Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2plfb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-24T05:43:53.908Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

EXTENSIONAL REALIZABILITY AND CHOICE FOR DEPENDENT TYPES IN INTUITIONISTIC SET THEORY

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 July 2022

EMANUELE FRITTAION*
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS TECHNISCHE UNIVERSITÄT DARMSTADT DARMSTADT, GERMANY
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

In [17], we introduced an extensional variant of generic realizability [22], where realizers act extensionally on realizers, and showed that this form of realizability provides inner models of $\mathsf {CZF}$ (constructive Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory) and $\mathsf {IZF}$ (intuitionistic Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory), that further validate $\mathsf {AC}_{\mathsf {FT}}$ (the axiom of choice in all finite types). In this paper, we show that extensional generic realizability validates several choice principles for dependent types, all exceeding $\mathsf {AC}_{\mathsf {FT}}$. We then show that adding such choice principles does not change the arithmetic part of either $\mathsf {CZF}$ or $\mathsf {IZF}$.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

In this paper, we prove that extensional generic realizability [Reference Frittaion and Rathjen17] validates the natural extension of $\mathsf { AC}_{\mathsf {FT}}$ (the axiom of choice in finite types) and $\mathsf {RDC}_{\mathsf {FT}}$ (relativized dependent choice in finite types) to transfinite dependent types. By routinely combining extensional generic realizability with a Beeson-style forcing construction, along the lines of [Reference Friedman and Ščedrov15, Section 5], we also show that T augmented with such choice principles is conservative over T for arithmetic sentences, for a host of intuitionistic set theories T. In particular, we extend Friedman and Ščedrov’s result [Reference Friedman and Ščedrov15] that $\mathsf {IZF}$ augmented with $\mathsf {CAC}_{\mathsf {FT}}$ (finite type countable choice) and $\mathsf {DC}_{\mathsf {FT}}$ (finite type dependent choice) is arithmetically conservative over $\mathsf {IZF}$ .Footnote 1

Generic realizabilityFootnote 2 is distinguished by its treatment of unbounded quantifiers: a realizer of $\forall x\, \varphi (x)$ (resp. $\exists x\, \varphi (x)$ ) must be a realizer of $\varphi (x)$ for every x (resp. some x). This strain of realizability goes back to Kreisel and Troelstra’s realizability for theories of elementary analysis with species variables [Reference Kreisel and Troelstra21, Section 3.7]. A direct descendant of Kreisel and Troelstra’s realizability was applied to nonextensional theories of higher order arithmetic and set theory by Friedman [Reference Friedman14] and Beeson [Reference Beeson5, Reference Beeson7]. McCarty [Reference McCarty22, Reference McCarty23] developed a version of generic realizability that applies directly to the extensional set theory $\mathsf {IZF}$ . He also employed, inspired by Feferman [Reference Feferman12], arbitrary partial combinatory algebras, rather than just natural numbers. Whereas McCarty’s approach is geared towards $\mathsf {IZF}$ , it was shown in [Reference Rathjen30] that $\mathsf {CZF}$ suffices for a formalization of generic realizability, thus providing a self-validating semantics for $\mathsf {CZF}$ and other fragments of $\mathsf {IZF}$ .

In [Reference Frittaion and Rathjen17], we added an extra layer of extensionality to McCarty’s generic realizability, and thus obtained inner models of both $\mathsf {CZF}$ and $\mathsf {IZF}$ that further validate $\mathsf {AC}_{\mathsf {FT}}$ .Footnote 3 In the present paper, we show that extensional generic realizability yields an interpretation of

  • $T+{\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}^{\dagger }+{\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {RDC}^{\dagger }$ in T, and

  • $T+\mathsf {REA}+ {\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}^{\dagger } +{\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {RDC}^{\dagger }$ in $T+\mathsf {REA}$ ,

where T can be either $\mathsf {CZF}$ , $\mathsf {IZF}$ or an extension thereof with other choice axioms. We will introduce this family of choice principles for dependent types in Section 2. Suffice it to say here that ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf { AC}^{\dagger }$ and ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}^{\dagger }$ are closely related to, and in fact follow from, Aczel’s ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}$ and ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}$ . The latter are validated by the type-theoretic interpretations of $\mathsf {CZF}$ [Reference Aczel1, Reference Aczel2] and $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {REA}$ [Reference Aczel3], respectively. Our interpretation does not appear to validate ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}$ and relatives, even if we assume it in the background theory. We will see in Section 4.4 that extensional generic realizability refutes the statement that every set is an image of a ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}$ -set ( ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}$ -set), which instead holds true in Aczel’s type-theoretic interpretation of $\mathsf {CZF}$ ( $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {REA}$ ).

The basic plan for interpreting choice via extensional generic realizability can be easily described as follows. Consider the ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}$ case. We start out with a realizability universe $\mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ , which is built on top of a given partial combinatory algebra A. We then construct an extensional type structure on A (Definition 4.3). In particular, types are elements of A. Next, we single out nice sets of $\mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ of the form $X_{\sigma }$ , where $\sigma $ runs over all types (Definition 4.9). We think of these sets as the extensions of the corresponding types. With this identification in mind, we show that $\mathsf {AC}_{\sigma ,\tau }$ and $\mathsf {RDC}_{\sigma }$ hold in $\mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ (Theorems 4.17 and 4.18). Finally, we prove that every ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}$ -set of $\mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ is nicely represented (Theorems 4.14 and 4.16). Niceness is captured by a suitable notion of being injectively presented in $\mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ (similar notions can be encountered in [Reference Aczel2, Reference Aczel3, Reference Rathjen27Reference Rathjen29]). It will be crucial to work with extensional type structures.

2 Preliminaries

2.1 $\mathsf {CZF}$ and $\mathsf {IZF}$

In this paper, we will be concerned with (extensions of) $\mathsf {CZF}$ (constructive Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory) and $\mathsf {IZF}$ (intuitionistic Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory). The logic is intuitionistic first order logic with equality in the language of classical $\mathsf {ZF}$ . As usual, a formula is bounded, or $\Delta _0$ , if all quantifiers appear in the form $\forall x\in y$ and $\exists x\in y$ .

The theory $\mathsf {CZF}$ consists of the following axioms:

$^{\ast} $ Let $x=0$ be $\forall y\in x\, (y\notin x)$ and $x=y\cup \{y\}$ be $\forall z\kern-1pt \in\kern-1pt x\, (z\kern-1pt \in\kern-1pt y\lor z\kern-1pt =\kern-1pt y)\land \forall z\kern-1pt \in\kern-1pt y\, (z\in x)\land y\kern-1pt \in\kern-1pt x$ .

The theory $\mathsf {IZF}$ consists of extensionality, pairing, union, infinity, induction,

Thus $\mathsf {IZF}$ is $\mathsf {CZF}$ with bounded separation replaced by full separation and subset collection replaced by powerset. Note that powerset implies subset collection, and strong collection follows from separation and collection. It is well known that $\mathsf { CZF}$ with classical logic, and hence $\mathsf {IZF}$ with classical logic, is equivalent to $\mathsf {ZF}$ .

2.2 Countable and dependent choice

The full axiom of choice $\mathsf {AC}$ is known to imply forms of excluded middle [Reference Diaconescu11]. For example, $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {AC}+\text { separation}=\mathsf {IZF}+\mathsf {AC}=\mathsf {ZFC}$ (cf. [Reference Aczel and Rathjen4]). Nevertheless, countable choice and several forms of dependent choice are deemed constructively acceptable. Note that $\mathsf {RDC}$ is an axiom of Myhill’s $\mathsf {CST}$ (constructive set theory) [Reference Myhill24], which provides a standard set-theoretical framework for Bishop-style constructive mathematics [Reference Bishop9]. Dependent choice also features in Brouwer’s intuitionistic analysis (cf. [Reference Troelstra and van Dalen34]).

Countable choice ( $\mathsf {AC}_{\omega }$ ): if $\forall n\in \omega \, \exists y\, \varphi (n,y)$ , then there exists a function f with $\operatorname {{\mathrm {dom}}}(f)=\omega $ such that $\forall n\in \omega \, \varphi (n,f(n))$ , for all formulae $\varphi $ .

Dependent choice ( $\mathsf {DC}$ ): if $\forall x\, \exists y\, \varphi (x,y)$ , then for every x there is a function f with $\operatorname {{\mathrm {dom}}}(f)=\omega $ such that $f(0)=x$ and $\forall n\in \omega \, \varphi (f(n),f(n+1))$ , for all formulae $\varphi $ .

