Introduction
This article examines how the early works of Alexei Losev (1893–1988), a religious philosopher of the Russian Silver Age, dealt with the concepts of hesychasm, Palamism, and Name-Glorification (Imiaslavie, Onomatodoxy) in the framework of the so-called Neo-Patristic movement. Before I turn to the main subject of this study, a few preliminary remarks are in order. Palamism is a theological system, formulated in fourteenth-century Byzantium by Gregory Palamas, arguing for the distinction in God between the unknowable and imparticipable essence on the one hand and the knowable and participable uncreated energies of this essence on the other. According to Palamas, the Taborian light, revealed to the apostles during the transfiguration of Christ (Matt 17:2), is such an uncreated energy. The representatives of the circle of the Russian Name-Glorifiers at the beginning of the twentieth century maintained that, when Christians think about God and name him, as in prayer, they participate in God himself, in his energies, and therefore God’s names, which human beings think of and utter, are themselves divine energies (in the Palamite sense), which means they are God himself.Footnote 1
The theme of the Palamite controversy and the teaching of Gregory Palamas played an important role in Alexei Losev’s oeuvre, as seen in the latter’s earliest-preserved text dealing with the problems of the Name-Glorifiers controversy, an essay entitled “Die Onomathodoxie (russisch Imiaslavie)” (“Onomatodoxy”), written in 1921–1922.Footnote 2 The text is preserved in Losev’s archive in German. The original, unpreserved Russian text was probably translated into German by Maria Grabar-Passek.Footnote 3 Contemporary editions of Losev’s works contain this article in the reverse translation from German to Russian, performed by Andrei Vashestov and edited by Liudmila Gogotishvili and Aza Takho-Godi.Footnote 4 As we shall see, Losev’s program of comprehending Name-Glorification in relation to Palamism and Platonism, in general, corresponds to Pavel Florensky’s program, expressed in the essay “Onomatodoxy as a Philosophical Premise.” At the same time, Losev’s “Onomatodoxy” has stipulations which differ from those of Florensky’s program.
Losev’s “Onomatodoxy”: Name-Glorification, Hesychasm, and Palamism
Losev’s “Onomatodoxy” consists of two parts: “The history of the question” and “Dogmatic teaching.” At the very start of his article, Losev defines Name-Glorification as “one of the ancient and characteristic mystical movements of the orthodox East, expressed in a special veneration of God’s name, interpreting God’s name as a necessary dogmatic condition of a religious teaching, and as a cult and mystical consciousness in Orthodoxy.” Footnote 5 Next, Losev embarks on a short historical outline of the Name-Glorifying tradition. He points out the corresponding parts of the Bible and turns to the patristic tradition, arguing that the gist of Name-Glorification is in the teaching of the Eastern monkhood on the Jesus Prayer which, in its final form, is revealed by the hesychasts, whose leader was Gregory Palamas.Footnote 6 Then, Losev briefly relates the contents of the Palamite debates to the Taborian light. According to him, the anti-Palamites, Barlaam of Calabria and Gregory Akindynos, taught that the Taborian light, seen by the apostles during the transfiguration of Christ and then by the monks and zealots during the Jesus Prayer, is simply the created light but not God as such. However, Palamas and his followers insisted that God himself, in his energies, appears before people. Here, Losev observes the clash between the two basic directions of human thought, namely the subjectivist psychologism (corresponding to the position of the anti-Palamites) and the objectivist position that insists on the existence of eternal forms present before things and in things.Footnote 7
