amenable relative to } A\rtimes \Gamma_{\widehat j} \text{ inside }M. \end{equation}

This implies by Lemma 3.6 that $\Psi ^j (Q_k z^j) \text { is }{\rm (id}\otimes \alpha ^j) \text {-rigid}$. Fix an arbitrary $m\ge k$. Since $Q_m\subset Q_k$, we have $z^j\in \mathcal {Z}(Q_k'\cap pMp)\subset Q_m'\cap pMp$ and

(3.3)\begin{equation} \Psi^j (Q_m z^j) \text{ is }{\rm (id}\otimes \alpha^j) \text{-rigid} \text{ and }Q_mz^j\nprec_M A\rtimes\Gamma_{\widehat j}. \end{equation}

Equation (3.2) also implies that

(3.4)\begin{equation} z_j(Q_m'\cap pMp)z^j \text{ is strongly non-amenable relative to } A\rtimes \Gamma_{\widehat j} \text{ inside }M. \end{equation}

By combining (3.3) and (3.4), it follows from the second part of Lemma 3.6 that $\Psi ^j (z^j(Q_m'\cap pMp) z^j) \text { is }{\rm (id}\otimes \alpha ^j) \text {-rigid}$, for any $m\ge k$. Note that (3.3) gives, in particular, that $z^j(Q_m'\cap pMp) z^j\nprec _M A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat j}$, for any $m\ge k$. Therefore, we may apply [Reference de Santiago, Hayes, Hoff and SinclairdSHHS20, Theorem 3.5] (see also [Reference DrimbeDri21, Theorem 3.2]) to deduce that $\Psi ^j (z^ j \bigvee _{m\ge k}(Q_m'\cap pMp) z^j) \text { is }{\rm (id}\otimes \alpha ^j) \text {-rigid}$. Using [Reference de Santiago, Hayes, Hoff and SinclairdSHHS20, Proposition 5.6] there exists a non-zero projection $\tilde z^j\in \mathcal {Z}(\bigvee _{m\ge n}(Q_m'\cap pMp))$ such that $\Psi ^j ( \bigvee _{m\ge k}(Q_m'\cap pMp) \tilde z^j) \text { is }{\rm (id}\otimes \alpha ^j) \text {-rigid}$. Note, however, that $\bigvee _{m\ge k}(Q_m'\cap pMp)$ is a factor since $\bigvee _{m\ge k}(Q_k'\cap L(\Lambda ))=L(\Lambda )$ and $\Lambda$ is icc. In particular, $\Psi ^j (L(\Lambda ) )$ is ${({\rm id}}\otimes \alpha ^j)$-rigid. Since $\Psi ^j(B)\subset M\otimes 1$, it follows that $\Psi ^j (M)$ is ${({\rm id}}\otimes \alpha ^j)$-rigid, which gives that $L(\Gamma _j)$ is $\alpha ^j$-rigid, contradiction. This ends the proof of the proposition.

4. Measure equivalence and tensor product decompositions for class $\mathscr {M}$

In this section we establish the main ingredients needed for the proof of Theorem B by building upon methods from [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Reference Isono and MarrakchiIM19]. Throughout this section, we will use Notation 3.7 and the following assumption.

Assumption 4.1 For any $i\in \overline {1,n}$, assume that $L(\Gamma _i)$ belongs to $\boldsymbol {\mathscr M}$ and denote by $(\tilde M_i, (\alpha ^i_t)_{t\in \mathbb {R}})$ the associated s-malleable deformation of $L(\Gamma _i)$.

4.1 Step 1

The main goal of this subsection is to prove the following theorem.

Theorem 4.2 Let $L(\Lambda )=P_1\bar \otimes P_2$ be a tensor product decomposition into II$_1$ factors.

Then there is a partition $S_1\sqcup S_2=\{1,\ldots,n\}$ into non-empty sets such that $\Delta (A\rtimes \Gamma _{S_i})\prec ^s_{M\bar \otimes L(\Lambda )} M\bar \otimes P_i$, for all $i\in \{1,2\}$.

Before proceeding to the proof of Theorem 4.2, we make the following remark and prove two lemmas.

Remark 4.3 In this remark we explain why the proof of Theorem 4.2 uses a relative version of the flip automorphism method introduced by Isono and Marrakchi [Reference Isono and MarrakchiIM19]. The conclusions (C1) and (C2) of Theorems 4.2 and 4.6, respectively, assert that:

  1. (C1) $\exists$ a partition $S_1\sqcup S_2=\{1,\ldots,n\}$ such that $\Delta (A\rtimes \Gamma _{S_i})\prec ^s_{M\bar \otimes L(\Lambda )} M\bar \otimes P_i$, for all $i\in \{1,2\}$;

  2. (C2) $\exists$ a partition $T_1\sqcup T_2=\{1,\ldots,n\}$ such that $P_i\prec ^s_{M} A\rtimes \Gamma _{T_i}$, for all $i\in \{1,2\}.$

Note that conclusion (C2) cannot be directly obtained by using Popa's spectral gap arguments (Lemma 3.6) since if $P_1$ and $P_2$ are both amenable relative to $A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat i}$ for some $i\in \overline {1,n}$, one cannot immediately derive a contradiction. To overcome this difficulty, we first show conclusion (C1) and use this result in order to prove conclusion (C2). Finally, note that since $P_1$ and $P_2$ do not hold any ‘relative solidity properties’, Lemma 3.6 cannot be directly applied for proving conclusion (C1). Hence, we proceed by using the flip automorphism method [Reference Isono and MarrakchiIM19] in order to obtain a situation where Lemma 3.6 can actually be applied.

Lemma 4.4 Let $L(\Lambda )=P_1\bar \otimes P_2$ be a tensor product decomposition into II$_1$ factors and denote $\mathcal {M}=M\bar \otimes L(\Lambda )$.

Then there is a partition $S_1\sqcup S_2=\{1,\ldots,n\}$ and a projection $0\neq z\in \Delta (L(\Gamma ))'\cap \mathcal {M}$ such that:

  • $\Delta (L(\Gamma _i))z$ is strongly non-amenable relative to $M\bar \otimes P_{1}$ inside $\mathcal {M}$ for all $i\in S_2$;

  • $\Delta (L(\Gamma _i))z$ is strongly non-amenable relative to $M\bar \otimes P_{2}$ inside $\mathcal {M}$ for all $i\in S_1.$

Proof. Let $i\in \{1,\ldots,n\}$. Since $\Gamma _i$ is non-amenable, by [Reference Krogager and VaesKV15, Proposition 2.4] we get that $\Delta (L(\Gamma _i))$ is strongly non-amenable relative to $M\otimes 1$ inside $\mathcal {M}$. It follows that for every non-zero projection $z\in \Delta (L(\Gamma ))'\cap \mathcal {M}$, there exist $f(i,z)\in \{1,2\}$ and a non-zero projection $p(i,z)\in \Delta (L(\Gamma ))'\cap \mathcal {M}$ with $p(i,z)\leq z$ such that

(4.1)\begin{equation} \Delta(L(\Gamma_i))p(i,z) \text{ is strongly non-amenable relative to } M\bar\otimes P_{f(i,z)} \text{ inside } \mathcal{M}. \end{equation}

Indeed, otherwise there exists a non-zero projection $z\in \Delta (L(\Gamma ))'\cap \mathcal {M}$ such that for any $k\in \{1,2\}$ and non-zero projection $z_0\in \Delta (L(\Gamma ))'\cap \mathcal {M}$ with $z_0\leq z$, there exists a non-zero projection $\tilde z_0\in \Delta (L(\Gamma ))'\cap \mathcal {M}$ with $\tilde z_0\leq z_0$ for which $\Delta (L(\Gamma _i))\tilde z_0$ is amenable relative to $M\bar \otimes P_k$ inside $\mathcal {M}$. By using [Reference Popa and VaesPV14, Proposition 2.7] we derive that there exists a non-zero projection $\tilde z_1\in \Delta (L(\Gamma ))'\cap \mathcal {M}$ with $\tilde z_1\leq z$ for which $\Delta (L(\Gamma _i))\tilde z_1$ is amenable relative to $M\bar \otimes 1$ inside $\mathcal {M}$, contradiction.

By applying (4.1) finitely many times, the proof will be obtained as follows. Define $z_1=p(1,1)$ and $f(1)=f(1,1)$. For any $i\in \{2,\ldots,n\}$ we recursively define $z_i=p(i,z_{i-1})$ and $f(i)=f(i,z_{i-1})$. Note that $z_1\ge z_2\ge \cdots \ge z_n$ are non-zero projections in $\Delta (L(\Gamma ))'\cap \mathcal {M}$. Hence, the lemma follows by letting $S_1=f^{-1}(2)$, $S_2=f^{-1}(1)$, and $z=z_n$.

We continue with the following notation that will be used in the following lemma, but also in the proof of Theorem 4.2. For any $1\leq j\leq n$, denote $\Psi ^{j,4}={\rm id}_{M}\otimes {\rm id}_{M}\otimes {\rm id}_{M}\otimes \Psi ^j$ and $\alpha ^{j,5}= {\rm id}_{M}\otimes {\rm id}_{M}\otimes {\rm id}_{M}\otimes {\rm id}_{M}\otimes \alpha ^j$. By letting $\mathcal {M}=M\bar \otimes L(\Lambda )$, note that $\Psi ^j(p)=p\otimes 1$ and $\Psi ^{j,4}(\mathcal {M}\bar \otimes \mathcal {M})\subset M\bar \otimes L(\Lambda ) \bar \otimes M \bar \otimes pMp \bar \otimes L(\Gamma _j).$

Lemma 4.5 Let $\sigma \in {\rm Aut}(\mathcal {M}\bar \otimes \mathcal {M})$ be an automorphism for which $\sigma _{|(M\otimes 1)\bar \otimes (M\otimes 1)}={\rm id}_{(M\otimes 1)\bar \otimes (M\otimes 1)}$ and $(1\otimes L(\Lambda ))\bar \otimes (1\otimes L(\Lambda ))$ is $\sigma$-invariant. Then $\Psi ^{j,4}(\sigma (\Delta (M)\bar \otimes \Delta (M))z$ is not $\alpha ^{j,5}$-rigid, for all non-zero projections $z\in \Psi ^{j,4}(\sigma (\Delta (M)\bar \otimes \Delta (M))'\cap M\bar \otimes L(\Lambda ) \bar \otimes M \bar \otimes pMp \bar \otimes L(\Gamma _j)$ and $j\in \overline {1,n}$.

Proof. By assuming the contrary, there exist $j\in \{1,\ldots,n\}$ and a projection $z$ as in the statement such that $\Psi ^{j,4}(\sigma (\Delta (M)\bar \otimes \Delta (M))z$ is $\alpha ^{j,5}$-rigid. Hence, for any $\epsilon >0$, there is $t_0>0$ such that

\[ \| \Psi^{j,4}(\sigma( v_g\otimes v_g\otimes v_h\otimes v_h ))z - \alpha_t^{j,5}( \Psi^{j,4}(\sigma( v_g\otimes v_g\otimes v_h\otimes v_h ))z) \|_2\leq \epsilon, \]

for all $g,h\in \Lambda$ and $|t|\leq t_0.$ Since $\sigma$ acts trivially on $( M\otimes 1)\bar \otimes ( M \otimes 1)$, we obtain that

\[ \| \Psi^{j,4}(\sigma( 1\otimes v_g\otimes 1\otimes v_h ))z - \alpha_t^{j,5}( \Psi^{j,4}(\sigma( 1\otimes v_g\otimes 1\otimes v_h ))z) \|_2\leq \epsilon, \]

for all $g,h\in \Lambda$ and $|t|\leq t_0.$ If we let $\mathcal {G}=\{\Psi ^{j,4}(\sigma ( 1\otimes v_g\otimes 1\otimes v_h ))|\; g,h\in \Lambda \}$, we get that $\mathcal {G}''=\Psi ^{j,4}(1\otimes L(\Lambda )\otimes 1\bar \otimes L(\Lambda ))=1\otimes L(\Lambda )\otimes 1\bar \otimes \Psi ^j(L(\Lambda ))$ since $(1\otimes L(\Lambda ))\bar \otimes (1\otimes L(\Lambda ))$ is $\sigma$-invariant. Note that $\mathcal {N}_{M\bar \otimes L(\Lambda )\bar \otimes M\bar \otimes pMp\bar \otimes L(\Gamma _j)}(\mathcal {G}'')\subset 1\otimes 1\otimes 1\otimes (\Psi ^{j}(L(\Lambda ))'\cap (pMp\bar \otimes L(\Gamma _j)))$.