Limited dependent choice ( $\mathsf {DC}^{\dagger }$ ): if X is a set and $\forall x\in X\, \exists y\in X\, \varphi (x,y)$ , then for every $x\in X$ there is a function $f\colon \omega \to X$ such that $f(0)=x$ and $\forall n\in \omega \, \varphi (f(n),f(n+1))$ , for all formulae $\varphi $ .

Relativized dependent choice ( $\mathsf {RDC}$ ): if $\forall x\, (\psi (x)\rightarrow \exists y\, (\psi (y)\land \varphi (x,y)))$ , then for every x such that $\psi (x)$ , there is a function f with $\operatorname {{\mathrm {dom}}}(f)=\omega $ such that $f(0)=x$ and $\forall n\in \omega \, \varphi (f(n),f(n+1))$ , for all formulae $\psi $ and $\varphi $ .

Limited relativized dependent choice ( $\mathsf {RDC}^{\dagger }$ ): if X is a set and $\forall x\in X\, (\psi (x)\rightarrow \exists y\in X\, (\psi (y)\land \varphi (x,y)))$ , then for every $x\in X$ such that $\psi (x)$ , there is a function $f\colon \omega \to X$ such that $f(0)=x$ and $\forall n\in \omega \, \varphi (f(n),f(n+1))$ , for all formulae $\psi $ and $\varphi $ .

Note that classically, say over $\mathsf {ZF}$ , the above forms of dependent choice are all equivalent to one another. Over $\mathsf {CZF}$ , $\mathsf {RDC}\rightarrow \mathsf {DC}$ and $\mathsf {RDC}\rightarrow \mathsf {RDC}^{\dagger }\rightarrow \mathsf {DC}^{\dagger }\rightarrow \mathsf { AC}_{\omega }$ . Over $\mathsf {IZF}$ , due to separation, $\mathsf {RDC}^{\dagger }\leftrightarrow \mathsf {DC}^{\dagger }$ .

2.3 Inductive definitions and the regular extension axiom

The theory $\mathsf {CZF}$ allows for a smooth treatment of inductively defined classes [Reference Aczel3, Reference Aczel and Rathjen4].

Definition 2.1. An inductive definition is a class $\Phi $ of ordered pairs. In other words, any formula $\Phi (X,x)$ is an inductive definition. We write

or simply $(X,x)\in \Phi $ , in place of $\Phi (X,x)$ . A class I is closed under $\Phi $ if, whenever $(X,x)\in \Phi $ and $X\subseteq I$ , we have $x\in I$ .

Theorem 2.2. Given an inductive definition $\Phi $ , there exists a class $I(\Phi )$ such that $\mathsf {CZF}$ proves that $I(\Phi )$ is closed under $\Phi $ , and for every class J, $\mathsf {CZF}$ proves that if J is closed under $\Phi $ , then $I\subseteq J$ . We say that $I(\Phi )$ is inductively defined by $\Phi $ .

Proof See, e.g., [Reference Aczel and Rathjen4] for details. The class $I(\Phi )$ is defined as follows. A set of ordered pairs Z is called an iteration set for $\Phi $ if for every $\langle {u,x}\rangle \in Z$ there exists $(X,x)\in \Phi $ such that $X\subseteq \bigcup _{v\in u}\{z\mid \langle {v,z}\rangle \in Z\}$ . Let

$$\begin{align*}I(\Phi)=\bigcup_u\{ x\mid \text{there is an iteration set } Z \text{ such that }\langle{u,x}\rangle\in Z\}.\end{align*}$$

To prove that $I(\Phi )$ is closed under $\Phi $ we invoke strong collection. The fact that $I(\Phi )$ is the smallest class closed under $\Phi $ is proved by induction.

Theorem 2.3 (Induction on the inductive definition $\Phi $ ).

$\mathsf {CZF}$ proves

$$\begin{align*}\forall (X,x)\in\Phi\, (\forall y\in X\, \varphi(y)\rightarrow \varphi(x))\rightarrow \forall x\in I(\Phi)\, \varphi(x), \end{align*}$$

for every formula $\varphi $ .

Proof Obvious.

In the presence of Aczel’s $\mathsf {REA}$ (regular extension axiom), one can show that many inductively defined classes exist as sets.

Definition 2.4 (Regular).

A set X is regular if it is transitive and, whenever $x\in X$ and R is a set such that $\forall u\in x\, \exists v\in X\, (\langle {u,v}\rangle \in R)$ , then there is a $y\in X$ such that

$$\begin{align*}\forall u\in x\, \exists v\in y\, (\langle{u,v}\rangle\in R)\land \forall v\in y\, \exists u\in x\, (\langle{u,v}\rangle\in R). \end{align*}$$

In particular, if $R\colon x\to X$ is a function, then $\operatorname {{\mathrm {ran}}}(R)\in X$ .

Regular extension axiom ( $\mathsf {REA}$ ): every set is a subset of a regular set.

Definition 2.5. An inductive definition $\Phi $ is bounded if:

  • the class $\{x\mid (X,x)\in \Phi \}$ is a set for every set X;

  • there is a set B such that whenever $(X,x)\in \Phi $ , then X is an image of a set in B, that is, there is a function f from Y onto X for some $Y\in B$ . The set B is called a bound for $\Phi $ .

Theorem 2.6 ( $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {REA}$ ).

If $\Phi $ is a bounded inductive definition, then the class $I(\Phi )$ is a set.

Proof See [Reference Aczel3, Theorem 5.2].

2.4 Dependent type constructions

The usual type constructors ${\Pi }$ (dependent product), ${\Sigma }$ (dependent sum), $\mathrm {I}$ (identity), and $\mathrm {W}$ have obvious set-theoretic analogues.

Definition 2.7 ( $\mathsf {CZF}$ ).

Let F be a function with $\operatorname {{\mathrm {dom}}}(F)=X$ . Let

$$ \begin{align*} {\Pi}(X,F)&= \prod_{x\in X}F(x)=\{f\colon X\to \bigcup_{x\in X}F(x)\mid \forall x\in X\, (f(x)\in F(x))\} && ({{Cartesian\ product}}), \\ {\Sigma}(X,F)&=\sum_{x\in X}F(x)=\{ \langle{x,y}\rangle\mid x\in X\land y\in F(x)\} && ({{disjoint\ union}}). \end{align*} $$

For x, y sets, let $\mathrm {I}(x,y)=\{z\in \{0\}\mid x=y\}$ .

Remark 2.8. Set exponentiation $X\to Y$ and the binary Cartesian product $X\times Y$ are special instances of ${\Pi }(X,F)$ and ${\Sigma }(X,F)$ respectively, with $F(x)=Y$ .

Definition 2.9 ( $\mathsf {CZF}$ ).

If F is a function with $\operatorname {{\mathrm {dom}}}(F)=X$ , then $\mathrm {W}(X,F)$ is the smallest class W such that

  • if $x\in X$ and $f\colon F(x)\to W$ , then $\langle {x,f}\rangle \in W$ .

Remark 2.10. $\mathrm {W}(X,F)$ is the class of well-founded rooted trees with labels in X such that the arity of a node with label x is the set $F(x)$ .

Theorem 2.11 ( $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {REA}$ ).

The class $\mathrm {W}(X,F)$ is a set.

Proof By Theorem 2.6, since $\mathrm {W}(X,F)$ is bounded inductively definable.

Definition 2.12 ( $\mathsf {CZF}$ ).

The class $I={\Pi }{\Sigma }$ is inductively defined by clauses:

  1. (i) $n\in I$ for every $n\in \omega $ ;

  2. (ii) $\omega \in I$ ;

  3. (iii) if $X\in I$ and $F\colon X\to I$ , then ${\Pi }(X,F),{\Sigma }(X,F)\in I$ .

The class $I={\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}$ is inductively defined by clauses (i), (ii), (iii), and

  1. (iv) if $X\in I$ and $x,y\in X$ , then $\mathrm {I}(x,y)\in I$ .

Definition 2.13 ( $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {REA}$ ).

The class $I={\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}$ is inductively defined by clauses (i), (ii), (iii), and

  1. (v) if $X\in I$ and $F\colon X\to I$ , then $\mathrm {W}(X,F)\in I$ .

The class $I={\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}$ is inductively defined by clauses (i)–(v).

Given a class I, we say that x is an I-set if x belongs to I.

2.5 Choice for dependent types

Definition 2.14 (Base).

A set X is a base if for every relation R such that $\forall x\in X\, \exists y\, (\langle {x,y}\rangle \in R)$ , there exists a function f with domain X such that $\forall x\in X\, (\langle {x,f(x)}\rangle \in R)$ .Footnote 4

Presentation axiom ( $\mathsf {PAx}$ ): every set is an image of a base.