It is for this reason, Losev notes, that the Synod of 1351 excommunicated Barlaam and Akindynos, declaring that the Taborian light is neither God’s creation nor the divine essence; that the divine essence is incomprehensible and inaccessible while its energies are comprehensible and participated in by humankind; and that the Taborian light is the intelligible light of the divine essence, the energy of the divine essence, inseparable from it and, therefore, is God himself.Footnote 8 Next, Losev focuses on the description of the hesychast way of prayer, after which he correlates the problematics of Name-Glorification with the eighth-century Byzantine polemics on icons. Losev likens iconoclasm, which corresponds, he argues, to the position of the Name-Glorifiers’ opponents,Footnote 9 with Kantianism, with its abyss dividing things-in-themselves and phenomena.Footnote 10 Then, he compares the position of the iconophiles and the corresponding doctrine of Name-Glorifiers with the Platonic teaching that a phenomenon is the revelation of an essence unknowable in itself and given only in symbols understood as transcendent forms.Footnote 11 According to Losev, after the waning of the medieval worldview, the ancient teachings on the differences between the essences and the energies in God had disappeared into the shadows and were revived, in modified form, only at the beginning of the twentieth century in the theology of Name-Glorifiers.Footnote 12
Next, Losev briefly elaborates on the history of the Name-Glorifying controversy, providing an outline of the basic provisions of the Name-Glorifiers’ teaching. Losev sees a direct analogy with the iconoclast and Palamite controversies in the polemic on Name-Glorification. Within this polemic, the teaching of Name-Glorifiers—who insisted that God’s names contain divine energies inseparable from God and, therefore, these names are God himself—corresponds to the Palamite doctrine, while the position of their opponents corresponds to the anti-Palamite one.Footnote 13
Sources of Losev’s “Onomatodoxy”
A. Pavel Florensky and the “Synodikon of Orthodoxy”
Overall, these stipulations in “Onomatodoxy” are in line with the reception of Palamism by the Russian thinkers who were proponents of Name-Glorification and especially with Florensky’s teaching in his “Onomatodoxy as a Philosophical Premise.” Indeed, Losev qualified Palamism (and the Name-Glorification identified with it) as Platonism, exactly as the preceding pro-imiaslavie philosophers and theologians, such as Mitrofan Muretov, Pavel Florensky, and Vladimir Ern, did. Losev connects anti-Palamism and BarlaamismFootnote 14 with subjective psychologism, which is close to nominalism. This is consistent with Florensky’s rhetoric, which also linked the anti-Palamites and the anti-Name-Glorifiers with Barlaamism and subjectivism.Footnote 15
Considering the nature of Losev’s account of the Palamite doctrine and his references to the anathemas against Barlaam and Akindynos in the conciliar decision of 1351, quoted in the “Synodikon for the Sunday of Orthodoxy,” I believe that Losev’s knowledge of Palamism in his “Onomatodoxy” came from the “Synodikon.” Apparently, it was also the only primary source on the Palamite doctrine that the earlier adherents of Name-Glorification had at their disposal.Footnote 16 Furthermore, the anathemas against Barlaam and Akindynos, which Losev refers to in his “Onomatodoxy,” bear resemblance to those from the “Synodikon” used by Florensky in his “Onomatodoxy.”Footnote 17 Obviously, Losev relied on Florensky’s elaboration, turning to the “Synodikon,” when he gave his own account of the Palamite doctrine.
B. Losev’s “Formula of Hesychasm” and Its Sources
In his “Onomatodoxy,” Losev also touches upon the ascetic dimension of Palamism, identifying it with hesychasm.Footnote 18 Losev describes the hesychasts, whose views Gregory Palamas represented, in the following way: “[A]ll of [their] thoughts are concentrated on one highest point and there is nothing left in the soul of a person who prays, except for the light of the divine essence.”Footnote 19 What were Losev’s sources for this “formula of hesychasm”?