By applying Proposition 3.2 we obtain a non-zero projection $z_0\in \Psi ^{j}(L(\Lambda ))'\cap (pMp\bar \otimes L(\Gamma _j))$ such that $\Psi ^{j}(L(\Lambda ))z_0$ is $({\rm id}\otimes \alpha ^j)$-rigid. Since $\Psi ^j(B)=B\otimes 1$ and $\Psi ^{j}(pMp)'\cap (pMp\bar \otimes L(\Gamma _j))=\mathbb {C} (p\otimes 1)$, it follows from Proposition 3.2 that $\Psi ^{j}(pMp)$ is $({\rm id}\otimes \alpha ^j)$-rigid, and hence, $\Psi ^{j}(M)$ is $({\rm id}\otimes \alpha ^j)$-rigid. This shows that $L(\Gamma _j)$ is $\alpha ^j$-rigid: contradiction.

Proof of Theorem 4.2 Denote $\mathcal {M}=M\bar \otimes L(\Lambda )$ and $\tilde {\mathcal {M}}=M\bar \otimes M$. For proving this theorem, we use the following variation of the flip automorphism method from [Reference Isono and MarrakchiIM19]. Namely, since $L(\Lambda )=P_1\bar \otimes P_2$, we define $\sigma _{P_1}\in {\rm Aut}(\mathcal {M}\bar \otimes \mathcal {M})$ by letting $\sigma _{P_1}(m\otimes p_1\otimes p_2 \otimes m'\otimes p_1'\otimes p_2')=m\otimes p_1'\otimes p_2 \otimes m'\otimes p_1\otimes p_2'$, for all $m,m'\in M,p_1,p_1'\in P_1, p_2,p_2'\in P_2$.

By applying Lemmas 4.4 and 2.4 we obtain a partition $S_1\sqcup S_2=\{1,\ldots,n\}$ and a non-zero projection $z\in \Delta (L(\Gamma ))'\cap \mathcal {M}$ such that

(4.2)\begin{equation} \begin{aligned} & \Delta(L(\Gamma_i))z\otimes 1 \text{ is strongly non-amenable relative to }(M\bar\otimes P_2)\bar\otimes (M\bar\otimes P_1) \text{ inside } \mathcal{M}\bar\otimes\mathcal{M},\\ & 1\otimes \Delta(L(\Gamma_j))z \text{ is strongly non-amenable relative to }(M\bar\otimes P_2)\bar\otimes (M\bar\otimes P_1) \text{ inside } \mathcal{M}\bar\otimes\mathcal{M}, \end{aligned} \end{equation}

for all $i\in S_1$ and $j\in S_2$. By applying the flip automorphism $\sigma _{P_1}$ to (4.2), we derive that

\begin{align*} \sigma_{P_1}(\Delta(L(\Gamma_i))z\otimes 1) \text{ is strongly non-amenable relative to }\mathcal{M}\bar\otimes (M\otimes 1) \text{ inside } \mathcal{M}\bar\otimes\mathcal{M},\\ \sigma_{P_1}(1\otimes \Delta(L(\Gamma_j))z) \text{ is strongly non-amenable relative to }\mathcal{M}\bar\otimes (M\otimes 1) \text{ inside } \mathcal{M}\bar\otimes\mathcal{M}, \end{align*}

for all $i\in S_1$ and $j\in S_2$. By using Lemma 2.4, we further deduce that

(4.3)\begin{equation} \begin{aligned} & \sigma_{P_1}(\Delta(L(\Gamma_i))z\otimes 1) \text{ is strongly non-amenable relative to }\mathcal{M}\bar\otimes (M\otimes 1) \text{ inside } \mathcal{M}\bar\otimes\tilde{\mathcal{M}},\\ & \sigma_{P_1}(1\otimes \Delta(L(\Gamma_j))z) \text{ is strongly non-amenable relative to }\mathcal{M}\bar\otimes (M\otimes 1) \text{ inside } \mathcal{M}\bar\otimes\tilde{\mathcal{M}}, \end{aligned} \end{equation}

for all $i\in S_1$ and $j\in S_2$. Denote $\widehat z=\sigma _{P_1}(z\otimes z)\in \sigma _{P_1}(\Delta (L(\Gamma ))\bar \otimes \Delta (L(\Gamma )))'\cap (\mathcal {M}\bar \otimes \mathcal {M})$ and note that $\widehat z\leq \sigma _{P_1}(z\otimes 1)$, $\widehat z\leq \sigma _{P_1}(1\otimes z)$. For ease of notation, we denote $Q_i=\Delta (L(\Gamma _i))\otimes 1$ and $R_i=\Delta (L(\Gamma _{\widehat i})\bar \otimes \Delta (L(\Gamma ))$, for all $i\in S_1$. Similarly, denote $Q_j=1\otimes \Delta (L(\Gamma _j))$ and $R_j=\Delta (L(\Gamma ))\bar \otimes \Delta (L(\Gamma _{\widehat j})$, for all $j\in S_2$. Note that $Q_i \vee R_i=\Delta (L(\Gamma ))\bar \otimes \Delta (L(\Gamma ))$, for any $i\in \{1,\ldots,n\}$.

By applying a similar argument to that used in the proof of Lemma 4.4, we deduce from (4.3) that there exist a non-zero projection $\tilde z\in \sigma _{P_1}(\Delta (L(\Gamma ))\bar \otimes \Delta (L(\Gamma )))'\cap (\mathcal {M}\bar \otimes \tilde {\mathcal {M}})$ and a function $\varphi :\{1,\ldots,n\}\to \{1,\ldots,n\}$ such that

(4.4)\begin{equation} \sigma_{P_1}(Q_i)\tilde z \text{ is strongly non-amenable relative to } \mathcal{M}\bar\otimes M\bar\otimes (A\rtimes \Gamma_{\widehat{\varphi(i)}}), \end{equation}

for all $i\in \{1,\ldots,n\}$. By Lemma 3.6, we get that for any $i\in \{1,\ldots,n\}$,

(4.5)\begin{equation} \Psi^{\varphi(i),4}(\sigma_{P_1}(R_i)\tilde{z}) \text{ is } \alpha^{\varphi (i),5} \text{ -rigid}. \end{equation}

Next, we claim that the map $\varphi$ is bijective. If this does not hold, it is easy to see that we can deduce from (4.4) that there exists $j\in \{1,\ldots,n\}$ such that

(4.6)\begin{equation} \Psi^{j,4}(\sigma_{P_1}(\Delta(L(\Gamma))\bar\otimes \Delta(L(\Gamma)))\tilde{z}) \text{ is }\alpha^{j,5}\text{-rigid}. \end{equation}

Using the position of $B\subset A$, and $\sigma _{P_1}(\Delta (B)\bar \otimes \Delta (B))\subset \mathcal {M}\bar \otimes (M\otimes 1)$, we obtain that

(4.7)\begin{equation} \Psi^{j,4}(\sigma_{P_1}(\Delta(A)\bar\otimes \Delta(A)) \text{ is } \alpha^{j,5} \text{-rigid}. \end{equation}

Relations (4.6) and (4.7) in combination with Proposition 3.2 gives a contradiction to Lemma 4.5. This shows that $\varphi$ is indeed bijective. Next, we claim that for all $i\in \{1,\ldots,n\}$,

(4.8)\begin{equation} \sigma_{P_1}(R_i)\tilde{z}\prec^s_{\mathcal{M}\bar\otimes \tilde{\mathcal{M}}} \mathcal{M}\bar\otimes M\bar\otimes (A\rtimes \Gamma_{\widehat{g(i)}}), \end{equation}

Assume by contradiction that there is $i\in \{1,\ldots, n\}$ for which (4.8) does not hold. Then by using [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Lemma 2.4(2)], it follows that, up to replacing $\tilde z$ by a smaller non-zero projection, we have $\sigma _{P_1}(R_i)\tilde {z}\nprec _{\mathcal {M}\bar \otimes \tilde {\mathcal {M}}} \mathcal {M}\bar \otimes M\bar \otimes (A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat {g(i)}})$. Using (4.4) and (4.5) we may apply Lemma 3.6 to deduce that $\Psi ^{j,4}(\sigma _{P_1}(\Delta (L(\Gamma ))\bar \otimes \Delta (L(\Gamma )))\tilde {z}) \text { is }\alpha ^{j,5}\text {-rigid}.$ As before, Proposition 3.2 leads to a contradiction.

Finally, by applying [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Lemma 2.8(2)] finitely many times, we deduce from (4.8) that

\[ \sigma_{P_1}(\Delta(L(\Gamma_{\widehat{S_1}}))\bar\otimes \Delta(L(\Gamma_{\widehat{S_2}}))) \prec_{\mathcal{M}\bar\otimes \tilde{\mathcal{M}}} \mathcal{M}\bar\otimes (M \otimes 1). \]

By applying Lemma 2.4 we further obtain that $\sigma _{P_1}(\Delta (L(\Gamma _{\widehat {S_1}}))\bar \otimes \Delta (L(\Gamma _{\widehat {S_2}}))) \prec _{\mathcal {M}\bar \otimes {\mathcal {M}}} \mathcal {M}\bar \otimes (M \otimes 1)$. By applying the flip automorphism $\sigma _{P_1}$ to the previous intertwining relation, we deduce that $\Delta (L(\Gamma _{S_i}))\prec _{\mathcal {M}} M\bar \otimes P_i$, for all $i\in \{1,2\}$. Since $\Delta (A)\prec ^s_{\mathcal {M}}B\otimes 1$, we may use [Reference Berbec and VaesBV14, Lemma 2.3] to get that $\Delta (A\rtimes \Gamma _{S_i})\prec _{\mathcal {M}} M\bar \otimes P_i$, for all $i\in \{1,2\}$. Since $\mathcal {N}_{\mathcal {M}}(\Delta (A\rtimes \Gamma _{S_i}))'\cap \mathcal {M}\subset \Delta (M)'\cap \mathcal {M}=\mathbb {C}1$, we obtain $\Delta (A\rtimes \Gamma _{S_i})\prec ^s_{\mathcal {M}} M\bar \otimes P_i$, for all $i\in \{1,2\}$.

For showing that $S_1$ and $S_2$ are non-empty sets, we suppose the contrary. Hence, without loss of generality, assume that $S_2$ is empty. This shows that $\Delta (M)\prec _{\mathcal {M}} M\bar \otimes P_1$, which implies from [Reference IoanaIoa11, Lemma 9.2] that $L(\Lambda )\prec _{L(\Lambda )} P_1$. This shows that $P_2$ is not diffuse: a contradiction.

4.2 Step 2

By using Step 1, we obtain the following intertwining result. Recall that we are using Notation 3.7 and Assumption 4.1.

Theorem 4.6 Let $L(\Lambda )=P_1\bar \otimes P_2$ be a tensor product decomposition into II$_1$ factors.

Then there is a partition $T_1\sqcup T_2=\{1,\ldots,n\}$ such that $P_i\prec ^s_{M} A\rtimes \Gamma _{T_i}$, for all $i\in \{1,2\}.$

Throughout the proof we are using the following notation: if $N$ is a tracial von Neumann algebra and $P\subset pNp$ and $Q\subset qNq$ are von Neumann subalgebras, we denote $P\prec _N^{s'}Q$ if $P\prec _N Qq'$, for any non-zero projection $q'\in Q'\cap qNq$.