${\Pi }{\Sigma }$ axiom of choice ( ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\text {-}\mathsf {AC}$ ): every ${\Pi }{\Sigma }$ -set is a base.

${\Pi }{\Sigma }$ presentation axiom ( ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\text {-}\mathsf {PAx}$ ): every set is an image of a ${\Pi }{\Sigma }$ -set and every ${\Pi }{\Sigma }$ -set is a base.

We have analogue axioms for ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}$ and relatives. A simple argument shows that $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {PAx}\vdash \mathsf { DC}^{\dagger }$ (cf. [Reference Aczel1, p. 65] and [Reference Aczel2, p. 27]). Aczel’s interpretation of $\mathsf {CZF}$ in type theory [Reference Aczel1] validates $\mathsf {RDC}$ [Reference Aczel1, Theorem 7.1], [Reference Aczel2, Theorem 5.7] and ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {PAx}$ [Reference Aczel2, Theorem 7.4]. In [Reference Aczel3], the type-theoretic interpretation of $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {REA}$ (by using $\mathrm {W}$ -types) is shown to validate $\mathsf {RDC}$ and ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {PAx}$ [Reference Aczel3, Theorem 5.6].Footnote 5 Similarly, Rathjen’s formulae-as-classes interpretation provides a model of $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf { RDC}+{\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}$ in $\mathsf {CZF}_{\mathsf {exp}}$ [Reference Rathjen29, Theorem 4.13] and of $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {REA}+\mathsf {RDC}+{\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}$ in $\mathsf {CZF}_{\mathsf { exp}}+\mathsf {REA}$ [Reference Rathjen29, Theorem 4.33], where $\mathsf {CZF}_{\mathsf {exp}}$ is $\mathsf {CZF}$ with exponentiation in lieu of subset collection.

We introduce the following natural extensions of $\mathsf {AC}_{\mathsf {FT}}$ and $\mathsf {RDC}_{\mathsf {FT}}$ .

${\Pi }{\Sigma }$ limited axiom of choice ( ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\text {-}\mathsf {AC}^{\dagger }$ ): if X and Y are ${\Pi }{\Sigma }$ -sets and $\forall x\in X\, \exists y\in Y\, \varphi (x,y)$ , then there is a function $f\colon X\to Y$ such that $\forall x\in X\, \varphi (x,f(x))$ , for all formulae $\varphi $ .

${\Pi }{\Sigma }$ limited relativized dependent choice ( ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\text {-}\mathsf {RDC}^{\dagger }$ ): this is just $\mathsf { RDC}^{\dagger }$ restricted to ${\Pi }{\Sigma }$ -sets.

We have similar axioms for ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}$ and relatives. Each schema can be replaced by a single axiom over say $\mathsf { IZF}+\mathsf {REA}$ . This is just an upper bound. For example, over $\mathsf {CZF}$ , ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\text {-}\mathsf {AC}^{\dagger }$ is equivalent to:

If X and Y are ${\Pi }{\Sigma }$ -sets, then for every relation R such that $\forall x\in X\, \exists y\in Y\, (\langle {x,y}\rangle \in R)$ , there is a function $f\colon X\to Y$ such that $\forall x\in X\, (\langle {x,f(x)}\rangle \in R)$ .

Clearly, ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\text {-}\mathsf {AC}^{\dagger }$ follows from ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\text {-}\mathsf {AC}$ , and similarly for ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}$ and the like. Note that ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\text {-}\mathsf {AC}^{\dagger }$ already includes the axiom of choice for all finite types.

Theorem 2.15. Over $\mathsf {CZF}$ , ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}\leftrightarrow {\Pi }{\Sigma }\text {-}\mathsf {AC}$ and ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {PAx} \ \leftrightarrow {\Pi }{\Sigma }\text {-}\mathsf {PAx}$ .

Over $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {REA}$ , ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}\leftrightarrow {\Pi }{\Sigma }\text {-}\mathsf {AC}$ and ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\text {-}\mathsf {PAx}\leftrightarrow {\Pi }{\Sigma }\text {-}\mathsf {PAx}$ .

Proof See [Reference Aczel3, Theorems 3.7 and 5.9].

Theorem 2.15 does not translate to ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\text {-}\mathsf {AC}^{\dagger }$ and relatives. For example, the proof of [Reference Aczel3, Theorem 3.7] consists in showing, under ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\text {-}\mathsf {AC}$ , that every set in ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}$ is in bijection with a set in ${\Pi }{\Sigma }$ . The use of ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\text {-}\mathsf {AC}$ is essential. The proof of the following is trivial.

Theorem 2.16. Over $\mathsf {CZF} +$ “every set is an image of a ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}$ -set,” $ {\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC} \leftrightarrow {\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}^{\dagger }$ . Similarly for $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {REA}$ and ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}$ in place of $\mathsf {CZF}$ and ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}$ respectively.

3 Extensional generic realizability

3.1 Partial combinatory algebras

Generic realizability is based on the notion of partial combinatory algebra. Let us review some basic facts. For more information, we refer the reader to [Reference Beeson7, Reference Feferman12, Reference Feferman13, Reference van Oosten26].

Definition 3.1. Application terms, or simply terms, over a set A are defined by clauses:

  1. (i) variables $x_1,x_2,\ldots $ are terms;

  2. (ii) elements of A are terms;

  3. (iii) if t and s are terms, $(ts)$ is also a term.

Definition 3.2. A partial algebra is a set A together with a partial binary operation $\cdot $ on A.

Every partial algebra A induces a partial interpretation of closed applications terms over A by elements of A in the obvious way.

Notation 3.3. Let $a,b,c\in A$ and $t,s$ be closed terms over A. Instead of $a\cdot b$ we just write $ab$ . We also employ the association to the left convention, meaning that $abc$ stands for $(ab)c$ . The relation $t\downarrow a$ is defined by clauses: (i) $a\downarrow a$ and (ii) $(ts)\downarrow a$ if $t\downarrow b$ , $s\downarrow c$ , and $bc=a$ for some $b,c\in A$ . We write $t\downarrow $ for $\exists a\, (t\downarrow a)$ . We use Kleene equality $t\simeq s$ to express that either both sides are undefined, or else they are both defined and equal. In the second case, we write $t=s$ .

Definition 3.4. A partial algebra $(A,\cdot )$ with at least two elements is a partial combinatory algebra (pca) if there are elements $\mathbf k$ and $\mathbf s$ in A such that for all $a,b,c\in A$ :

  • $\mathbf ka b\simeq a$ ;

  • $\mathbf sab\downarrow $ and $\mathbf sabc\simeq ac(bc)$ .

The combinators $\mathbf k$ and $\mathbf s$ are due to Schönfinkel [Reference Schönfinkel31] and the defining equations, although formulated just in the total case, are due to Curry [Reference Curry10]. The name combinatory stems from the property known as combinatory completeness. Informally, this means that we can form $\lambda $ -terms.

Lemma 3.5 ( $\lambda $ -abstraction).

Let A be a pca. For every term $t(x,x_1,\ldots ,x_n)$ , one can find (in an effective way) a new term $s(x_1,\ldots ,x_n)$ , denoted $\lambda x.t$ , such that for all $a_1,\ldots ,a_n\in A$ :

  • $s(a_1,\ldots ,a_n)\downarrow $ ;

  • $s(a_1,\ldots ,a_n)a\simeq t(a,a_1,\ldots ,a_n)$ .

Remark 3.6. The term $\lambda x.t$ is built solely with the aid of $\mathbf k$ , $\mathbf s$ , and symbols occurring in t. Also, the construction of this term is uniform in the given pca.

An immediate consequence of $\lambda $ -abstraction is the existence of pairing and unpairing combinators $\mathbf p$ , $\mathbf {p_0}$ , and $\mathbf {p_1}$ such that $\mathbf pab\downarrow $ and $\mathbf {p_i}(\mathbf pa_0a_1)\simeq a_i$ .Footnote 6 A more remarkable application of $\lambda $ -abstraction is the recursion theorem for pca’s.

Lemma 3.7 (Recursion theorem).

There exists a closed term $\mathbf f$ such that for all $a,b\in A$ we have $\mathbf f a\downarrow $ and $\mathbf f ab\simeq a(\mathbf fa) b$ .

It is worth considering some additional structure (see however Remark 3.9).