As far as I can see, Losev relied on at least two sources. Textual analysis demonstrates that, in terms of the expressed metaphysics of light and the assumption that there is nothing in the mind of a hesychast except for the divine light, Losev could have used the following excerpt from “The Practical and Theological Chapters” by Symeon the New Theologian, published in the fifth volume of the Philokalia, in the Russian translation by Theophan the Recluse: “[O]ur mind, being simple when it is freed from all outward thinking and immersed in the simple light of God, embraced and enveloped by this light, cannot countenance anything other than the light it is in” (ch. 147).Footnote 20 However, this excerpt talks about the divine light, which leaves nothing except for itself in the mind it pierces, but not about “the light of the divine essence” (which is understood as divine energy), as Losev did. In other words, Losev’s formula of hesychasm should have one more source apart from Symeon’s fragment. This source is the “Synodikon,” which Losev turns to in his article a bit later after he uses the formula of hesychasm. To be precise, Losev draws on the anathemas against Barlaam and Akindynos from the “Synodikon,” specifically three provisions summarizing the meaning of the first three anathemas out of the six. One of these provisions, corresponding to the first anathema, states: “The Taborian light, the intelligible light of the divine essence, is the energy of the essence, inseparable from his essence and, therefore, is God himself.”Footnote 21 Thus, the source of the expression “the light of the divine essence” from Losev’s formula of hesychasm is found in the “Synodikon,” in the fragment that Losev himself used in his essay.
Losev’s “Onomatodoxy” and the Problem of Universals
While describing Palamism and Name-Glorification as a variety of Platonism, Losev touches on the problem of universals; he argues that Palamism (and Name-Glorification) suggests a position substantiated from the standpoint of eternal forms, which are present before things and in things. In my mind, the problem of universals, which appeared in Losev’s article, is contextualized by the early stage of the Name-Glorifying debates.
This matter dates back to Fedor Uspensky (1845–1928), a Russian historian, philologist, and byzantinist, the first Russian historian of Byzantine philosophy and the editor of the critical edition of the “Synodikon,”Footnote 22 which Losev used. Uspensky suggested an understanding of the course of Byzantine theology and philosophy in which orthodox Byzantine thought is associated with Aristotelianism-Nominalism and the non-orthodox with Platonism. In Uspensky’s scheme, Palamism was associated with Aristotelianism-Nominalism and Barlaamism with Realism-Platonism.Footnote 23 Concerning the latter, he referred to the tenth section of the chapter “Against Barlaam and Akindynos” of the “Synodikon” published by Uspensky himself.Footnote 24 This scheme was not fully accepted by subsequent Russian thought, but it raised a question that would be answered in some way in the following years during the Name-Glorifying debates.
Mitrofan Muretov, a professor of the Moscow Theological Academy and sympathizer of the Name-Glorifying movement, maintained an understanding directly opposite to Uspensky’s scheme: associating Palamism (and the Name-Glorification identified with it) with Platonism and philosophical realism and Barlaamism with nominalism. He accepted such a qualification of Palamism and Barlaamism by default, without turning to the sources. Anthony Bulatovich, an Athonite monk and a leader of the Name-Glorifiers, did not expressly formulate his views in the philosophical qualification of Palamism and Barlaamism. However, he assimilated Palamism in his works, polemically ascribed the Barlaamite position to his opponents,Footnote 25 and, like Muretov, put forward a teaching about the forms in the context of Name-Glorification.Footnote 26 According to Muretov and Bulatovich, divine names refer to, and are associated with, such forms in God.