Proof of Theorem 4.6 Theorem 4.2 implies that there exist projections $r_1\in \Delta (L(\Gamma _{S_1}))$, $q_1\in M\bar \otimes P_1$, a non-zero partial isometry $w_1\in q_1 (M\bar \otimes M) r_1$ and a $*$-homomorphism $\varphi _1: r_1\Delta (L(\Gamma _{S_1}))r_1\to q_1(M\bar \otimes P_1)q_1$ such that $\varphi _1(x)w_1=w_1x$, for all $x\in r_1\Delta (L(\Gamma _{S_1}))r_1$. Fix an arbitrary $j_0\in S_1$. Since $L(\Gamma _{j_0})$ is a II$_1$ factor we can apply [Reference Chifan, de Santiago and SucpikarnonCdSS18, Lemma 4.5] and therefore assume without loss of generality that $r_1\in L(\Gamma _{j_0})$. In addition, we can assume that the support projection of $E_{M\bar \otimes P_1}(w_1w_1^*)$ equals $q_1$. For any $j\in S_1$, denote $Q_1^j=\varphi _1 (r_1\Delta (L(\Gamma _j))r_1)\subset q_1(M\bar \otimes P_1)q_1$ and let $Q_1=\bigvee _{j\in S_1} Q_1^j$. Note that for any subset $S\subset S_1$, we have $\Delta (L(\Gamma _S))\prec ^{s'}_{M\bar \otimes P_1} \bigvee _{j\in S}Q_1^j$. Indeed, let $S\subset S_1$ and consider a non-zero projection $z\in Q_1'\cap q_1 (M\bar \otimes P_1) q_1$. Note that $\tilde w_1:=zw_1\neq 0$ since otherwise $zE_{M\bar \otimes P_1}(w_1w_1^*)=0$, which implies that $z=0$, false. This shows that the $*$-homomorphism $\tilde \varphi _1:r_1\Delta (L(\Gamma _{S}))r_1\to \bigvee _{j\in S} Q_1^jz$ satisfies $\tilde \varphi _1 (x)\tilde w_1=\tilde w_1 x$, for all $x\in r_1\Delta (L(\Gamma _{S}))r_1.$ By replacing $\tilde w_1$ by the partial isometry from its polar decomposition, we derive that $\Delta (L(\Gamma _S))\prec _{M\bar \otimes P_1} \bigvee _{j\in S}Q_1^jz$. By using [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Lemma 2.4] it follows that $\Delta (L(\Gamma _S))\prec ^{s'}_{M\bar \otimes P_1} \bigvee _{j\in S}Q_1^j$. By applying [Reference DrimbeDri20b, Lemma 2.3], we derive that for any subset $S\subset S_1$,

(4.9)\begin{equation} \Delta(L(\Gamma_S))\prec^{s'}_{M\bar\otimes M} \bigvee_{j\in S} Q_1^j. \end{equation}

The rest of the proof is divided between three claims.

Claim 1 For any $j\in S_1$ and non-zero projection $z\in Q_1'\cap q_1 (M\bar \otimes P_1) q_1$, there exist $k\in \{1,\ldots,n\}$ and a non-zero projection $z_0 \in Q_1'\cap q_1 (M\bar \otimes P_1) q_1$ with $z_0\leq z$ such that $Q_1^{j} z_0$ is strongly non-amenable relative to $M\bar \otimes (A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat {k}})$ inside $M\bar \otimes M$.

Proof of Claim 1 We assume by contradiction that there exist $j\in S_1$ and a non-zero projection $z\in Q_1'\cap q_1 (M\bar \otimes P_1) q_1$ such that $Q_1^{j} z$ is amenable relative to $M\bar \otimes (A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat {k}}),$ for all $k\in \{1,\ldots,n\}$. By applying [Reference Popa and VaesPV14, Proposition 2.7] we get that $Q_1^{j}z$ is amenable relative to $M\otimes 1$ inside $M\bar \otimes M$. Relation (4.9) implies that $\Delta (L(\Gamma _j))\prec ^{}_{M\bar \otimes M} Q_1^j z.$ We can apply [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Lemma 2.4(3) and Lemma 2.6(3)] and derive that there exists a non-zero projection $r'\in \Delta (L(\Gamma _{j}))'\cap M\bar \otimes M$ such that $\Delta (L(\Gamma _{j}))r'$ is amenable relative to $Q_1^{j}z\oplus \mathbb {C}(1-z)$. Using [Reference Ozawa and PopaOP10, Proposition 2.4(3)] we derive that $\Delta (L(\Gamma _{j}))r'$ is amenable relative to $M\otimes 1$. By using [Reference Ioana, Popa and VaesIPV13, Lemma 10.2(5)] we deduce that $\Gamma _{j}$ is amenable: a contradiction. Thus, there exist $k\in \{1,\ldots, n\}$ such that $Q_1^{j} z$ is non-amenable relative to $M\bar \otimes (A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat {k}}).$ By [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Lemma 2.6], there exists a non-zero projection $z_0 \in \mathcal {N}_{q_1(M\bar \otimes M)q_1}(Q_1^j)'\cap q_1 (M\bar \otimes M_1) q_1\subset Q_1'\cap q_1(M\bar \otimes P_1)q_1$ with $z_0\leq z$ such that $Q_1^{j} z_0$ is strongly non-amenable relative to $M\bar \otimes (A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat {k}}).$

By applying Claim 1 finitely many times and proceeding as in the proof of Lemma 4.4, there exist a non-zero projection $z\in Q_1'\cap q_1 (M\bar \otimes P_1) q_1$ and a map $\overline {1,n}\ni j\to k_j\in \overline {1,n}$ such that

(4.10)\begin{equation} Q_1^{j} z \text{ is strongly non-amenable relative to } M\bar\otimes (A\rtimes\Gamma_{\widehat {k_{j}}}), \text{ for any }j\in\overline{1,n}. \end{equation}

Claim 2 We claim that $P_2\prec _M^s A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat {k_j}}$, for all $j\in S_1$.

Proof of Claim 2 Fix an arbitrary $j\in S_1$. We are in one of the following situations. First, if we assume that $(1\otimes P_2)z\prec _{M\bar \otimes M}M\bar \otimes (A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat {k_j}})$, we get $P_2\prec _M A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat {k_j}}$. Since $\mathcal {N}_{pMp}(P_2)'\cap pMp\subset L(\Gamma )'\cap pMp=\mathbb {C}p$, the claim follows from [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Lemma 2.4(3)]. Second, assume that $(1\otimes P_2)z\nprec _{M\bar \otimes M}M\bar \otimes (A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat {k_j}})$. Since $Q_1^j z\subset ((1\otimes P_2)z)'\cap z (M\bar \otimes M) z$, (4.10) implies that $((1\otimes P_2)z)'\cap z (M\bar \otimes M) z$ is strongly non-amenable relative to $M\bar \otimes (A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat {k_j}})$. Altogether, we can apply Lemma 3.6 to deduce that $(1\otimes \Psi ^{k_j}) (z(M\bar \otimes L(\Lambda ))z)$ is $({\rm id}\otimes {\rm id}\otimes \alpha ^{k_j})$-rigid. Since $M\bar \otimes L(\Lambda )$ is a II$_1$ factor and $(1\otimes \Psi ^{k_j})(1\otimes B)\subset 1\otimes B\otimes 1$, it follows that $(1\otimes \Psi ^{k_j}) (M\bar \otimes M)$ is $({\rm id}\otimes {\rm id}\otimes \alpha ^{k_j})$-rigid, which implies that $L(\Gamma _{k_j})$ is $\alpha ^{k_j}$-rigid: a contradiction. This completes the proof of the claim.

Note that $Q_1$ and $(1\otimes P_2)q_1$ are commuting subalgebras of $q_1 (M\bar \otimes M) q_1$ Thus, (4.10) together with Lemma 3.6 imply that for any $j\in S_1$ we have

(4.11)\begin{equation} (1\otimes\Psi^{k_j})\biggl(\bigvee_{i\in S_1\setminus\{j\}}Q_1^iz \vee (1\otimes P_2)z\biggr) \text{ is } ({\rm id}\otimes{\rm id}\otimes \alpha^{k_j})\text{-rigid.} \end{equation}

We now ready to prove the following.

Claim 3 The map $S_1\ni j \to k_j\in \{1,\ldots,n\}$ is injective.

Proof of Claim 3 Assume by contradiction that there exist two distinct elements $j_1,j_2\in S_1$ such that $k:=k_{j_1}=k_{j_2}$. Thus, $(S_1\setminus \{j_1\})\cup (S_1\setminus \{j_2\})=S_1$. Since the algebras $Q_1^jz, j\in S_1$, are commuting, we deduce from (4.11) that $(1\otimes \Psi ^k)(Q_1z) \text { is } ({\rm id}\otimes {\rm id}\otimes \alpha ^{k})\text {-rigid.}$ As in the proof of Claim 1, we note that $zw_1\neq 0$. Note also that $Q_1zw_1=zw_1r_1\Delta (L(\Gamma _{S_1}))r_1$. By applying Proposition 3.2 we obtain a non-zero projection $e_1\in (1\otimes \Psi ^k)(\Delta (L(\Gamma )))'\cap M\bar \otimes M\bar \otimes L(\Gamma )$ such that

(4.12)\begin{equation} (1\otimes\Psi^k)(\Delta(L(\Gamma_{S_1})))e_1 \text{ is } ({\rm id}\otimes{\rm id}\otimes \alpha^{k})\text{-rigid.} \end{equation}

Since $z\in q_1(M\bar \otimes P_1)q_1$ and $M\bar \otimes P_1$ is a II$_1$ factor, one can check that (4.11) implies

(4.13)\begin{equation} \Psi^k(P_2) \text{ is } ({\rm id}\otimes \alpha^{k}) \text{ -rigid.} \end{equation}

Next, since $\Delta (L(\Gamma _{S_2}))\prec ^s_{M\bar \otimes L(\Lambda )} M\bar \otimes P_2$, we obtain from [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Remark 2.2] that

\[ (1\otimes \Psi^k)(\Delta(L(\Gamma_{S_2})))\prec^s_{M\bar\otimes M\bar\otimes L(\Gamma_k)} M\bar\otimes \Psi^k(P_2). \]

Therefore, $(1\otimes \Psi ^k)(\Delta (L(\Gamma _{S_2})))e_1\prec _{M\bar \otimes M\bar \otimes L(\Gamma _k)} M\bar \otimes \Psi (P_2)$, which implies by (4.13) that there is a projection $0\neq e_2\in (1\otimes \Psi ^k)(\Delta (L(\Gamma _{S_2})))'\cap (M\bar \otimes M\bar \otimes L(\Gamma _k))$ with $e_2\leq e_1$ such that

(4.14)\begin{equation} (1\otimes\Psi^k)(\Delta(L(\Gamma_{S_2})))e_2 \text{ is } ({\rm id}\otimes{\rm id}\otimes \alpha^{k})\text{-rigid.} \end{equation}

Note that (4.12) implies that $e_2(1\otimes \Psi ^k)(\Delta (L(\Gamma _{S_1})))e_2 \text { is } ({\rm id}\otimes {\rm id}\otimes \alpha ^{k})\text {-rigid.}$ Together with (4.14) and the fact that $\Psi ^k(A)\subset A\otimes 1$, we deduce from Proposition 3.2 that there exists a non-zero projection $e_3\in (1\otimes \Psi ^k)(\Delta (M))'\cap M\bar \otimes M\bar \otimes L(\Gamma _k)$ such that

(4.15)\begin{equation} (1\otimes\Psi^k)(\Delta(M))e_3 \text{ is } ({\rm id}\otimes{\rm id}\otimes \alpha^{k})\text{-rigid.} \end{equation}

This implies that for any $\epsilon >0$, there exists $t_0>0$ such that for all $|t|\leq t_0$ and $g\in \Lambda$,

\[ \|(1\otimes \Psi^k)(v_g\otimes v_g)e_3 -({\rm id}\otimes{\rm id}\otimes \alpha_t^{k}) ((1\otimes \Psi^k)(v_g\otimes v_g)e_3) \|_2\leq \epsilon, \]

and, therefore,

\[ \|(1\otimes \Psi^k)(1\otimes v_g)e_3 -({\rm id}\otimes{\rm id}\otimes \alpha_t^{k}) ((1\otimes \Psi)(1\otimes v_g)e_3) \|_2\leq \epsilon. \]

Note that $\Psi ^k(B)\subset B\otimes 1$. By applying Proposition 3.2 we get that $\Psi ^k(M)e_0$ is $({\rm id}\otimes \alpha ^k)$-rigid for a projection $0\neq e_0\in \Psi ^k(M)'\cap ( M\bar \otimes L(\Gamma _k))$. Since $\Gamma _k$ is icc, we get $\Psi ^k(M)'\cap ( M\bar \otimes L(\Gamma _k))=\mathbb {C}1$. Thus, we obtain that $L(\Gamma _k)$ is $\alpha ^k$-rigid, contradiction.