Definition 3.8. We say that A is a pca over $\omega $ if there are combinators $\mathbf {succ}, \mathbf {pred}$ (successor and predecessor combinators), $\mathbf d$ (definition by cases combinator), and a map $n\mapsto \bar n$ from $\omega $ to A such that for all $n\in \omega $

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{\mathbf{succ}}} \bar n&\simeq \overline{n+1}, & \operatorname{\mathrm{\mathbf{pred}}}\overline{n+1}&\simeq \bar n, & \mathbf d\bar n\bar mab\simeq \begin{cases} a, & n=m,\\ b, & n\neq m. \end{cases} \end{align*} $$

One then defines $\mathbf 0=_{\mathrm {def}}\bar 0$ and ${\mathbf 1}=_{\mathrm {def}}\bar 1$ .

For the rest of the paper, by a pca we really mean a pca over $\omega $ . The only closed terms we ever need are built up by using the combinators $\mathbf k$ , $\mathbf s$ , $\mathbf p$ , $\mathbf {p_0}$ , $\mathbf {p_1}$ , $\mathbf 0$ , ${\mathbf 1}$ , $\mathbf {succ}$ , $\mathbf {pred}$ , and $\mathbf d$ .

Note that one can do without $\mathbf k$ by letting $\mathbf k=_{\mathrm {def}}\mathbf d\mathbf 0\mathbf 0$ . The existence of $\mathbf d$ implies that the map $n\mapsto \bar n$ is one-to-one. In fact, suppose $\bar n=\bar m$ but $n\neq m$ . Then $\mathbf d\bar n\bar n\simeq \mathbf d\bar n\bar m$ . It then follows that $a\simeq \mathbf d\bar n\bar nab\simeq \mathbf d\bar n\bar mab\simeq b$ for all $a,b$ . On the other hand, by our definition, every pca contains at least two elements.

Remark 3.9. Every pca can be turned into a pca over $\omega $ . For example, one can define Curry numerals and construct by $\lambda $ -abstraction a combinator $\mathbf d$ for this representation of natural numbers. In practice, however, all natural examples of pca come already equipped with a canonical copy of the natural numbers and pertaining combinators.

3.2 Defining realizability

Definition 3.10 ( $\mathsf {CZF}$ ).

Given a pca A, the class $\mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ is inductively defined by the clause:

  • if $x\subseteq A\times A\times \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ , then $x\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ .

The inductive definition of $\mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ within $\mathsf {CZF}$ is on par with that of $\mathrm {V}(A)$ [Reference Rathjen30,Lemma 3.4].

Notation 3.11. We use $(a)_i$ or simply $a_i$ for $\mathbf {p_i}a$ . Whenever we write a term t, we assume that it is defined. In other words, a formula $\varphi (t)$ stands for $\exists a\, (t\downarrow a\land \varphi (a))$ .

Definition 3.12 (Extensional realizability).

We define the relation $a=b\Vdash \varphi $ , where $a,b\in A$ and $\varphi $ is a realizability formula with parameters in $\mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ . The atomic cases fall under the scope of definitions by transfinite recursion.

$$ \begin{align*} a=b&\Vdash x\in y && \Leftrightarrow && \exists z\, (\langle (a)_0,(b)_0,z\rangle \in y\land (a)_1=(b)_1\Vdash x=z),\\ a=b& \Vdash x=y && \Leftrightarrow &&\forall \langle c,d,z\rangle \in x\, ((ac)_0=(bd)_0\Vdash z\in y) \text{ and } \\ &&&&& \forall \langle c,d,z\rangle \in y\, ((ac)_1=(bd)_1\Vdash z\in x),\\ a=b& \Vdash \varphi\land \psi && \Leftrightarrow && (a)_0=(b)_0\Vdash \varphi \land (a)_1=(b)_1\Vdash \psi, \\ a=b& \Vdash \varphi\lor\psi && \Leftrightarrow && (a)_0=(b)_0=\mathbf 0\land (a)_1=(b)_1\Vdash \varphi \text{ or } \\ &&&&& (a)_0=(b)_0={\mathbf 1}\land (a)_1=(b)_1\Vdash \psi, \\ a=b&\Vdash \neg\varphi && \Leftrightarrow && \forall c, d\, \neg (c=d\Vdash \varphi), \\ a=b&\Vdash \varphi\rightarrow\psi && \Leftrightarrow && \forall c,d\, (c=d\Vdash \varphi\rightarrow ac=bd\Vdash \psi), \\ a=b& \Vdash \forall x\in y\, \varphi && \Leftrightarrow && \forall \langle c,d,x\rangle\in y\, (ac=bd\Vdash \varphi), \\ a=b&\Vdash \exists x\in y\, \varphi && \Leftrightarrow && \exists x\, (\langle (a)_0,(b)_0,x\rangle \in y\land (a)_1=(b)_1\Vdash \varphi),\\ a=b& \Vdash \forall x\, \varphi && \Leftrightarrow && \forall x\in \mathrm{V_{ext}}(A)\, (a=b\Vdash \varphi), \\ a=b& \Vdash \exists x\, \varphi && \Leftrightarrow && \exists x\in \mathrm{V_{ext}}(A)\, (a=b\Vdash \varphi). \end{align*} $$

Notation 3.13. We write $\Vdash \varphi $ in place of $\exists a,b\in A\, (a=b\Vdash \varphi )$ and $a\Vdash \varphi $ for $a=a\Vdash \varphi $ .

We will repeatedly use the following internal pairing function $\langle {x,y}\rangle _{\!A}$ in $\mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ .

Definition 3.14 (Pairing).

For $x,y\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ , let

$$ \begin{align*} \{{x}\}_{A}&=\{\langle{\mathbf 0,\mathbf 0,x}\rangle\}, \\ \{{x,y}\}_{A}&=\{\langle{\mathbf 0,\mathbf 0,x}\rangle,\langle{{\mathbf 1},{\mathbf 1},y}\rangle\}, \\ \langle{x,y}\rangle_{\!A}&=\{\langle{\mathbf 0,\mathbf 0,\{{x}\}_{A}}\rangle, \langle{{\mathbf 1},{\mathbf 1},\{{x,y}\}_{A}}\rangle\}. \end{align*} $$

Note that all these sets are in $\mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ .

We use $\operatorname {{\mathrm {OP}}}(z,x,y)$ as abbreviation for the set-theoretic formula expressing that z is the ordered pair of x and y. In standard notation, $z=\langle {x,y}\rangle $ . Ordered pairs can be defined as usual as $\langle {x,y}\rangle =_{\mathrm {def}}\{\{x\},\{x,y\}\}$ .

Lemma 3.15. There are closed terms ${\mathbf u}_i$ such that $\mathsf {CZF}$ proves

$$ \begin{align*} {\mathbf u}_0 & \Vdash \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(\langle{x,y}\rangle_{\!A},x,y),\\ {\mathbf u}_1 & \Vdash \langle{x,y}\rangle_{\!A}=\langle{u,v}\rangle_{\!A}\rightarrow x=u\land y=v, \\ {\mathbf u}_2 &\Vdash \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z,x,y) \rightarrow z=\langle{x,y}\rangle_{\!A}. \end{align*} $$

Proof This is similar to [Reference McCarty22, Lemmas 3.2 and 3.4].

Theorem 3.16 [Reference Frittaion and Rathjen17].

For every theorem $\varphi $ of $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {AC}_{\mathsf {FT}}$ , there is a closed term ${\mathbf t}$ such that $\mathsf { CZF}$ proves ${\mathbf t}\Vdash \varphi $ . The same for $\mathsf {IZF}$ .

Remark 3.17. The realizability relation $\Vdash $ uses A as a parameter. We should then write $\Vdash _A$ . The soundness theorem claims that for every theorem $\varphi $ of T there is a closed term ${\mathbf t}$ such that $T\vdash \forall A\, (A\text { is a pca}\rightarrow {\mathbf t}\Vdash _A \varphi )$ . For special cases, where the pca A is definable as a set in T and $T\vdash A \text { is a pca}$ , we obtain $T\vdash {\mathbf t}\Vdash _A \varphi $ . For instance, in the case of Kleene’s first algebra, we have that for every theorem $\varphi $ , there is a closed term ${\mathbf t}$ such that $T\vdash \exists n\in \omega \, ({\mathbf t}\downarrow n\land n\Vdash \varphi )$ .

Definition 3.18. Write $T\models \varphi $ for $T\vdash \exists a,b\in A\, (a=b\Vdash \varphi )$ . In general, we write $T\models S$ if $T\models \varphi $ for every sentence $\varphi $ of S. We say that T is self-validating if $T\models T$ .