Sergey Troitsky, an opponent of the Name-Glorifiers, criticized the teaching of Muretov and Bulatovich on the forms and accused them of Barlaamism, associating the latter with Platonism, partially following the scheme of Uspensky and referring, as he did, to the “Synodikon.” In Troitsky’s mind, Bulatovich’s and Muretov’s teaching that God’s names necessarily refer to the forms in God, which are God himself (in the sense of the divine energies), stands in opposition to Gregory Palamas’s teaching of deification, for the latter is given by the grace of the Holy Spirit and consists in supranatural illumination, not in rational cognition (what grasping the forms would require).Footnote 27 Troitsky thought that Bulatovich and Muretov occupied a rationalist position and followed Barlaam, who was condemned in 1352 for introducing Plato’s forms into the Church. Here, Troitsky referredFootnote 28 to the same words of the conciliar decree that Uspensky had quoted, when speaking about Barlaam’s Platonism. Next, Vladimir Ern and Florensky, acting as apologists for the Name-Glorifying teaching, developed Muretov’s understanding in which Palamism and Name-Glorification were connected with Platonism and realism while Barlaamism and the teaching of the opponents of Name-Glorification were connected with nominalism.Footnote 29
Thus, Losev’s mentioning of the universals seems polemically loaded, and this is connected with the Name-Glorifying controversy. Here, Losev is polemicizing the position of Troitsky who, in the course of the controversy, denied the possibility of speaking about the existence of the forms in God as Muretov and Bulatovich did, protecting the Name-Glorifying doctrine. Troitsky argued that the postulation of the forms in God contradicts the teaching of Gregory Palamas on deification, which is a supernatural epiphany but not the result of rational inquiry. It is in opposition to Troitsky that Losev states that the Palamite and Name-Glorifying doctrine presupposes the existence of the eternal and unchangeable forms that are present in things and before things.Footnote 30 Apart from this, the polemical context of Losev’s remark might be connected to the historical-philosophical scheme of Uspensky, linking Palamism with Aristotelianism and Barlaamism with Platonism, which are diametrically opposed to the scheme of Losev (and the preceding pro-imiaslavie Russian thinkers), maintaining that true orthodox philosophy—that is, Name-Glorification and Palamism—is Platonic.
Losev’s Absolute Symbolism and Florensky’s Platonism
While reasoning about the philosophical and dogmatic component of the Name-Glorifying doctrine, Losev states that, similar to hesychasm, it denies absolute apophatism or agnosticism (which presupposes the total incomprehensibility of God)Footnote 31 as well as absolute rationalism (which presupposes that God reveals himself completely), but represents absolute symbolism, that is, “the teaching that the divine essence, incomprehensible in itself, manifests and reveals itself in certain appearances.” Such symbolism, in Losev’s mind, unites both apophatism and rationalism and corresponds to the doctrine of symbol by Byzantine theologians such as Dionysius the Areopagite, Maximus the Confessor, and Symeon the New Theologian, and the hesychasts of the fourteenth century, that is, the Palamites.Footnote 32
Here, Losev, as he often does in his “Onomatodoxy,” is obviously following the line of Florensky’s principle of logical schematizing and replicating the specific logical scheme given in Florensky’s “Onomatodoxy.” Specifically, Florensky discusses Palamism and Name-Glorification as a variety of Platonism, and characterizes them using the language of symbolic logic in such a way that these doctrines exhibit the following relation between essence and phenomenon: phenomenon is included in essence, but essence is not included in phenomenon (“phenomenon ⸧ essence: entity ⸧–Footnote 33essence”Footnote 34). It is exactly this scheme of Florensky that represents the basis for Losev’s reasoning on the relation between the name of God, essence, and energies in Palamism and in the Name-Glorifying doctrine. Florensky further describes Platonism as a dialectical compound of Kantianism and Immanentism.Footnote 35 He states that Platonism is related to Kantianism with its conviction of the self-existence of essences (here the Kantian thesis on the unknowability of the manifested through manifestation is left out) and, to a certain extent, to Immanentism, which says that manifestation fully represents essence (here the aspect of Immanentism that does not distinguish between the manifested and manifestation is left out). In this way, Florensky provides a scheme on the basis of which Losev determines his absolute symbolism as the doctrine compounding agnosticism (Florensky’s Kantianism) and rationalism (Florensky’s Immanentism).
The Structure of Symbol
The principle of symbolism, understood in terms of an essence’s energicity, also plays an important role in Florensky’s “Onomatodoxy as a Philosophical Premise.”Footnote 36 However, in this essay, Florensky understands “symbol” differently compared to the understanding in Losev’s “Onomatodoxy.” Florensky is developing a teaching about symbol as essence, whose energy is merged with the energy of a higher essence,Footnote 37 which presupposes the concept of “synergy” in Florensky.Footnote 38 Such a scheme is absent in Losev’s essay, where “symbol” is a manifestation and disclosure of the essence and does not represent a separate essence with its own energy, as Florensky states.