Denote $R_1=\{k_j\mid j\in S_1\}\subset \{1,\ldots,n\}$. Claim 3 implies that $|S_1|=|R_1|$ while Claim 2 together with [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Lemma 2.8(2)] gives that $P_1\prec _M^s B\rtimes \Lambda _{\widehat {R_1}}$. In a similar way, there exists a subset $R_2\subset \{1,\ldots,n\}$ with $|S_2|=|R_2|$ such that $P_2\prec _M^s A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat {R_2}}$. By using [Reference Chifan, Diaz-Arias and DrimbeCDD21, Proposition 4.4] we deduce that $L(\Gamma )\prec _M^s A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat {R_1}\cup \widehat {R_2}}$. Using [Reference Berbec and VaesBV14, Lemma 2.3] we get that $M\prec _{M} A\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat {R_1}\cup \widehat {R_2}}$, which implies that $\widehat {R_1}\cup \widehat {R_2}=\{1,\ldots,n\}$.

Finally, we let $T_1=\widehat {R_1}$ and $T_2=\widehat {R_2}$. Since $S_1\sqcup S_2=\{1,\ldots,n\}$ is a partition, it follows that $T_1\sqcup T_2=\{1,\ldots,n\}$ is a partition as well. This ends the proof.

5. From unitary conjugacy of subalgebras to cohomologous cocycles

In this section we prove Proposition 5.1 which provides sufficient conditions at the von Neumann algebra level for untwisting the underlying cocycle of an orbit equivalence of irreducible actions.

Throughout this section we will use the well-known fact that if $\Gamma \curvearrowright (X,\mu )$ and $\Lambda \curvearrowright (Y,\nu )$ are free ergodic pmp actions such that there is a measure space isomorphism $\theta :X\to Y$ with $\theta (\Gamma x)=\Lambda \theta (x)$, for almost every $x\in X$, then the induced isomorphism of von Neumann algebras $\pi : L^\infty (X) \to L^\infty (Y)$ given by $\pi (a)=a\circ \theta ^{-1}$ extends to an isomorphism $\pi : L^\infty (X)\rtimes \Gamma \to L^\infty (Y)\rtimes \Lambda$ satisfying $\pi (u_g)=v_{\theta \circ g \circ \theta ^{-1}}$, for any $g\in \Gamma$. Here and throughout the section, we denote by $v_{\phi }\in \mathcal {U}(L^\infty (Y)\rtimes \Lambda )$ the associated unitary of $\phi \in [\mathcal {R}(\Lambda \curvearrowright Y)]$; see [Reference Anantharaman and PopaAP10, § 1.5.2] for more details.

Proposition 5.1 Let $\Gamma =\Gamma _1\times \cdots \times \Gamma _n\curvearrowright (X,\mu )$ and $\Lambda =\Lambda _1\times \cdots \times \Lambda _n\curvearrowright (Y,\nu )$ be free, irreducible, pmp actions such that are OE via a map $\theta :X\to Y$. Denote by $\pi :L^\infty (X)\rtimes \Gamma \to L^\infty (Y)\rtimes \Lambda$ the $*$-isomorphism associated to $\theta$ and let $c:\Gamma \times X\to \Lambda$ be the Zimmer cocycle associated to $\theta$.

If there exist $u_1,\ldots,u_n\in \mathcal {U}(L^\infty (Y)\rtimes \Lambda )$ such that $\pi (L^\infty (X)\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat i})= u_i(L^\infty (Y)\rtimes \Lambda _{\widehat i})u_i^*$, for any $i\in \{1,\ldots,n\}$, then $c$ is cohomologous to a group isomorphism $\delta :\Gamma \to \Lambda$.

We first need the following elementary result. For completeness, we provide a proof.

Lemma 5.2 Let $\Gamma \overset {}{\curvearrowright } (X,\mu )$ and $\Lambda \overset {}{\curvearrowright } (Y,\nu )$ be free, ergodic, pmp actions. For any $1\leq i\leq 2$, assume that there exist a $*$-isomorphism $\pi _i: L^\infty (X)\rtimes \Gamma \to L^\infty (Y)\rtimes \Lambda$ such that $\pi _i (L^\infty (X))=L^\infty (Y)$, let $\theta _i:X\to Y$ be the measure space isomorphism defined by $\pi _i(a)=a\circ \theta _i^{-1}$, for any $a\in L^\infty (X)$, and let $c_i:\Gamma \times X\to \Lambda$ be the Zimmer cocycle associated to $\theta _i$.

If there exists $\omega \in \mathcal {U}(L^\infty (Y)\rtimes \Lambda )$ such that $\pi _2={\rm Ad}(\omega ) \circ \pi _1$, then the cocycles $c_1$ and $c_2$ are cohomologous.

Proof. Since $\omega \in \mathcal {N}_{L^\infty (Y)\rtimes \Lambda }(L^\infty (Y))$, we can write $\omega =b v_{\varphi }$, for some $b\in \mathcal {U}(L^\infty (Y))$ and $\varphi \in [\mathcal {R}(\Lambda \curvearrowright Y)]$ (see, for instance, [Reference Anantharaman and PopaAP10, Lemma 12.1.16]). Take a measurable map $\psi : Y\to \Lambda$ such that $\varphi ^{-1}(y)=\psi (y)y$, for almost every $y\in Y$. For any $a\in L^\infty (X)$, we have $a\circ \theta _2^{-1}=\omega (a\circ \theta _1^{-1}) \omega ^*=a\circ \theta _1^{-1}\circ \varphi ^{-1}$. This shows that $\theta _2=\varphi \circ \theta _1$. We will prove the lemma by showing that

(5.1)\begin{equation} c_1(g,x)\psi(\theta_2(x))=\psi(\theta_2(gx))c_2(g,x), \text{ for all } g\in\Gamma \text{ and almost every }x\in X. \end{equation}

To this end, fix an arbitrary $g\in \Gamma$. Define $\tilde \psi =\psi \circ \theta _2$. Since for almost every $y\in Y$ and $i\in \{1,2\}$, we have $(\theta _i\circ g \circ \theta _i^{-1})(y)=c_i(g,\theta _i^{-1}(y))y$, it follows that

\begin{align*} c_1(g^{-1}, \theta_2^{-1}(y))\tilde \psi(\theta_2^{-1}(y))y &= c_1(g^{-1}, \theta_1^{-1}(\psi(y)y))\psi(y)y\\ &= (\theta_1\circ g \circ \theta_1^{-1})(\psi(y)y) )= (\theta_1\circ g\circ \theta_1^{-1}\circ \varphi^{-1})(y)\\ &= (\varphi^{-1}\circ \theta_2\circ g \circ \theta_2^{-1})(y)=\psi ((\theta_2\circ g \circ \theta_2^{-1})(y)) (\theta_2\circ g \circ \theta_2^{-1})(y)\\ &= \tilde\psi (g\theta_2^{-1}(y)) c_2(g,\theta_2^{-1}(y))y. \end{align*}

Since $\Lambda \curvearrowright Y$ is free, we obtain that (5.1) holds, thus proving the lemma.

The following lemma is a particular case of [Reference Horbez, Huang and IoanaHHI21, Lemma 3.1] and it goes back to [Reference Monod and ShalomMS06, § 5]. For the convenience of the reader, we provide a short proof for it using von Neumann algebras.

Lemma 5.3 [Reference Horbez, Huang and IoanaHHI21]

Let $\Gamma =\Gamma _1\times \Gamma _2\overset {\sigma }{\curvearrowright } (X,\mu )$ and $\Lambda =\Lambda _1\times \Lambda _2\overset {\rho }{\curvearrowright } (Y,\nu )$ be free, ergodic, pmp actions with $\Gamma _1$ and $\Lambda _1$ acting ergodically. Assume that there exists a measure space isomorphism $\theta : X\to Y$ such that $\theta (\Gamma \cdot x)=\Lambda \cdot \theta (x)$ and $\theta (\Gamma _1\cdot x)=\Lambda _1\cdot \theta (x)$ for almost every $x\in X$. Let $c$ be the Zimmer cocycle associated to $\theta$.

Then there exists a group isomorphism $\delta _2:\Gamma _2\to \Lambda _2$ such that $c(g,x)\in \Lambda _1\delta _2(g_2)$ for every $g=(g_1,g_2)\in \Gamma$ and almost every $x\in X$.

Proof. Denote by $\pi :L^\infty (X)\rtimes \Gamma \to L^\infty (Y)\rtimes \Lambda$ the $*$-isomorphism associated to $\theta$. For ease of notation, we suppress $\pi$. Recall that for each $g\in \Gamma$ we can decompose

(5.2)\begin{equation} u_g=\sum_{\lambda\in \Lambda}1_{Y_{g,\lambda}}v_\lambda, \end{equation}

where $Y_{g,\lambda }=\{y\in Y\mid c(g^{-1},\theta ^{-1}(y))=\lambda ^{-1} \},$ as $\lambda \in \Lambda$. By assumption, $c(g,x)\in \Lambda _1$, for any $g\in \Gamma _1$ and almost every $x\in X$. Hence, we deduce $N:=L^\infty (X)\rtimes \Gamma _1=L^\infty (Y)\rtimes \Lambda _1$.

Next, we fix $g\in \Gamma _2$. Note that the actions $\sigma _{|\Gamma _2}$ and $\rho _{|\Lambda _2}$ extend in a natural way to actions on $N$. We can write $u_g=\sum _{\lambda \in \Lambda _2}b^g_\lambda v_\lambda$, with $b^g_\lambda \in N$, for all $\lambda \in \Lambda _2$. Note that for any $a\in N$ we have $b_\lambda ^g\rho _\lambda (a)=\sigma _g(a)b_\lambda ^g$, for all $\lambda \in \Lambda _2$. Thus, for any $\lambda \in \Lambda _2$, we get $(b_\lambda ^g)^*b_\lambda ^g\in N'\cap M=\mathbb {C}1$. Assume by contradiction that there exist $\lambda _1\neq \lambda _2\in \Lambda _2$ such that $b^g_{\lambda _1}$ and $b^g_{\lambda _2}$ are non-zero. Thus, there exist $\lambda _0\in \Lambda _2\setminus \{e\}$ and a unitary $c\in N$ such that $\rho _{\lambda _0}(a)c=ca$, for all $a\in N$. By writing $c=\sum _{\lambda \in \Lambda _1}c_\lambda v_\lambda$, we have $\rho _{\lambda _0\lambda ^{-1}}(a)\rho _{\lambda ^{-1}}(c_{\lambda })=a\rho _{\lambda ^{-1}}(c_{\lambda })$, for all $a\in L^\infty (Y)$ and $\lambda \in \Lambda _1.$ Since $\lambda _0\lambda ^{-1}$ acts freely, we get that $c=0$: a contradiction. Thus, we have shown that there exist a map $\delta _2:\Gamma _2\to \Lambda _2$ and a unitary $b_g\in N$, as $g\in \Gamma _2$ satisfying

(5.3)\begin{equation} u_g=b_gv_{\delta_2(g)}. \end{equation}

One immediately obtains that $\delta _2:\Gamma _2\to \Lambda _2$ is a group homomorphism. In a similar way, we can write $v_\lambda =\tilde b_{\lambda } u_{\eta _2(\lambda )}$ for some $\tilde b_\lambda \in N$ and a group homomorphism $\eta _2:\Lambda _2\to \Gamma _2$. It follows that $\eta _2\circ \delta _2={\rm Id}$ and $\delta _2\circ \eta _2={\rm Id}$, hence showing that $\delta _2$ is a group isomorphism.

Therefore, by combining (5.2) and (5.3), we deduce that for any $g\in \Gamma _2$, we have that $\mu (Y_{g,\lambda })=0$, for any $\lambda \notin \Lambda _1\delta _2(g)$. This implies that $c(g,x)\in \Lambda _1\delta _2(g)$, for any $g\in \Gamma _2$. Finally, if $g=(g_1,g_2)\in \Gamma$, we get that $c(g,x)=c(g_1,g_2x)c(g_2,x)\in \Lambda _1\delta _2(g_2)$. This ends the proof of the lemma.