Theorem 3.19. Let T be any of the theories obtained by appending to either $\mathsf {CZF}$ or $\mathsf {IZF}$ some or all of the axioms $\mathsf { REA}$ , $\mathsf {AC}_{\omega }$ , $\mathsf {DC}$ , $\mathsf {DC}^{\dagger }$ , $\mathsf {RDC}$ , $\mathsf {RDC}^{\dagger }$ , and $\mathsf {PAx}$ . Then T is self-validating.

Proof This holds in the case of generic realizability. See [Reference Rathjen30, Theorem 6.2] for $\mathsf {REA}$ and [Reference Rathjen30, Theorem 10.1] for $\mathsf {DC}^{\dagger }$ (there called $\mathsf {DC}$ ), $\mathsf {RDC}$ , and $\mathsf { PAx}$ . The other axioms are treated in a similar way. In the case of extensional generic realizability, the proof is a nearly verbatim copy of that for generic realizability.

Let us sketch a proof for $\mathsf {PAx}$ . We wish to find a closed term ${\mathbf e}$ such that, over $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {PAx}$ ,

$$\begin{align*}{\mathbf e}\Vdash \forall y\, \exists x\, \exists f\, (x \text{ is a base and } f\colon x\twoheadrightarrow y). \end{align*}$$

By definition, this means that for every $y\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ there are $x,f\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ such that

$$\begin{align*}{\mathbf e}\Vdash x \text{ is a base and } f\colon x\twoheadrightarrow y. \end{align*}$$

Let $y\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ . By $\mathsf {PAx}$ in the background universe, there exists a base B and a function F from B onto y. Say $F(u)=\langle {a_u,b_u,z_u}\rangle \in y$ for $u\in B$ . By transfinite recursion, define

$$\begin{align*}\check u=\{\langle{\mathbf 0,\mathbf 0, \check{v}}\rangle\mid v\in u\}. \end{align*}$$

Then for every set u, $\check u\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ . Moreover, by induction, one can show that these names are absolute, namely,

$$\begin{align*}u=v \leftrightarrow (\Vdash \check{u}=\check{v}). \end{align*}$$

Let

$$ \begin{align*} x&=\{\langle{a_u,b_u,\check u}\rangle\mid u\in B\},\\[5pt] f&=\{\langle{a_u,b_u,\langle{\check u,z_u}\rangle_{\!A}}\rangle\mid u\in B\}, \end{align*} $$

where $\langle {u,v}\rangle _{\!A}$ is the internal pair in $\mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ from Definition 3.14. One can find a closed term $\mathbf f$ such that $\mathbf f \Vdash \operatorname {{\mathrm {Fun}}}(f)$ thanks to the absoluteness of $\check {}$ names. It is not difficult to build a closed term ${\mathbf t}$ such that ${\mathbf t} \Vdash f\colon x\twoheadrightarrow y$ . Finally, it is straightforward to cook up a closed term $\mathbf b$ and show that $\mathbf b\Vdash x \text { is a base}$ , by using the fact that B is a base.

In view of Definition 3.18, our goal is to show that:

  • $T\models T+{\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}^{\dagger }+{\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {RDC}^{\dagger }$ ,

  • $T+\mathsf {REA}\models T+\mathsf {REA}+{\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf { AC}^{\dagger }+{\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {RDC}^{\dagger }$ ,

where T is as in Theorem 3.19.

4 Realizing choice for dependent types

4.1 Dependent types over partial combinatory algebras

Given a pca A, we wish to define extensional type structures on A, that is, structures of the form

$$\begin{align*}(\mathbb{T},\sim,(A_{\sigma},\sim_{\sigma})_{\sigma\in\mathbb{T}}), \end{align*}$$

where $\sim $ is a partial equivalence relation on A and $\sim _{\sigma }$ is a partial equivalence relation on A for every $\sigma $ such that $\sigma \sim \sigma $ . Then $\mathbb {T}=\{\sigma \in A\mid \sigma \sim \sigma \}$ and $A_{\sigma }=\{a\in A\mid a\sim _{\sigma } a\}$ for every $\sigma \in \mathbb {T}$ . Clearly, we want equivalent types to have the same elements. We must then ensure that if $\sigma \sim \tau $ , then $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ iff $a\sim _{\tau } b$ .

Definition 4.1. We say that $\sigma $ is a type if $\sigma \in \mathbb {T}$ . We say that $a\in A$ has type $\sigma $ if $a\in A_{\sigma }$ .

From now on, definitions and theorems take place in $\mathsf {CZF}$ , unless we are dealing with $\mathrm {W}$ -types, in which case we work in $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {REA}$ .

Notation 4.2. Given a pca A, $a,b,c\in A$ , and $n\in \omega $ , we write:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathsf{N}_n&=_{\mathrm{def}} \mathbf p \bar 0\bar n, & \mathsf{N}&=_{\mathrm{def}}\mathbf p\bar 1\mathbf 0, \\ {\Pi}_ab&=_{\mathrm{def}} \mathbf p \bar 2(\mathbf pab), & {\Sigma}_ab&=_{\mathrm{def}}\mathbf p \bar 3(\mathbf pab), \\ \mathrm{I}_c(a,b)&=_{\mathrm{def}} \mathbf p \bar 4(\mathbf p c(\mathbf pab)), & \mathrm{W}_ab &=_{\mathrm{def}}\mathbf p \bar 5(\mathbf p ab). \end{align*} $$

This ensures unique readability. For example, $\mathsf {N}\neq {\Pi }_a b$ , and ${\Pi }_ab={\Pi }_cd$ implies $a=b$ and $c=d$ .

Definition 4.3 ( ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}$ -types).

Given a pca A, we inductively define the ${\Pi }{\Sigma }$ type structure by clauses:

  1. (i) $\mathsf {N}_n\sim \mathsf {N}_n$ and $a\sim _{\mathsf {N}_n} b$ iff $a=b=\bar m$ for some $m<n$ ;

  2. (ii) $\mathsf {N}\sim \mathsf {N}$ and $a\sim _{\mathsf {N}} b$ iff $a=b=\bar n$ for some $n\in \omega $ ;

  3. (iii) if $\sigma \sim \tau $ , and $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ implies $ia\sim jb$ , then:

    • $\alpha ={\Pi }_{\sigma } i\sim {\Pi }_{\tau } j$ ;

    • $f\sim _{\alpha } g$ iff $fa\sim _{ia} gb$ whenever $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ ; and

    • $\beta ={\Sigma }_{\sigma } i\sim {\Sigma }_{\tau } j$ ;

    • $a\sim _{\beta } b$ iff $a_0\sim _{\sigma } b_0$ and $a_1\sim _{ia_0} b_1$ .

The $\Pi {\Sigma }\mathrm {I}$ type structure is inductively defined by adding the clause:

  1. (iv) if $\sigma \sim \tau $ , $a\sim _{\sigma } \breve a$ , and $b\sim _{\sigma } \breve b$ , then:

    • $\gamma =\mathrm {I}_{\sigma }(a,b)\sim \mathrm {I}_{\tau }(\breve a,\breve b)$ ;

    • $c\sim _{\gamma } d$ iff $c=d=\mathbf 0$ and $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ .

The ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}$ type structure is inductively defined by clauses (i), (ii), (iii), (iv), and

  1. (v) if $\sigma \sim \tau $ , and $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ implies $ia\sim jb$ , then:

    • $\delta =\mathrm {W}_{\sigma } i\sim \mathrm {W}_{\tau } j$ ;

    • $c\sim _{\delta } d$ iff $c_0\sim _{\sigma } d_0$ and $c_1p\sim _{\delta } d_1q$ whenever $p\sim _{ic_0} q$ .

Remark 4.4. To be precise, each type structure from Definition 4.3 is an inductively defined class I of triples $\langle {\sigma ,\tau ,B}\rangle $ . The intended meaning is $\sigma \sim \tau $ and $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ iff $\langle {a,b}\rangle \in B$ . For instance, the rules for the introduction of ${\Pi }$ -types and $\mathrm {W}$ -types are

where $\sigma ,\tau ,i,j\in A$ , and for some set $B\subseteq A\times A$ and some function F with $\operatorname {{\mathrm {dom}}}(F)=B$ , we have:

  • $\{\langle {\sigma ,\tau ,B}\rangle \}\cup \{\langle {ia,jb,F(a,b)}\rangle \mid \langle {a,b}\rangle \in B\}\subseteq X$ ,

  • $C=\{\langle {f,g}\rangle \in A\times A\mid \forall \langle {a,b}\rangle \in B\, (\langle {fa,gb}\rangle \in F(a,b))\}$ ,

  • $D=\{\langle {c,d}\rangle \in A\times A\mid \langle {c_0,d_0}\rangle \in B\land \forall \langle {p,q}\rangle \in F(c_0,d_0)\, \langle {c_1p,d_1p}\rangle \in D\}$ .