This matches the development of Losev’s doctrine of symbol, suggested by Lyudmila Gogotishvili. From her perspective, in the times of Losev’s formative period as a thinker, there were two main traditions in conceptualizing symbol. The first tradition, dating back to Kant, suggests that symbols refer to something totally different—to the meaning not provided directly within the symbol itself.Footnote 39 According to the second tradition, symbol is considered as a balance between the internal and the external (the symbolizing and the symbolized), and, within the structure of the symbol, there is no reference to a totally different entity. This treatment of symbols ascends to Neoplatonism and has clear expression in Friedrich Schelling.Footnote 40 Early-Losev adhered to the second interpretation of symbol;Footnote 41 later, however, Losev followed the first tradition of perceiving symbol as an unbalanced structure.Footnote 42 “Symbolism,” which Losev discusses in his “Onomatodoxy,” presupposes the pairing of the incomprehensible essence and the appearance [= symbol] that reveals it (or, in the language of Palamism, the incomprehensible essence and the energy revealing it). This conceptualization of symbolism belongs, obviously, to the balanced interpretation of symbol, which he adhered to in his early period.
Interestingly, Palamas, in his “Triads,” also offers a teaching on symbol: he calls energy the natural symbol of essence.Footnote 43 This strictly corresponds to the interpretation of symbol in Losev’s “Onomatodoxy,” although, at that time, Losev was not familiar with the corpus of Palamas’s philosophical-dogmatic texts, including “Triads.”
“The Mystical Formula of Name-Glorification,” Antinomies, and Palamism
Now we can focus on Losev’s interpretation of the dialectical dimension of the Name-Glorifying doctrine, following his deliberations on its philosophical background. Losev suggests the following “mystical formula of Name-Glorification”: “a) God’s Name is God’s energy, inseparable from God’s very essence and, therefore, is God himself; b) however, God differs from His energies and His Name and, therefore, God is not His Name, and not any name as such.” Losev repeats this formula, presenting it first in Russian and then in Greek.Footnote 44 Next, Losev argues that the philosophical-dialectical level of Name-Glorification is antinomic and constructs the Name-Glorifying formula in an antinomic way: “Energy is God, but God is not energy; energy differs from essence, albeit is inseparable from it.”Footnote 45
In my opinion, while following the spirit of his ageFootnote 46 and desiring to make all pivotal philosophical-theological provisions antinomical, Losev makes a significant misjudgement. Indeed, the Palamite doctrine that Losev relies on in his deliberation on the theological foundations of Name-Glorification does not agree with his stipulation that God differs from his energy and is not the divine energy. According to historical Palamism, God is the divine essence and energies at once, and the absence of any of these modes of being in God is impossible.Footnote 47 In accordance with Losev’s “mystical formula of Name-Glorification,” energy which is different but inseparable from God’s essence is God; but God is not energy. In my opinion, this formula is linked to the interpretation of Palamism that Losev inherited from Florensky. I discern in Florensky the following logic of relating God’s essence and energies in their connection to naming: God as such, on his own, is the divine essence, and the energies are the mode of God’s “spreading outwards,” towards humans as created beings, and in this respect the energies differ from the essence. Therefore, according to Florensky, the name “God,” in the proper sense, corresponds to the divine essence, and it is from this that the name is transferred to the divine energies.Footnote 48 In my opinion, it is precisely this intuition of Florensky—that the notion of God in the proper sense is related to the divine essence (and in the proper sense God is the divine essence) and from the essence this notion is transferred into energy—which lies behind Losev’s formula found in his “Onomatodoxy,” where energy, being inseparable from the essence but differing from it, is God himself, while God is not energy. I think that within Losev’s formula of Name-Glorification, as well as in Florensky, the word “God” refers to the divine essence, which, according to this view, is God in the proper sense. Precisely because of that, Losev’s formula states that God is not energy.Footnote 49 In fact, this formula claims that action (energy) is named in accordance with the actor (essence), while the actor is not named in accordance with its action.Footnote 50