5.1 Proof of Proposition 5.1

Fix an arbitrary $i\in \overline {1,n}$. By Lemma 5.2 we get that the underlying Zimmer cocycle $c_i:\Gamma \times X\to \Lambda$ of the orbit equivalence $\theta _i:X\to Y$ associated to $\pi _i:= {\rm Ad}(u_i^*)\circ \pi :L^\infty (X)\rtimes \Gamma \to L^\infty (Y)\rtimes \Lambda$ is cohomologous to $c$. Hence, there is a map $\varphi _i:X\to \Lambda$ such that $c(g,x)=\varphi _i(gx)^{-1}c_i(g,x)\varphi _i(x)$, for all $g\in \Gamma$ and almost every $x\in X$. Note that $\Gamma _{\widehat i}\curvearrowright X$ and $\Lambda _{\widehat i}\curvearrowright Y$ are ergodic. Since $\pi _i(L^\infty (X)\rtimes \Gamma _{\widehat i})=L^\infty (Y)\rtimes \Lambda _{\widehat i}$, we get that $\theta _i(\Gamma _{\widehat i}\cdot x)=\Lambda _{\widehat i}\cdot \theta (x)$, for almost every $x\in X$ and, hence, we obtain from Lemma 5.3 that there is a group isomorphism $\delta _i:\Gamma _i\to \Lambda _i$ such that $c_i(g,x)\in \Lambda _{\widehat i}\delta _i(g_i)$, for every $g=(g_{\widehat i},g_i)\in \Gamma =\Gamma _{\widehat i}\times \Gamma _i$ and almost every $x\in X$.

Next, since $\Lambda =\Lambda _1\times \cdots \times \Lambda _n$ we decompose $\varphi _i=\varphi _i^1\ldots \varphi _i^n$ and $c_i=c_i^1 \ldots c_i^n$ where $\varphi _i^j$ and $c_i^j$ are valued to $\Lambda _j$, for any $j\in \overline {1,n}$. By letting $\varphi =\varphi _1^1\ldots \varphi _n^n:X\to \Lambda$ and $\tilde c:\Gamma \times X\to \Lambda$ defined by $\tilde c(g,x)=\varphi (gx)c(g,x)\varphi (x)^{-1}$, we get $\tilde c(g,x)=\phi (gx) \phi _i(gx)^{-1} c_i(g,x) \phi _i(x) \phi (x)^{-1}$, for all $i\in \overline {1,n}$, $g\in \Gamma$ and almost every $x\in X$. Consequently, we obtain that for every $g=(g_{\widehat i},g_i)\in \Gamma =\Gamma _{\widehat i}\times \Gamma _i$ and almost every $x\in X$, we have $\tilde c^i(g,x)=c_i^i(g,x)=\delta _i(g_i);$ here, we denoted by $\tilde c=\tilde c^1 \ldots \tilde c^n$ the decomposition along $\Lambda =\Lambda _1\times \cdots \times \Lambda _n$. We define the group isomorphism $\delta :\Gamma \to \Lambda$ by letting $\delta (g_1\ldots g_n)=\delta _1(g_1)\ldots \delta _n(g_n)$, for all $g_1\in \Gamma _1,\ldots,g_n\in \Gamma _n$. This shows that $\tilde c (g,x)=\delta (g)$, for all $g\in \Gamma$ and almost every $x\in X$, which entails to $c$ is cohomologous to the group isomorphism $\delta.$

6. Proofs of Theorems A and B and Corollary C

In this section we prove the first three main results stated in the introduction. Towards this, we first prove an abstract version of [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Lemma 5.10] in the sense that we only require the lack of property Gamma instead of relative solidity assumptions. In order to properly state and prove the result, we assume the terminology introduced in Notation 3.7.

Lemma 6.1 Let $L(\Lambda )=P_1\bar \otimes P_2$ be a tensor product decomposition into II$_1$ factors.

Assume there exist two partitions $T_1\sqcup T_2=S_1\sqcup S_2=\{1,\ldots,n\}$ such that for any $i\in \{1,2\}$ we have $P_i\prec ^s_{M} A\rtimes \Gamma _{T_i}$ and $\Delta (A\rtimes \Gamma _{S_i})\prec ^s_{M\bar \otimes L(\Lambda )} M\bar \otimes P_i$.

If $L(\Lambda )$ does not have property Gamma, then $T_i=S_i$, for any $i\in \{1,2\}$. Moreover, there exist subgroups $\Sigma _1,\Sigma _2<\Lambda$ such that for all $i\in \{1,2\}$ we have:

  1. (1) $B\rtimes \Sigma _i\prec ^s_M A\rtimes \Gamma _{T_i}$ and $A\rtimes \Gamma _{S_i}\prec ^s_M B\rtimes \Sigma _i$;

  2. (2) $P_i\prec ^s_{L(\Lambda )} L(\Sigma _i)$ and $L(\Sigma _i)\prec _{L(\Lambda )}^s P_i$.

Proof. (1) The assumption $\Delta (A\rtimes \Gamma _{S_1})\prec ^s_{M\bar \otimes L(\Lambda )} M\bar \otimes P_1$ implies from [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Theorem 4.1] (see also [Reference IoanaIoa12, Theorem 3.1] and [Reference Chifan, de Santiago and SinclairCdSS16, Theorem 3.3]) that there exists a decreasing sequence of subgroups $\Omega _k<\Lambda$, $k\ge 1$, such that $A\rtimes \Gamma _{S_1}\prec _M^s B\rtimes \Omega _k$, for any $k\ge 1$ and $P_2\prec _{L(\Lambda )} L(\cup _{k\ge 1}C_{\Lambda }(\Omega _k))$. Using Proposition 2.3, there is $k\ge 1$ such that $P_2\prec _{L(\Lambda )} L(\Omega _k)'\cap L(\Lambda )$ and using [Reference VaesVae08, Lemma 3.5] we further derive that $L(\Omega _k)\prec _{L(\Lambda )} P_1$. By letting $\Sigma _1=\Omega _k$, we get

(6.1)\begin{equation} A\rtimes\Gamma_{S_1}\prec_M^s B\rtimes\Sigma_1 \text{ and } L(\Sigma_1)\prec_{L(\Lambda)} P_1. \end{equation}

We continue by showing that $B\rtimes \Sigma _1\prec ^s_M A\rtimes \Gamma _{T_1}$. By applying [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Lemma 2.4], we get from (6.1) a non-zero projection $e\in L(\Sigma _1)'\cap L(\Lambda )$ such that $L(\Sigma _1)e\prec ^s_{L(\Lambda )} P_1$. Since $P_1\prec ^s_{M} A\rtimes \Gamma _{T_1}$, we obtain from [Reference VaesVae08, Lemma 3.7] that $L(\Sigma _1)e\prec ^s_M A\rtimes \Gamma _{T_1}$. By applying Lemma 2.2 there exists a projection $f\in (B\rtimes \Sigma _1)'\cap pMp\subset B$ with $f\ge e$ such that $(B\rtimes \Sigma _1)f\prec ^s_M A\rtimes \Gamma _{T_1}$. Since $f\in B$, $e\in L(\Lambda )$ and $f\ge e$, we deduce that $f=1$. Thus, $B\rtimes \Sigma _1\prec ^s_M A\rtimes \Gamma _{T_1}$. Similarly, there exists a subgroup $\Sigma _2<\Lambda$ satisfying conclusion (1).

(2) This follows verbatim the proofs of Claims 2 and 3 from [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Lemma 5.10].

6.1 Proof of Theorem A

Assume Notation 3.7. Fix an arbitrary $i\in \overline {1,m}$. By applying Theorem 4.2 there is a partition $S^i_1\sqcup S^i_2=\overline {1,n}$ such that $\Delta (A\rtimes \Gamma _{S_1^i})\prec _{M\bar \otimes L(\Lambda )} M\bar \otimes L(\Lambda _{\widehat i})$ and $\Delta (A\rtimes \Gamma _{S_2^i})\prec _{M\bar \otimes L(\Lambda )} M\bar \otimes L(\Lambda _{i})$. Standard arguments (see, for instance, the proof of [Reference IoanaIoa11, Lemma 9.2(1)]) imply that

(6.2)\begin{equation} A\rtimes\Gamma_{S_1^i}\prec_{M}^s B\rtimes\Lambda_{\widehat i} \quad\text{and}\quad A\rtimes\Gamma_{S_2^i}\prec_{M}^s B\rtimes\Lambda_{ i}. \end{equation}

Hence, Theorem 4.6 combined with [Reference Berbec and VaesBV14, Lemma 2.3] gives that there is a partition $T^i_1\sqcup T^i_2=\overline {1,n}$ such that

(6.3)\begin{equation} B\rtimes\Lambda_{\widehat i}\prec^s_{M} A\rtimes\Gamma_{T_1^i} \quad \text{and} \quad B\rtimes\Lambda_{ i}\prec^s_{M} A\rtimes\Gamma_{T_2^i}. \end{equation}

By applying [Reference VaesVae08, Lemma 3.7] we derive that $S_1^i=T_1^i$, $S_2^i=T_2^i$. Consequently, by using relations (6.2) and (6.3), [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Proposition 3.1] implies that $\Gamma _{T_1^i}$ and $\Lambda _{\widehat i}$ are measure equivalent and $\Gamma _{T_2 ^i}$ and $\Lambda _{i}$ are measure equivalent as well, for any $i\in \overline {1,m}$. The conclusion now follows by a simple induction argument.

6.2 Proof of Theorem B

We first obtain the following classification of tensor product decompositions in the spirit of [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Theorem C]. Theorem B will then follow by applying this result together with an induction argument.

Theorem 6.2 Let $\Gamma$ and $\Lambda$ be countable icc groups that are measure equivalent. Assume $L(\Lambda )=P_1\bar \otimes P_2$ and $\Gamma =\Gamma _1\times \cdots \times \Gamma _n$ is a product into icc groups such that $L(\Gamma _i)$ belongs to $\boldsymbol {\mathscr M}$ for any $i\in \{1,\ldots,n\}$.

Then there exist a direct product decomposition $\Lambda =\Lambda _1\times \Lambda _2$, a partition $T_1\sqcup T_2=\{1,\ldots,n\}$, a decomposition $L(\Lambda )=P_1^{t_1}\bar \otimes P_2^{t_2}$, for some $t_1,t_2>0$ with $t_1t_2=1$, and a unitary $u\in L(\Lambda )$ such that:

  1. (1) $P_1^{t_1}=uL(\Lambda _1)u^*$ and $P_2^{t_2}=uL(\Lambda _2)u^*$;

  2. (2) $\Lambda _1$ is measure equivalent to $\times _{j\in T_1}\Gamma _j$ and $\Lambda _2$ is measure equivalent to $\times _{j\in T_2}\Gamma _j$.

Proof. For the proof, we assume Notation 3.7. Using Proposition 3.8, we get that $L(\Gamma )$ does not have property Gamma. Next, by applying Theorems 4.2 and 4.6 and Lemma 6.1, we obtain a partition $T_1\sqcup T_2=\{1,\ldots,n\}$ and some subgroups $\Sigma _1,\Sigma _2<\Lambda$ such that for all $i\in \{1,2\}$ we have:

  1. (1) $B\rtimes \Sigma _i\prec ^s_M A\rtimes \Gamma _{T_i}$ and $A\rtimes \Gamma _{S_i}\prec ^s_M B\rtimes \Sigma _i$;

  2. (2) $P_i\prec ^s_{L(\Lambda )} L(\Sigma _i)$ and $L(\Sigma _i)\prec _{L(\Lambda )}^s P_i$.

Part (2) together with [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Theorem 6.1] give a product decomposition $\Lambda =\Lambda _1\times \Lambda _2$, a decomposition $L(\Lambda )=P_1^{t_1}\bar \otimes P_2^{t_2}$, for some $t_1,t_2>0$ with $t_1t_2=1$, and a unitary $u\in L(\Lambda )$ such that $P_1^{t_1}=uL(\Lambda _1)u^*$ and $P_2^{t_2}=uL(\Lambda _2)u^*$. In addition, we have that $\Lambda _i$ is measure equivalent to $\Sigma _i$, for any $i\in \{1,2\}$.