It is not difficult to see that D has a bounded inductive definition, and therefore by Theorem 2.6 is a set in $\mathsf { CZF}+\mathsf {REA}$ .

By induction on the inductive definition of I, one may show that if $\langle {\sigma ,\tau _0,B_0}\rangle \in I$ and $\langle {\sigma ,\tau _1,B_1}\rangle \in I$ , then $B_0=B_1$ . Hence, by letting

$$ \begin{align*} \sim &=_{\mathrm{def}} \{\langle{\sigma,\tau}\rangle\mid \exists B\, \langle{\sigma,\tau,B}\rangle\in I\}, \\ \sim_{\sigma} &=_{\mathrm{def}} \bigcup\{ B\mid \exists \tau\, \langle{\sigma,\tau,B}\rangle\in I\}, \end{align*} $$

we obtain in particular that if $\langle {\sigma ,\tau ,B}\rangle \in I$ , then $B=\bigcup \{B\mid \exists \tau \, \langle {\sigma ,\tau ,B}\rangle \in I\}$ is a set, and so $\sim _{\sigma }$ is a set as well.

Lemma 4.5. Suppose $\sigma \sim \tau $ and $\tau \sim \rho $ . Then:

  1. (i) $\sigma \sim \sigma $ , $\tau \sim \sigma $ , and $\sigma \sim \rho $ ;

  2. (ii) $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ iff $a\sim _{\tau } b$ ;

  3. (iii) $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ and $b\sim _{\sigma } c$ implies $a\sim _{\sigma } a$ , $b\sim _{\sigma } a$ , and $a\sim _{\sigma } c$ .

In other words, $\sim $ and $\sim _{\sigma }$ are partial equivalence relations on A.

Proof By induction on the (inductive definition of the) type structure. The case of $\mathrm {W}_{\sigma } i$ is dealt with a further induction on the given $\mathrm {W}$ -type.

4.2 Representing ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}$

Definition 4.6. Given a type structure on A and a type $\sigma $ , we say that $i\in A$ is a family of types over $\sigma $ if $ia\sim ib$ whenever $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ . If $\sigma $ is a type and $ia\sim jb$ whenever $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ , we write $i\approx _{\sigma } j$ .

Note that in any of the type structures here considered, if i is a family of types over $\sigma $ , then ${\Pi }_{\sigma } i$ and ${\Sigma }_{\sigma } i$ are types. Moreover, if $\sigma \sim \tau $ and $i\approx _{\sigma } j$ , then $i\approx _{\tau } j$ .

Definition 4.7 (Mapping typed elements of A in $\mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ ).

For $n\in \omega $ , let

$$\begin{align*}\dot n=\{\langle{\bar m,\bar m,\dot m}\rangle\mid m<n\}. \end{align*}$$

For every ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}$ -type $\sigma $ , we inductively define $a^{\sigma }\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ for every a of type $\sigma $ by:

  • if $\sigma =\mathsf {N}_n$ or $\sigma =\mathsf {N}$ , let $a^{\sigma }=\dot m$ , where $a=\bar m$ ;

  • if $\alpha ={\Pi }_{\sigma } i$ , let $ f^{\alpha }=\{\langle {a,b,\langle {a^{\sigma },(fa)^{\tau }}\rangle _{\!A}}\rangle \mid a\sim _{\sigma } b\land ia=\tau \}$ ;

  • if $\beta ={\Sigma }_{\sigma } i$ , let $ a^{\beta }=\langle {(a_0)^{\sigma },(a_1)^{\tau }}\rangle _{\!A}$ , where $ia_0= \tau $ ;

  • if $\gamma =\mathrm {I}_{\sigma }(a,b)$ , let $ c^{\gamma }=0 $ .

For ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}$ -types, we add the clause:

  • if $\delta =\mathrm {W}_{\sigma } i$ , let $c^{\delta }=\langle {a^{\sigma },\{\langle {p,q,\langle {p^{ia},(c_1p)^{\delta }}\rangle _{\!A}}\rangle \mid p\sim _{ia} q\}}\rangle _{\!A}$ , where $a=c_0$ .

Remark 4.8. A comment on the above definition may be in order. The class function $(\sigma ,a)\mapsto a^{\sigma }$ is obtained by defining a class E of pairs $\langle {\sigma ,e_{\sigma }}\rangle $ , the intended meaning of which is $e_{\sigma }=\{\langle {a,a^{\sigma }}\rangle \mid a\in A_{\sigma }\}$ , where $A_{\sigma }=\{a\in A\mid a\text { has type } \sigma \}$ . Note that $A_{\sigma }$ is a set. Hence, $a^{\sigma }$ is really $e_{\sigma }(a)$ . For example, the rules for ${\Sigma }$ -types and $\mathrm {W}$ -types are

where $\sigma $ is type, i is a family of types over $\sigma $ , and there exist functions $e_{\sigma }$ and f on $A_{\sigma }$ such that:

  • $\operatorname {{\mathrm {Fun}}}(f(a))\land \operatorname {{\mathrm {dom}}}(f(a))=A_{ia}$ , for every $a\in A_{\sigma }$ ,

  • $X=\{\langle {\sigma ,e_{\sigma }}\rangle \}\cup \{\langle {ia,f(a)}\rangle \mid a\in A_{\sigma }\}$ ,

  • $e_{\beta }=\{\langle {a,\langle {e_{\sigma }(a_0),f(a_0,a_1)}\rangle _{\!A}}\rangle \mid a\text { has type } {\Sigma }_{\sigma } i\}$ ,

and $e_{\delta }$ is inductively defined by the clause:

  • if c has type $\mathrm {W}_{\sigma } i$ and there exists a function k with $\operatorname {{\mathrm {dom}}}(k)=A_{ic_0}$ such that $\langle {c_1p,k(p)}\rangle \in e_{\delta }$ for every $p\in \operatorname {{\mathrm {dom}}}(k)$ , then

    $$\begin{align*}\langle{c,\langle{e_{\sigma}(c_0),\{\langle{p,q,\langle{f(c_0,p), k(p)}\rangle_{\!A}}\rangle\mid p\sim_{ic_0} q\}}\rangle_{\!A}}\rangle \in e_{\delta}. \end{align*}$$

By induction on the inductive definition of E, one shows that E is a class function on $\mathbb {T}$ , and $E(\sigma )=e_{\sigma }\colon A_{\sigma }\to \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ , for every type $\sigma $ . Note that $e_{\delta }$ has a bounded inductive definition and so is a set in $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {REA}$ .

Definition 4.9 (Canonical ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}$ -sets in $\mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ ).

Given a type $\sigma $ and a family i of types over $\sigma $ , we define sets $X_{\sigma }, F_{\sigma ,i}\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ by:

  • $X_{\sigma }=\{\langle {a,b,a^{\sigma }}\rangle \mid a \sim _{\sigma } b\}$ ;

  • $F_{\sigma ,i}=\{\langle {a,b,\langle {a^{\sigma },X_{\tau }}\rangle _{\!A}}\rangle \mid a\sim _{\sigma } b\land ia= \tau \}$ .

Remark 4.10. The set $X_{\mathsf {N}_n}=\dot n$ is the canonical name for $n\in \omega $ , and $X_{\mathsf {N}}=\dot \omega =\{\langle {\bar n,\bar n, \dot n}\rangle \mid n\in \omega \}$ is the canonical name for $\omega $ .

Lemma 4.11 (Absoluteness and uniqueness up to extensional equality).

Let $\sigma \sim \tau $ and $a,b$ of type $\sigma $ . Then:

  • $\Vdash a^{\sigma }=b^{\tau }$ implies $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ ;

  • $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ implies $a^{\sigma }=b^{\tau }$ .

Proof By induction on the (inductive definition of the) type structure. The cases $\sigma =\tau =\mathsf {N}_n$ and $\sigma =\tau =\mathsf {N}$ are straightforward.