The Formula of Name-Glorification and Platonism in Losev’s “Onomatodoxy” and “Essays on Ancient Symbolism and Mythology”: Commonalities and Differences
Losev’s interpretation of the relation between naming, essence, and energy finds confirmation in another of his texts where he offers a broad overview of the Palamite doctrine. These are the well-known final chapters in Losev’s “Essays on Ancient Symbolism and Mythology” (1930), written seven or eight years after “Onomatodoxy.” His views on some subjects had changed during the intervening years, but his interpretation of the relation between naming, essence, and energy remained the same. A comparison of “Onomatodoxy” and “Essays on Ancient Symbolism and Mythology” shows Losev’s rethinking of the status of Platonism. In “Onomatodoxy,” he exhibits a positive, almost enthusiastic attitude toward Platonism and Neoplatonism. As I have pointed out, in “Onomatodoxy,” following Florensky, Losev analyzes Palamism and Name-Glorification as a variation of Platonism. He even uses the Neoplatonic doctrine as an example of the future development of the Name-Glorifying system.Footnote 51 In “Essays on Ancient Symbolism,” however, he exhibits a very critical attitude toward historical Platonism and Neoplatonism and dedicates entire sections of the work to demonstrating the inferiority of non-Christian Platonism (and Catholic Platonism) as a worldview to the position of Orthodoxy with which he associates himself.Footnote 52 In this regard, Losev speaks positively of “our, Byzantine Platonism,”Footnote 53 that is, Palamism and Name-Glorification.
This line of argument in “Essays on Ancient Symbolism” is linked to his reappraisal of Florensky. As we have seen, in “Onomatodoxy,” Losev, in many ways, follows Florensky’s Name-Glorifying project established in “Onomatodoxy as a Philosophical Premise” as well as his enthusiastic attitude toward Platonism. However, in “Essays on Ancient Symbolism,” we observe Losev’s careful, even critical, attitude toward Florensky.Footnote 54 This rethinking of Losev’s attitude toward Florensky correlates with Losev’s changed view of historical Platonism. In Losev’s “Essays on Ancient Symbolism,” I find the same line descending from Florensky on the application of the notion “God” to the divine essence and energies as in his “Onomatodoxy.” In “Essays” as in “Onomatodoxy,” Losev discusses the formula: “God’s energy is God, but God is not energy.” In this context, he expresses the idea that “God” in the proper sense is precisely the divine essence, while energy is different from, but also inseparable from, the essence, and it is precisely for this reason that the notion “God,” which, in the proper sense refers to the essence, is being transferred into energy as well: “The essence as such is non-energic; it does not reveal, manifest, or share itself. God’s essence is God himself; the energy of the essence is not separable from the essence itself; therefore, divine energy is God himself. However, God in himself differs from His energies and, therefore, God is not His energy.”Footnote 55
Conclusion
While developing his formulas of hesychasm and Name-Glorifying, Losev employed a range of sources in his “Onomatodoxy.” These sources include “Philokalia,” “Synodikon of Orthodoxy,” and Florensky’s essay “Onomatodoxy as a Philosophical Premise,” the latter affecting Losev the most. Losev’s project of interpreting Palamism and Name-Glorification through Platonism corresponds to the analogous project of Florensky. Although Losev follows the main framework of Florensky’s project in his “Onomatodoxy,” as in, for instance, treating Palamism and Name-Glorification as derivatives of Platonism, he differs from Florensky in his interpretation of the structure of symbol. Losev adopts from Florensky a specific understanding of the application of the concept of “God” to essence and energies in Palamism, according to which precisely the divine essence is taken as God as such. In Losev’s later work, “Essays on Ancient Symbolism and Mythology” (1930), he shifts in his understanding of the correlation of Palamism and Name-Glorification with historical Platonism, a change that directly correlates with his changed attitude toward Florensky. However, in “Essays,” the specific interpretation of the application of the notion “God” to the essence and energies, dating back to Florensky, is preserved.