Part (1) together with [Reference Drimbe, Hoff and IoanaDHI16, Proposition 3.1] implies that for any $i\in \{1,2\}$, $\Gamma _{T_i}$ is measure equivalent to $\Sigma _i$ and, hence, to $\Lambda _i$.

6.3 Proof of Corollary C

Assume first that there exists a partition $J_1\sqcup J_2=\{1,\ldots,n\}$ for which $K={\rm Fix}_K(J_1)\times {\rm Fix}_K(J_2)$. By letting $G_1= (\times _{i\in J_1} \Gamma )\rtimes {\rm Fix}_K(J_2)$ and $G_2=(\times _{i\in J_2}\Gamma )\rtimes {\rm Fix}_K(J_1)$, it follows that $G= G_1 \times G_2$. This clearly shows that $L(G)$ is not prime.

For proving the other implication, assume that $L(G)=P_1\bar \otimes P_2$ can be written as a tensor product of diffuse factors. Using Theorem B and its proof, it follows that there exist a direct product decomposition $G=G_1\times G_2$ into infinite groups and a partition $J_1\sqcup J_2=\overline {1,n}$ such that $L(G_i)\prec _{L(G)} L(\Gamma _{J_i})$, for any $i\in \overline {1,2}.$ By [Reference Chifan and IoanaCI18, Lemma 2.2] we get a finite index subgroup $G_i^0< G_i$ such that $G_i^0< \Gamma _{J_i}$, for any $i\in \overline {1,2}$. By passing to relative commutants, we get that $\Gamma _{J_2}< G_2$ since $G_1$ is icc. By passing again to relative commutants, we deduce that $G_1< C_{G}(\Gamma _{J_2})=(\times _{i\in J_1} \Gamma )\rtimes {\rm Fix}_K(J_2)$. Similarly, we get $G_2<(\times _{i\in J_2} \Gamma )\rtimes {\rm Fix}_K(J_1)$. This proves $K={\rm Fix}_K(J_1)\times {\rm Fix}_K(J_2)$ which ends the proof.

7. Proof of Theorem D

7.1 OE rigidity for irreducible actions

An important ingredient for proving Theorem D is the following OE rigidity result for irreducible actions of product group that belong to ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}.$

Theorem 7.1 Let $\Gamma =\Gamma _1\times \cdots \times \Gamma _n$ be a product of $n\ge 2$ groups that belong to ${\rm {\boldsymbol {\mathscr {M}}}}$. Let $\Lambda =\Lambda _1\times \cdots \times \Lambda _m$ be a product of $m\ge 2$ infinite icc groups. Assume $\Gamma \curvearrowright (X,\mu )$ and $\Lambda \curvearrowright (Y,\nu )$ are OE free, irreducible, pmp actions.

If $m\ge n$, then $m=n$ and $\Gamma \curvearrowright (X,\mu )$ and $\Lambda \curvearrowright (Y,\nu )$ are conjugate.

Proof. Theorem A implies that $m\ge n$. For the remaining part of the proof, assume that $m=n$. By assumption, we have the identification $M:=L^\infty (X)\rtimes \Gamma =L^\infty (Y)\rtimes \Lambda$ with $A:=L^\infty (X)=L^\infty (Y)$. By proceeding as in the proof of Theorem A, it follows that for any $i$ there is a partition $S_1^i\sqcup S_2^i=\overline {1,n}$ such that $A\rtimes \Gamma _{S_1^i}\prec _{M}^s A\rtimes \Lambda _{\widehat i}$ and $A\rtimes \Lambda _{\widehat i} \prec _M^s A\rtimes \Gamma _{S_1^i}$. Hence, by using [Reference Ioana, Peterson and PopaIPP08, Lemma 8.4] there is $u_i\in \mathcal {U}(M)$ such that $u_i (A\rtimes \Lambda _{\widehat i}) u_i^*=A\rtimes \Gamma _{S_1^i}$. Theorem A implies that $S_1^i$ has $n-1$ elements. It is easy to see that there is a bijection $\varphi$ of the set $\overline {1,n}$ such that $S_1^i=\widehat {\varphi (i)}$ for any $i$. Thus, we can apply Proposition 5.1 and derive that the Zimmer cocycle associated to the orbit equivalence between $\Gamma \curvearrowright (X,\mu )$ and $\Lambda \curvearrowright (Y,\nu )$ is cohomologous to a group isomorphism. Hence, by applying [Reference VaesVae07, Lemma 4.7] we get that $\Gamma \curvearrowright (X,\mu )$ and $\Lambda \curvearrowright (Y,\nu )$ are conjugate.

7.2 Strongly cocycle rigidity

We start this subsection by recording the following particular case of [Reference Horbez, Huang and IoanaHHI21, Theorem 7.1] which is inspired by several works [Reference FurmanFur99, Reference Monod and ShalomMS06, Reference KidaKid08]. For properly formulating the result we introduce the following definition (see also [Reference Horbez, Huang and IoanaHHI21, § 7]). We say that a product group $\Gamma =\Gamma _1\times \cdots \times \Gamma _n$ is strongly cocycle rigid if given any two free, irreducible, pmp actions $\Gamma \curvearrowright (X,\mu )$ and $\Gamma \curvearrowright (Y,\nu )$ that are OE, the underlying Zimmer cocycle is cohomologous to a group isomorphism.

Theorem 7.2 [Reference Horbez, Huang and IoanaHHI21]

Let $\Gamma =\Gamma _1\times \cdots \times \Gamma _n$ be an icc strongly cocycle rigid group. Assume $\Gamma \curvearrowright (X,\mu )$ is a free, irreducible, pmp action that is OE to a free, mildly mixing, pmp action $\Lambda \curvearrowright (Y,\nu )$.

Then $\Gamma \curvearrowright (X,\mu )$ and $\Lambda \curvearrowright (Y,\nu )$ are virtually conjugate.

Corollary 7.3 If $\Gamma _1,\ldots,\Gamma _n$ are countable groups with $L(\Gamma _i)\in \boldsymbol {\mathscr M}$, for any $i\in \{1,\ldots,n\}$, then $\Gamma _1\times \cdots \times \Gamma _n$ is strongly cocycle rigid.

Proof. Denote $\Gamma =\Gamma _1\times \cdots \times \Gamma _n$ and let $\Gamma \curvearrowright (X,\mu )$ and $\Gamma \curvearrowright (Y,\nu )$ be free, irreducible, pmp actions that are OE. The proof of Theorem 7.1 gives, in particular, that the underlying Zimmer cocycle is cohomologous to a group isomorphism.

7.3 Proof of Theorem D

This is a direct consequence of Corollary 7.3 and Theorem 7.2.

8. Proofs of Theorem E and Corollary F

8.1 Proof of Theorem E

Let $\{u_g\}_{g\in \Gamma }$ be the canonical unitaries that generate $L(\Gamma )$. Denote $\mathcal {M}=M\bar \otimes L(\Gamma )$, $\tilde {\mathcal {M}}=\tilde M\bar \otimes L(\Gamma )$, and $\hat \alpha _t=\alpha _t\otimes {\rm id}\in {\rm Aut}(\tilde {\mathcal {M}})$. Note that the $*$-homomorphism $\Delta :L(\Gamma )\to L(\Gamma )\bar \otimes L(\Gamma )$ defined by $\Delta (u_g)=u_g\otimes u_g$, as $g\in \Gamma$ (see [Reference Popa and VaesPV10]), naturally extends to a map $\Delta :\ell ^2(\Gamma )\to \ell ^2(\Gamma )\otimes \ell ^2(\Gamma )$. By denoting $\hat \xi =\Delta (\xi )$, for any $\xi \in \ell ^2(\Gamma )$, it follows that if $\xi =\sum _{g\in \Gamma }\xi _g u_g\in \ell ^2(\Gamma )$ and $t\in \mathbb {R}$, then

(8.1)\begin{equation} \| \hat\alpha_t (\hat \xi)-\hat\xi \|_2^2=\sum_{g\in\Gamma}|\xi_g|^2 \| \alpha_t(u_g)-u_g \|_2^2. \end{equation}

Since $\Gamma$ is inner amenable, there exists a sequence $(\xi _n)_{n\ge 1}\subset \ell ^2(\Gamma )$ of unit vectors satisfying $\|u_g \xi _n -\xi _n u_g\|_2\to 0,$ for all $g\in \Gamma$ and $\xi _n(g)\to 0$, for any $g\in \Gamma$. Let $\omega$ be a free ultrafilter on $\mathbb {N}$. The remaining part of the proof is divided between two claims.

Claim 1 We claim that $\lim _{t\to 0} (\lim _{n\to \omega } \| \hat \alpha _t(\hat \xi _n) -\hat \xi _n \| )=0$.

Proof of Claim 1 We define the unitary representations $\pi :\Gamma \to \mathcal {U}(L^2(\tilde M)\ominus L^2(M))$ by $\pi _g(\xi )=u_g\xi u_g^*$, for all $g\in \Gamma, \xi \in L^2(\tilde M)\ominus L^2(M)$ and $d:\Gamma \to \mathcal {U}(\ell ^2(\Gamma ))$ by $d_g(x)=u_g xu_g^*$, for all $g\in \Gamma, x\in \ell ^2(\Gamma )$. Since $L^2(\tilde M)\ominus L^2(M)$ is weakly contained in the coarse bimodule $L^2(M)\otimes L^2(M)$ as $M$-bimodules, we derive that $L^2(\tilde M)\ominus L^2(M)$ is weakly contained in the coarse bimodule $L^2(L(\Gamma ))\otimes L^2(L(\Gamma ))$ as $L(\Gamma )$-bimodules. Therefore, $\pi$ is weakly contained in the left regular representation $\lambda _{\Gamma }$. Consequently, by applying [Reference Bekka, de la Harpe and ValetteBdlHV08, Corollary E.2.6] we derive that $\pi \otimes d$ is weakly contained in $\lambda _{\Gamma }$. Note that $\hat \pi :=\pi \otimes d :\Gamma \to \mathcal {U}(L^2(\tilde {\mathcal {M}})\ominus L^2(\mathcal {M}))$ is defined by $\hat \pi _g(\eta )=\hat {u}_g\eta \hat {u}_g^*$ for all $g\in \Gamma,\eta \in L^2(\tilde {\mathcal {M}})\ominus L^2(\mathcal {M})$. Since $\Gamma$ is non-amenable, it follows that the trivial representation $1_{\Gamma }$ is not weakly contained in $\hat \pi$. This implies that for any $\epsilon >0$, there exist $\delta >0$ and a finite set $F\subset \Gamma$ satisfying that for any unit vector $\eta \in L^2(\tilde {\mathcal {M}})$ for which $\|\hat \pi _g(\eta )-\eta \|_2\leq \delta$, as $g\in F$, we have

(8.2)\begin{equation} \| \eta - E_{\mathcal{M}}(\eta) \|_2\leq\epsilon. \end{equation}

Since $\tau (\hat \alpha _t(\hat u_g)\hat u_h^*)=\tau (\alpha _t( u_g) u_h^*) \delta _{g,h}$, we obtain that $E_{\Delta (L(\Gamma ))}(\hat \alpha _t(\hat u_g))=\tau (\alpha _t(u_g)u_g^*)\hat u_g$, for any $g\in \Gamma$. This implies that for all $g\in \Gamma$ and $\xi \in \ell ^2(\Gamma )$, we have

(8.3)\begin{equation} \| \hat\alpha_t(\hat u_g) \hat\xi -\hat u_g\hat \xi \|_2=\| \alpha_t( u_g) - u_g \|_2 \|\xi\|_2\quad \text{and}\quad \|\hat\xi \hat\alpha_t(\hat u_g) - \hat\xi\hat u_g \|_2=\| \alpha_t(u_g) -u_g \|_2 \|\xi\|_2. \end{equation}

Let $t_0>0$ such that $\| \alpha _t(u_g)-u_g \|_2\leq \delta /4$, for all $|t|< t_0$ and $g\in F$. Take also $n_0\in \mathbb {N}$ such that $\| u_g\xi _n -\xi _n u_g \|_2\leq \delta /2$, for all $g\in F$ and $n\ge n_0$. Together with (8.3) we obtain

(8.4)\begin{equation} \begin{aligned} \| \hat\alpha_t(\hat u_g) \hat\xi_n - \hat \xi_n \hat\alpha_t(\hat u_g) \|_2 & \leq \| \hat\alpha_t(\hat u_g) \hat\xi_n -\hat u_g\hat \xi_n \|_2 + \| u_g\xi_n -\xi_n u_g \|_2 +\|\hat\xi_n\hat u_g- \hat\xi_n \hat\alpha_t(\hat u_g) \|_2\\ & \leq \delta/2 +\delta/4+\delta/2=\delta, \end{aligned} \end{equation}

for all $g\in F, n\ge n_0$ and $|t|\leq t_0$. By applying $\hat \alpha _{-t}$ in (8.4) and by replacing $t$ by $-t$, we get that $\| \hat \alpha _t(\hat \xi _n) \hat u_g - \hat u_g \hat \alpha _t(\hat \xi _n) \|_2\leq \delta$, for all $g\in F, n\ge n_0$ and $|t|\leq t_0$. Using (8.2), we get $\| \hat \alpha _t(\hat \xi _n) - E_{\mathcal {M}}(\hat \alpha _t(\hat \xi _n)) \|_2\leq \epsilon$, and by using Popa's transversality property, see [Reference PopaPop08, Lemma 2.1], we further derive that $\| \hat \alpha _{2t}(\hat \xi _n))-\hat \xi _n \|_2\leq 2\epsilon$, for all $n\ge n_0$ and $|t|\leq t_0$. This ends the proof of the claim.