Let $\alpha ={\Pi }_{\sigma } i\sim {\Pi }_{\tau } j=\gamma $ and $f,g\in A_{\alpha }$ . Recall that:

$$ \begin{align*} f^{\alpha}&=\{\langle{a,b,\langle{a^{\sigma},(fa)^{ia}}\rangle_{\!A}}\rangle\mid a\sim_{\sigma} b\};\\ g^{\gamma}&=\{\langle{a,b,\langle{a^{\tau},(ga)^{ja}}\rangle_{\!A}}\rangle\mid a\sim_{\tau} b\}. \end{align*} $$

Suppose $\Vdash f^{\alpha }=g^{\gamma }$ . Let us show that $f\sim _{\alpha } g$ . Let $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ . We want to prove $fa\sim _{\rho } gb$ , where $\rho =ia$ . By definition of realizability, we have that

$$\begin{align*}\Vdash \langle{a^{\sigma},(fa)^{\rho}}\rangle_{\!A}=\langle{\breve{a}^{\tau},(g\breve{a})^{\eta}}\rangle_{\!A}, \end{align*}$$

for some $\breve {a}\in A_{\tau }$ , where $\eta =j\breve {a}$ . Then $\Vdash a^{\sigma }=\breve a^{\tau }$ and $\Vdash (fa)^{\rho }=(g\breve a)^{\eta }$ . By induction, $a\sim _{\sigma } \breve a$ and $fa\sim _{\rho } g\breve a$ . By Lemma 4.5, $\breve a\sim _{\sigma } b$ . Hence, $\breve a\sim _{\tau } b$ , and therefore $g\breve a\sim _{\eta } gb$ . Since $i\approx _{\sigma } j$ , it also follows from $a\sim _{\sigma } \breve a$ that $\rho \sim \eta $ . Thus $g\breve a\sim _{\rho } gb$ . By transitivity, $fa\sim _{\rho } gb$ .

Now suppose $f\sim _{\alpha } g$ . We wish to show that $f^{\alpha }=g^{\gamma }$ . Since $\sigma \sim \tau $ , it suffices to show that if $a\in A_{\sigma }$ , then $a^{\sigma }=a^{\tau }$ and $(fa)^{ia}=(ga)^{ja}$ . This follows by induction since $\sigma \sim \tau $ , $a\sim _{\sigma } a$ , $ia\sim ja$ , and $fa\sim _{ia} ga$ .

The cases ${\Sigma }_{\sigma } i$ , $\mathrm {I}_{\sigma }(a,b)$ and $\mathrm {W}_{\sigma } i$ are left as an exercise.

By virtue of Lemmas 4.5 and 4.11, every $X_{\sigma }$ is injectively presented in the following sense.

Definition 4.12. A set $x\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ is injectively presented if

$$\begin{align*}x=\{\langle{a,b,f(a)}\rangle\mid a\sim b\}, \end{align*}$$

where $\sim $ is a partial equivalence relation on A and f is a (definable) function from the domain of $\sim $ to $\mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ such that:

  • $\Vdash f(a)=f(b)$ implies $a\sim b$ ;

  • $a\sim b$ implies $f(a)=f(b)$ .

This property will ensure the validity of choice for names of the form $X_{\sigma }$ (see Theorem 4.17).

Lemma 4.13. Let $\sigma \sim \tau $ and $i\approx _{\sigma } j$ . Then $X_{\sigma }=X_{\tau }$ and $F_{\sigma ,i}=F_{\tau ,j}$ .

Proof By Lemma 4.11.

Theorem 4.14. There are closed terms such that:

(i) $$ \begin{align} \mathbf o&\Vdash X_{\mathsf{N}}=\omega; \end{align} $$
(ii) $$ \begin{align} \mathbf{fun}&\Vdash \operatorname{{\mathrm{Fun}}}(F_{\sigma,i})\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{dom}}}(F_{\sigma,i}) = X_{\sigma}; \end{align} $$
(iii) $$ \begin{align} \mathbf{prod}&\Vdash X_{{\Pi}_{\sigma} i}={\Pi}(X_{\sigma}, F_{\sigma,i}); \end{align} $$
(iv) $$ \begin{align} \mathbf{sum}&\Vdash X_{{\Sigma}_{\sigma} i}={\Sigma}(X_{\sigma}, F_{\sigma,i}); \end{align} $$
(v) $$ \begin{align} \mathbf{id}&\Vdash X_{\mathrm{I}_{\sigma}(a,b)}=\mathrm{I}(a^{\sigma},b^{\sigma}); \end{align} $$
(vi) $$ \begin{align} \mathbf w&\Vdash X_{\mathrm{W}_{\sigma} i}=\mathrm{W}(X_{\sigma},F_{\sigma,i}), \end{align} $$

where $\sigma $ is a type, i is a family of types over $\sigma $ , and $a,b$ have type $\sigma $ .

Remark 4.15. $\mathsf {CZF}$ proves (i)–(v) for ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}$ -types. $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {REA}$ proves (i)–(vi) for ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}$ -types.

Theorem 4.16. There are closed terms $\mathbf i$ and ${\mathbf e}$ such that:

$$\begin{align*}c=d\Vdash X\in {\Pi}{\Sigma}\mathrm{I} \ \ \text{implies} \ \ \sigma=\mathbf ic\sim\mathbf id\ \ \text{and}\ \ \mathbf ec={\mathbf e} d\Vdash X=X_{\sigma}, \end{align*}$$

for every $X\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ . The same for ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}$ .

We prove Theorems 4.14 and 4.16 in Section 6.

4.3 Realizing choice

Theorem 4.17 ( $\mathsf {AC}_{\sigma ,\tau }$ ).

There is a closed term ${\mathbf e}$ such that $\mathsf {CZF}$ proves

$$\begin{align*}{\mathbf e} \Vdash \forall x\in X_{\sigma}\, \exists y\in X_{\tau}\, \varphi(x,y)\rightarrow \exists f\colon X_{\sigma}\to X_{\tau}\, \forall x\in X_{\sigma}\, \varphi(x,f(x)), \end{align*}$$

for all ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}$ -types $\sigma ,\tau $ and for every formula $\varphi $ . The same for $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {REA}$ and ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}$ -types.

Proof Suppose $c=d\Vdash \forall x\in X_{\sigma }\, \exists y\in X_{\tau }\, \varphi (x,y)$ . Then, whenever $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ , we have $(ca)_0\sim _{\tau } (db)_0$ and $(ca)_1=(db)_1\Vdash \varphi (a^{\sigma },e^{\tau })$ , where $e=(ca)_0$ . Let

$$\begin{align*}f=\{\langle{a,b,\langle{a^{\sigma},e^{\tau}}\rangle_{\!A}}\rangle\mid a\sim_{\sigma} b\land e=(ca)_0\}. \end{align*}$$

Then $f\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ . We wish to find ${\mathbf e}$ such that

$$\begin{align*}{\mathbf e} c=\mathbf ed\Vdash f\colon X_{\sigma}\to X_{\tau}\land \forall x\in X_{\sigma}\, \varphi(x,f(x)). \end{align*}$$

It suffices to look for closed terms $\mathbf {r},\mathbf {c},\mathbf {f}$ such that:

(1) $$ \begin{align} \mathbf{r}c = \mathbf{r}d \Vdash f\subseteq X_{\sigma}\times X_{\tau}, \qquad\qquad\qquad\qquad\qquad\qquad \end{align} $$
(2) $$ \begin{align} \mathbf cc = \mathbf cd \Vdash \forall x\in X_{\sigma}\, \exists y\, \exists z\in f\, (\operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z,x,y)\land \varphi(x,y)), \end{align} $$
(3) $$ \begin{align} \mathbf fc = \mathbf fd \Vdash f \text{ is functional}, \qquad\qquad\qquad\qquad\qquad\quad \ \ \end{align} $$

where $f\subseteq X_{\sigma }\times X_{\tau }$ stands for $\forall z\in f\, \exists x\in X_{\sigma }\, \exists y\in X_{\tau }\, \operatorname {{\mathrm {OP}}}(z,x,y)$ , and f is functional stands for

$$\begin{align*}\forall z_0\in f\, \forall z_1\in f\, \forall x\, \forall y_0\, \forall y_1\, (\operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z_0,x,y_0)\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z_1,x,y_1)\rightarrow y_0=y_1). \end{align*}$$

(1) and (2) are straightforward. (3) Let $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ and $\breve a\sim _{\sigma } \breve b$ . We want

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf fca\breve a=\mathbf fd b\breve b\Vdash \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(\langle{a^{\sigma},e^{\tau}}\rangle_{\!A},x,y_0)\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(\langle{\breve a^{\sigma},\breve e^{\tau}}\rangle_{\!A},x,y_1)\rightarrow y_0=y_1, \end{align*}$$

for all $x,y_0,y_1\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ , where $e=(ca)_0$ and $\breve e=(c\breve a)_0$ . Suppose

$$\begin{align*}\breve c=\breve d\Vdash \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(\langle{a^{\sigma},e^{\tau}}\rangle_{\!A},x,y_0)\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(\langle{\breve a^{\sigma},\breve e^{\tau}}\rangle_{\!A},x,y_1). \end{align*}$$

In particular, $\Vdash a^{\sigma }=\breve a^{\sigma }$ . By Lemma 4.11, $a\sim _{\sigma } \breve a$ . By Lemma 4.5, since $(ca)_0\sim _{\tau } (da)_0$ and $(c\breve a)_0\sim _{\tau } (da)_0$ , it follows that $(ca)_0\sim _{\tau } (c\breve a)_0$ . That is, $e\sim _{\tau } \breve e$ . By Lemma 4.11 again, we get $e^{\tau }=\breve e^{\tau }$ . By the properties of equality, there is a closed term $\mathbf q$ such that $\mathbf q\breve c=\mathbf q\breve d\Vdash y_0=y_1$ . We may let $\mathbf f=_{\mathrm {def}}\lambda ca\breve a\breve c. \mathbf q\breve c$ .