For all $t\in \mathbb {R}$ and $r>0$, we denote $B_r^t=\{ g\in \Gamma \mid \|\alpha _t(u_g)-u_g \|_2\leq r \}$. We are now ready to prove the following claim.

Claim 2 We claim that $\lim _{t\to 0}(\sup _{g\in \Gamma } \|\alpha _t(u_g)-u_g \|_2)=0$.

Proof of Claim 2 To this end, fix some arbitrary $\epsilon >0$. Let $t_1>0$ and $n_1\in \mathbb {N}$ such that $\| \hat \alpha _t(\hat \xi _n) -\hat \xi _n \|_2\leq \epsilon /4$, for all $|t|\leq t_1$ and $n\ge n_1$. Fix $g\in \Gamma$ and $|t|\leq t_1$. We continue by showing that there exists an unbounded sequence $(k_n)_n \subset \Gamma$ such that $k_n, g k_n g^{-1}\in B_{{\epsilon }/{2}}^t$, for any $n\ge 1$. Since $\|\hat u_g \hat \xi _n -\hat \xi _n \hat u_g\|_2\to 0$, we get that there exists $n_2\in \mathbb {N}$ such that

\[ \| \hat\alpha_t(\hat \xi_n) -\hat\xi_n \|_2^2 + \| \hat\alpha_t(\hat u_g \hat \xi_n \hat u_g^*) - \hat u_g \hat\xi_n \hat u_g^* \|_2^2 \leq \epsilon^2/4, \text{ for any } n\ge n_2. \]

By writing $\xi _n=\sum _{g\in \Gamma } \xi _{n,g} u_g\in \ell ^2(\Gamma )$ and using (8.1) we obtain that

\[ \sum_{h\in\Gamma} |\xi_{n,h}|^2 ( \|\alpha_t(u_h)-u_h \|_2^2 + \|\alpha_t(u_{ghg^{-1}})-u_{ghg^{-1}} \|_2^2 )\leq \epsilon^2/4, \text{ for any } n\ge n_2. \]

For any $n\ge n_2$, since $\sum _{h\in \Gamma } |\xi _{n,h}|^2=1$, there exists $k_n\in \Gamma$ with $\xi _{n,k_n}\neq 0$ such that $\|\alpha _t(u_{k_n})-u_{k_n} \|_2\leq \epsilon /2$ and $\|\alpha _t(u_{gk_ng^{-1}})-u_{gk_ng^{-1}} \|_2 \leq \epsilon /2$. Since $\xi _{n,h}\to 0$, for any $h\in \Gamma$, it follows that $k_n$ can be chosen such that $k_n\to \infty$.

Next, we note that for any $n\ge n_2$, we have

(8.5)\begin{equation} \| \alpha_t (u_{gk_ng^{-1}})u_g - u_g \alpha_t(u_{k_n}) \|_2\leq \|\alpha_t(u_{k_n})-u_{k_n} \|_2 + \|\alpha_t(u_{gk_ng^{-1}}) - u_{gk_n g^{-1}} \|_2\leq \epsilon. \end{equation}

By letting $e:L^2 (\tilde M)\to L^2(M)$ be the orthogonal projection, we have $v_{g,t}:=\alpha _t(u_g)-e(\alpha _t(u_g))\in L^2(\tilde M)\ominus L^2(M)$. By applying $\alpha _{-t}$ to (8.5) and by projecting onto $L^2(\tilde M)\ominus L^2(M)$, we get

(8.6)\begin{equation} \| u_{gk_n g^{-1}} v_{-t,g} -v_{-t,g} u_{k_n} \|_2\leq \epsilon, \text{ for all } n\ge n_2. \end{equation}

Since the $M$-bimodule $L(\tilde M)\ominus L^2(M)$ is mixing and $k_n\to \infty$, we obtain that

(8.7)\begin{equation} \lim_{n\to\infty}\langle v_{-t,g}u_{k_n},u_{gk_ng^{-1}} v_{-t,g} \rangle=0. \end{equation}

By combining (8.6) and (8.7), it follows that $\|v_{-t,g}\|_2\leq \epsilon /\sqrt {2}$. By using once again Popa's transversality property, see [Reference PopaPop08, Lemma 2.1], we obtain $\| \alpha _{-t}(u_g)-u_g \|\leq \epsilon \sqrt {2}$. Since $t$ was arbitrary chosen such that $|t|\leq t_1$ and $g\in \Gamma$ arbitrary, we get that $\lim _{t\to 0}(\sup _{g\in \Gamma } \|\alpha _t(u_g)-u_g \|_2)=0$.

Standard arguments now imply the conclusion.

8.2 Proof of Corollary F

The proof follows directly from Theorem E.

8.3 Consequence to Kurosh-type rigidity results

We conclude our paper with the following rigidity result for tracial free product factors arising from non-amenable inner amenable groups.

Corollary 8.1 Let $M=L(\Gamma _1)*\cdots *L(\Gamma _m)=L(\Lambda _1)*\cdots *L(\Lambda _n)$, where all the groups $\Gamma _i$ and $\Lambda _j$ are non-amenable inner amenable icc groups.

Then $m=n$, and after a permutation of indices, $L(\Gamma _i)$ is unitarily conjugate to $L(\Lambda _i)$, for any $i\in \overline {1,n}.$

Proof. Fix an arbitrary $i\in \overline {1,m}$. By decomposing $M=L(\Gamma _1*\cdots *\Gamma _{n-1})*L(\Gamma _n)$, we note that $M$ belongs to $\boldsymbol {\mathscr M}$ and let $(\tilde M, (\alpha _t)_{t\in \mathbb {R}})$ be the associated s-malleable deformation of $M$. Since $\Gamma _i$ is non-amenable inner amenable group, Theorem E implies that $L(\Gamma _i)$ is $\alpha$-rigid. By applying the main technical result of [Reference Ioana, Peterson and PopaIPP08] (see also [Reference IoanaIoa15, Theorem 2.11]), we get that $L(\Gamma _i)\prec _M L(\Gamma _1*\cdots *\Gamma _{n-1})$ or $L(\Gamma _i)\prec _M L(\Gamma _n)$. By assuming the latter holds, there exist projections $p\in L(\Gamma _i), q\in L(\Gamma _n)$, a non-zero partial isometry $v\in qMp$ and a $*$-homomorphism $\theta : pL(\Gamma _i)p\to qL(\Gamma _n)q$ satisfying $\theta (x)v=vx$, for all $x\in pL(\Gamma _i)p$. Note that [Reference Ioana, Peterson and PopaIPP08, Theorem 1.2.1] gives that $vv^*\in L(\Gamma _n)$ and, hence, $v L(\Gamma _i)v^*\subset L(\Gamma _n)$. Note that since $L(\Gamma _i)'\cap M=\mathbb {C} 1$ and $v^*v\in p(L(\Gamma _i)'\cap M) p$, we get that $v^*v=p$. By letting $u$ be a unitary that extends $v$, we derive that $u p L(\Gamma _i) pu^*\subset L(\Gamma _n)$. Since $L(\Gamma _n)$ is a factor, after passing to a new unitary $u$, one can replace $p$ by its central support in $L(\Gamma _i)$; therefore, we obtain that $u L(\Gamma _i)u^*\subset L(\Gamma _n)$. Similarly, if $L(\Gamma _i)\prec _M L(\Gamma _1*\cdots *\Gamma _{n-1})$ holds, we obtain a unitary $u\in M$ such that $u L(\Gamma _i)u^*\subset L(\Gamma _1*\cdots *\Gamma _{n-1})$. By repeating this argument finitely many times, we conclude that there exists a map $\sigma : \overline {1,m}\to \overline {1,n}$ such that for any $i\in \overline {1,m}$, there is a unitary $u_i\in M$ satisfying $u_i L(\Gamma _i) u_i^* \subset L(\Lambda _{\sigma (i)})$.

In a similar way, we obtain a map $\tau : \overline {1,n}\to \overline {1,m}$ and a unitary $w_j\in M$, for any $j\in \overline {1,n}$, such that $w_jL(\Lambda _j) w_j^* \subset L(\Gamma _{\tau (j)})$, for any $j\in \overline {1,n}$. Thus, $u_{\tau (j)}w_j L(\Lambda _j) w_j^* u_{\tau (j)}^*\subset L(\Lambda _{\sigma (\tau (j))})$, for any $j\in \overline {1,n}$. By applying [Reference Ioana, Peterson and PopaIPP08, Theorem 1.2.1] we deduce that $\sigma \circ \tau ={\rm Id}$ and $u_{\tau (j)}w_j\in L(\Lambda _j)$, for any $j\in \overline {1,n}$. Similarly, we get $\tau \circ \sigma ={\rm Id}$ and $w_{\sigma (i)}u_i\in L(\Gamma _i)$ for any $i\in \overline {1,m}$. In particular, $m=n$ and $u_i L(\Gamma _i) u_i^* = L(\Lambda _{\sigma (i)})$, for any $i\in \overline {1,n}$.

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Adrian Ioana for sharing with me his original proof of [Reference Tucker-DrobTuc14, Theorem 11] which led to Theorem E. I would like to thank Adrian Ioana and Stefaan Vaes for numerous comments and suggestions that helped improve the exposition of the paper. I would also like to thank Srivatsav Kunnawalkam Elayavalli and Changying Ding for helpful comments. Finally, I am grateful to the referee for many comments that helped improve the exposition.

Conflicts of Interest

None.

Footnotes

The author holds the postdoctoral fellowship fundamental research 12T5221N of the Research Foundation Flanders.

1 A subgroup $H< G$ is called almost malnormal if $gHg^{-1}\cap H$ is finite for any $g\in G\setminus$H.

2 Two pmp actions $\Gamma \curvearrowright (X,\mu )$ and $\Lambda \curvearrowright (Y,\nu )$ are virtually conjugate if there exist some finite normal subgroups $A<\Gamma$ and $B<\Lambda$ such that the associated actions $\Gamma /A\curvearrowright X/A$ and $\Lambda /B\curvearrowright Y/B$ are induced from conjugate actions.

References

Anantharaman, C. and Popa, S., An introduction to II $_1$ factors, book in preparation, available on Sorin Popa's website: https://www.math.ucla.edu/~popa/Books/IIunV15.pdf.Google Scholar
Bannon, J., Marrakchi, A., Ozawa, N., Full factors and co-amenable inclusions, Comm. Math. Phys. 378 (2020), 11071121.10.1007/s00220-020-03816-yCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bekka, B., de la Harpe, P. and Valette, A., Kazhdan's property (T), New Mathematical Monographs, vol. 11 (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2008).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berbec, M. and Vaes, S., W$^*$-superrigidity for group von Neumann algebras of left–right wreath products, Proc. Lond. Math. Soc. (3) 108 (2014), 11161152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boutonnet, R., Ioana, A. and Peterson, J., Properly proximal groups and their von Neumann algebras, Ann. Sci. Éc. Norm. Supér. (4) 54 (2021), 445482.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, N. and Ozawa, N., C*-algebras and finite-dimensional approximations, Grad. Stud. Math., vol. 88 (American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 2008).Google Scholar
Chifan, I. and Das, S., Primeness results for II $_1$ factors associated with fibered product groups, Preprint (2019).Google Scholar
Chifan, I., de Santiago, R. and Sinclair, T., W$^*$-rigidity for the von Neumann algebras of products of hyperbolic groups, Geom. Funct. Anal. 26 (2016), 136159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chifan, I., de Santiago, R. and Sucpikarnon, W., Tensor product decompositions of II$_1$ factors arising from extensions of amalgamated free product groups, Commun. Math. Phys. 364 (2018), 11631194.10.1007/s00220-018-3175-zCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chifan, I., Diaz-Arias, A. and Drimbe, D., $W^*$ and $C^*$-superrigidity results for coinduced groups, Preprint (2021), arXiv:2107.05976.Google Scholar
Chifan, I., Drimbe, D. and Ioana, A., Tensor product indecomposability results for existentially closed factors, Preprint (2022), arXiv:2208.00259.Google Scholar
Chifan, I. and Ioana, A., Ergodic subequivalence relations induced by a Bernoulli action, Geom. Funct. Anal. 20 (2010), 5367.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chifan, I. and Ioana, A., Amalgamated free product rigidity for group von Neumann algebras, Adv. Math. 329 (2018), 819850.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chifan, I., Popa, S. and Sizemore, O., OE and W$^*$-rigidity results for actions by wreath product groups, J. Funct. Anal. 263 (2012), 34223448.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chifan, I. and Sinclair, T., On the structural theory of II$_1$ factors of negatively curved groups, Ann. Sci. Éc. Norm. Supér. (4) 46 (2013), 133.10.24033/asens.2183CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Connes, A., Classification of injective factors, Ann. Math. 104 (1976), 73115.10.2307/1971057CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Connes, A., Feldman, J. and Weiss, B., An amenable equivalence relations is generated by a single transformation, Ergodic Theory Dynam. Systems 1 (1981), 431450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Santiago, R., Hayes, B., Hoff, D. and Sinclair, T., Maximal rigid subalgebras of deformations and L$^2$-cohomology, Anal. PDE, to appear. Preprint (2020).Google Scholar
Ding, C., Kunnawalkam Elayavalli, S. and Peterson, J., Properly Proximal von Neumann Algebras, Preprint (2022), arXiv:2204.00517.Google Scholar
Drimbe, D., Prime II$_1$ factors arising from actions of product groups, J. Funct. Anal. 278 (2020), 108366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Drimbe, D., Orbit equivalence rigidity for product actions, Comm. Math. Phys. 379 (2020), 4159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Drimbe, D., Product rigidity in von Neumann and C$^*$-algebras via s-malleable deformations, Comm. Math. Phys. 388 (2021), 329349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Drimbe, D., Hoff, D. and Ioana, A., Prime II$_1$ factors arising from irreducible lattices in product of rank one simple Lie groups, J. Reine Angew. Math., to appear. Preprint (2016), arXiv:1611.02209.Google Scholar
Drimbe, D., Ioana, A. and Peterson, J., Cocycle superrigidity for profinite actions of irreducible lattices, Groups Geom. Dyn., to appear. Preprint (2019).Google Scholar
Dye, H., On groups of measure preserving transformation. I, Amer. J. Math. 81 (1959), 119159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Effros, E. G., Property $\Gamma$ and inner amenability, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 47 (1975), 483486.Google Scholar
Furman, A., Orbit equivalence rigidity, Ann. of Math. (2) 150 (1999), 10831108.10.2307/121063CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Furman, A., A survey of measured group theory, in Geometry, Rigidity, and Group Actions (The University of Chicago Press, Chicago and London, 2011), 296374.Google Scholar
Gaboriau, D., Co$\hat u$t des relations d’équivalence et de groupes, Invent. Math. 139 (2000), 4198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaboriau, D., Invariants $\ell ^2$ de relations d'equivalence et de groupes, Publ. Math. Inst. Hautes Études Sci. 95 (2002), 93150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaboriau, D., Orbit equivalence and measured group theory, in Proceedings of the ICM (Hyderabad, India, 2010), vol. III (Hindustan Book Agency, 2010), 15011527.Google Scholar
Ge, L., Applications of free entropy to finite von Neumann algebras. II, Ann. of Math. (2) 147 (1998), 143157.10.2307/120985CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gromov, M., Asymptotic invariants of infinite groups, in Geometric group theory, Vol. 2, London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series, vol. 182 (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1993), 1295.Google Scholar
Horbez, C. and Huang, J., Measure equivalence rigidity among the Higman groups, Preprint (2022), arXiv:2206.00884.Google Scholar
Horbez, C., Huang, J. and Ioana, A., Orbit equivalence rigidity of irreducible actions of right-angled Artin groups, Compos. Math., to appear. Preprint (2021), arXiv:2110.04141.Google Scholar
Houdayer, C. and Ueda, Y., Rigidity of free product von Neumann algebras, Compos. Math. 152 (2016), 24612492.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ioana, A., Rigidity results for wreath product of II$_1$ factors, J. Funct. Anal. 252 (2007), 763791.10.1016/j.jfa.2007.04.005CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ioana, A., W$^*$ -superrigidity for Bernoulli actions of property (T) groups, J. Amer. Math. Soc. 24 (2011), 11751226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ioana, A., Uniqueness of the group measure space decomposition for Popa's $\mathcal {H}\mathcal {T}$ factors, Geom. Funct. Anal. 22 (2012), 699732.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ioana, A., Classification and rigidity for von Neumann algebras, in European Congress of Mathematics, Kraków, 2–7 July, 2012 (EMS Press, 2014), 601625.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ioana, A., Cartan subalgebras of amalgamated free product II$_1$ factors. With an appendix by Adrian Ioana and Stefaan Vaes, Ann. Sci. Éc. Norm. Supér. (4) 48 (2015), 71130.10.24033/asens.2239CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ioana, A., Rigidity for von Neumann algebras, in Proceedings of the International Congress of Mathematicians—Rio de Janeiro 2018, Invited lectures, vol. III (World Scientific, Hackensack, NJ, 2018), 16391672.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ioana, A., Peterson, J. and Popa, S., Amalgamated free products of weakly rigid factors and calculation of their symmetry groups, Acta Math. 200 (2008), 85153.10.1007/s11511-008-0024-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ioana, A., Popa, S. and Vaes, S., A class of superrigid group von Neumann algebras, Ann. of Math. (2) 178 (2013), 231286.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ioana, A. and Spaas, P., A class of II$_1$ factors with a unique McDuff decomposition, Math. Ann. 375 (2019), 177212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ishan, I., Peterson, J. and Ruth, L., Von Neumann equivalence and properly proximal groups, Preprint (2019), arXiv:1910.08682.Google Scholar
Isono, Y. and Marrakchi, A., Tensor product decompositions and rigidity of full factors, Ann. Sci. Éc. Norm. Supér. (4), to appear. Preprint (2019).Google Scholar
Kida, Y., Orbit equivalence rigidity for ergodic actions of the mapping class group, Geom. Dedicata 131 (2008), 99109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kida, Y., Measure equivalence rigidity of the mapping class group, Ann. of Math. (2) 171 (2010), 18511901.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krogager, A. and Vaes, S., A class of II$_1$ factors with exactly two crossed product decompositions, Math. Pures Appl., to appear. Preprint (2015), arXiv:1512.06677J.Google Scholar
Monod, N. and Shalom, Y., Orbit equivalence rigidity and bounded cohomology, Ann. of Math. 164 (2006), 825878.10.4007/annals.2006.164.825CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murray, F. J. and von Neumann, J., Rings of operators. IV, Ann. Math. 44 (1943), 716808.10.2307/1969107CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ornstein, D. and Weiss, B., Ergodic theory of amenable group actions. I. The Rohlin lemma, Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. (N.S.) 2 (1980), 161164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ozawa, N., Solid von Neumann algebras, Acta Math. 192 (2004), 111117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ozawa, N., A Kurosh-type theorem for type II$_1$ factors, Int. Math. Res. Not. IMRN 2006 (2006), 097560.Google Scholar
Ozawa, N. and Popa, S., On a class of II$_1$ factors with at most one Cartan subalgebra, Ann. of Math. (2) 172 (2010), 713749.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, J., L$^2$-rigidity in von Neumann algebras, Invent. Math. 175 (2009), 417433.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, J. and Thom, A., Group cocycles and the ring of affiliated operators, Invent. Math. 185 (2011), 561592; MR 2827095 (2012j:22004).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popa, S., Orthogonal pairs of $*$-subalgebras in finite von Neumann algebras, J. Operator Theory 9 (1983), 253268.Google Scholar
Popa, S., On a class of type II$_1$ factors with Betti numbers invariants, Ann. of Math. 163 (2006), 809899.10.4007/annals.2006.163.809CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popa, S., Strong rigidity of II$_1$ factors arising from malleable actions of w-rigid groups. I, Invent. Math. 165 (2006), 369408.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popa, S., Strong rigidity of II$_11$ factors arising from malleable actions of w-rigid groups. II, Invent. Math. 165 (2006), 409452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popa, S., Deformation and rigidity for group actions and von Neumann algebras, in Proceedings of the ICM (Madrid, 2006), vol. I (European Mathematical Society Publishining House, 2007), 445477.10.4171/022-1/18CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popa, S., On Ozawa's property for free group factors, Int. Math. Res. Not. IMRN 2007 (2007), Art. ID rnm036.Google Scholar
Popa, S., On the superrigidity of malleable actions with spectral gap, J. Amer. Math. Soc. 21 (2008), 9811000.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popa, S., UCLA lecture notes, Functional analysis seminar, January 8, 2021.Google Scholar
Popa, S. and Vaes, S., Group measure space decomposition of II$_1$ factors and W$^*$-superrigidity, Invent. Math. 182 (2010), 371417.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popa, S. and Vaes, S., Unique Cartan decomposition for II$_1$ factors arising from arbitrary actions of free groups, Acta Math. 212 (2014), 141198.10.1007/s11511-014-0110-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sako, H., Measure equivalence rigidity and bi-exactness of groups, J. Funct. Anal. 257 (2009), 31673202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shalom, Y., Measurable group theory, in European Congress of Mathematics (European Mathematical Society Publishing House, 2005), 391423.Google Scholar
Sizemore, O. and Winchester, A., Unique prime decomposition results for factors coming from wreath product groups, Pacific J. Math. 265 (2013), 221232.10.2140/pjm.2013.265.221CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tucker-Drob, R. D., Invariant means and the structure of inner amenable groups, Duke Math. J. 169 (2014), 25712628.Google Scholar
Vaes, S., Rigidity results for Bernoulli actions and their von Neumann algebras (after Sorin Popa), Séminaire Bourbaki, exposé 961, Astérisque 311 (2007), 237294.Google Scholar
Vaes, S., Explicit computations of all finite index bimodules for a family of II$_1$ factors, Ann. Sci. Éc. Norm. Supér. (4) 41 (2008), 743788.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vaes, S., Rigidity for von Neumann algebras and their invariants, in Proceedings of the ICM (Hyderabad, India, 2010), vol. III (Hindustan Book Agency, 2010), 16241650.Google Scholar
Vaes, S., An inner amenable group whose von Neumann algebra does not have property Gamma, Acta Math. 208 (2012), 389394.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vaes, S., One-cohomology and the uniqueness of the group measure space decomposition of a II$_1$ factor, Math. Ann. 355 (2013), 661696.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zimmer, R., Ergodic theory and semisimple groups, Monographs in Mathematics, vol. 81 (Basel, Birkḧauser, 1984).CrossRefGoogle Scholar