Theorem 4.18 ( $\mathsf {RDC}_{\sigma }$ ).

There is a closed term ${\mathbf e}$ such that $\mathsf {CZF}$ proves

$$ \begin{align*} {\mathbf e} \Vdash \forall x\in X_{\sigma}\, &(\psi(x)\rightarrow \exists y\in X_{\sigma}\, (\psi(x)\land \varphi(x,y))) \rightarrow \forall x\in X_{\sigma}\, (\psi(x)\rightarrow \\ &\qquad\qquad\qquad\exists f\colon \omega\to X_{\sigma}\, (f(0)=x\land \forall n\in\omega\, \varphi(f(n),f(n+1)))), \end{align*} $$

for every ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}$ -type $\sigma $ and for every formula $\varphi $ . The same for $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {REA}$ and ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}$ -types.

Proof Suppose

(1) $$ \begin{align} c=d\Vdash \forall x\in X_{\sigma}\, (\psi(x)\rightarrow \exists y\in X_{\sigma}\, (\psi(y)\land \varphi(x,y))), \end{align} $$

$\mathring a\sim _{\sigma } \mathring b$ and $\mathring c=\mathring d\Vdash \psi (a^{\sigma })$ . We search for ${\mathbf e}$ such that

$$\begin{align*}{\mathbf e} c\mathring a\mathring c=\mathbf ed\mathring b\mathring d\Vdash \exists f \colon \omega\to X_{\sigma}\, (f(0)=\mathring a^{\sigma}\land \forall n\in\omega\, \varphi(f(n),f(n+1))). \end{align*}$$

By (1), whenever $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ and $\breve c=\breve d\Vdash \psi (a^{\sigma })$ , we have

(2) $$ \begin{align} e=(ca\breve c)_0\sim_{\sigma} (d b\breve d)_0, \end{align} $$
(3) $$ \begin{align} (ca\breve c)_1= (db\breve d)_1\Vdash \psi(e^{\sigma})\land \varphi(a^{\sigma}, e^{\sigma}). \end{align} $$

In every pca one can simulate primitive recursion. We thus have a closed term $\mathbf r$ satisfying the following equations, where r is an abbreviation for $\mathbf rc\mathring a\mathring c$ :

$$ \begin{align*} r\mathbf 0&\simeq \mathbf p \mathring a(\mathbf p\mathring c\mathbf 0);\\ r\overline{n+1}&\simeq \mathbf p (c(r\bar n)_0(r\bar n)_{10} )_0 (c(r\bar n)_0(r\bar n)_{10})_1. \end{align*} $$

By induction, owing to (2) and (3), one can verify that for every $n\in \omega $ ,

$$\begin{align*}a_n=(\mathbf rc\mathring a\mathring c \bar n)_0\sim_{\sigma} (\mathbf rd\mathring b\mathring d \bar n)_0=b_n, \end{align*}$$
$$\begin{align*}(\mathbf rc\mathring{a}\mathring{c}\: \overline{n+1})_1= (\mathbf rd\mathring b\mathring{d}\: \overline{n+1})_1\Vdash \psi(a_n^{\sigma})\land \varphi(a_n^{\sigma},a_{n+1}^{\sigma}). \end{align*}$$

Note that $\mathring a=(\mathbf rc\mathring a\mathring c \mathbf 0)_0\sim _{\sigma } (\mathbf rd\mathring b\mathring d \mathbf 0)_0=\mathring b$ , and $\mathring c=(\mathbf rc\mathring a\mathring c \mathbf 0)_{10}= (\mathbf rd\mathring b\mathring d \bar 0)_{10}=\mathring d \Vdash \psi (\mathring a^{\sigma })$ . Let

$$\begin{align*}f=\{\langle{\bar n,\bar n,\langle{\dot n,a_n^{\sigma}}\rangle_{\!A}}\rangle\mid n\in\omega\land a_n=(\mathbf rc\mathring a\mathring c \bar n)_0\}. \end{align*}$$

Then $f\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ . By using $\mathbf r$ , it is not difficult to build ${\mathbf e}$ such that

$$\begin{align*}{\mathbf e} c\mathring a\mathring c=\mathbf ed\mathring b\mathring d\Vdash f \colon \omega\to X_{\sigma}\land f(0)=\mathring a^{\sigma}\land \forall n\in\omega\, \varphi(f(n),f(n+1)).\\[-2.8pc] \end{align*}$$

Theorem 4.19. There is a closed term $\mathbf c$ such that $\mathsf {CZF}$ proves $\mathbf c\Vdash \chi $ , for every instance $\chi $ of ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}^{\dagger }$ . The same for ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {RDC}^{\dagger }$ . Similarly, there is a closed term $\mathbf c$ such that $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {REA}$ proves $\mathbf c\Vdash \chi $ , for every instance $\chi $ of ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}^{\dagger }$ . The same for ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {RDC}^{\dagger }$ .

Proof By Theorems 4.164.18.

Corollary 4.20. It thus follows by Theorem 3.19 that:

  1. (i) $T\models T+{\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}^{\dagger }+{\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf { RDC}^{\dagger }$ ,

  2. (ii) $T+\mathsf {REA}\models T+\mathsf {REA}+{\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf { AC}^{\dagger }+{\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {RDC}^{\dagger }$ ,

for every theory T obtained by appending to either $\mathsf {CZF}$ or $\mathsf {IZF}$ some or all of the axioms $\mathsf { AC}_{\omega }$ , $\mathsf {DC}$ , $\mathsf {DC}^{\dagger }$ , $\mathsf {RDC}$ , $\mathsf {RDC}^{\dagger }$ , and $\mathsf {PAx}$ .

4.4 Failure of presentation

The interpretations of $\mathsf {CZF}$ and $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {REA}$ in type theory validate strong presentation axioms (see Section 2.5). It is natural to ask whether extensional generic realizability validates the statement that every set is an image of a ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}$ -set, even under the assumption that this holds in the background universe. If it did, in view of Theorems 2.16 and 4.19, we would obtain that $T+\text {every set is an image of a } {\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-set} \models {\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {PAx}$ , and similarly for $T+\mathsf {REA}$ and ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}$ -sets. However, the answer is negative.

Theorem 4.21. The following holds.

$$\begin{align*}\mathsf{CZF}\models\text{there is a set that is not an image of a } {\Pi}{\Sigma}\mathrm{I}\text{-set}. \end{align*}$$

Similarly for $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {REA}$ and ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}$ -sets.

Proof Let $y=\{\langle {\mathbf 0,\mathbf 0,\dot 0}\rangle ,\langle {\mathbf 0,\mathbf 0,\dot 1}\rangle \}\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ . Although y is in bijection with $2=\{0,1\}$ , this fact is not realizable. The proof is the same in both cases. Let us consider the ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}$ case and show that

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf 0\Vdash \neg \exists X\, \exists f\, (X\in{\Pi}{\Sigma}\mathrm{I}\land f\colon X \twoheadrightarrow y). \end{align*}$$

Towards a contradiction, suppose $\Vdash X\in {\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\land f\colon X \twoheadrightarrow y$ , for some $X,f\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ . By soundness and Theorem 4.16, there is a ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}$ -type $\sigma $ such that $\Vdash f\colon X_{\sigma } \twoheadrightarrow y$ . In particular, there are $a,b$ such that

$$\begin{align*}a=b\Vdash \forall v\in y\, \exists x\in X_{\sigma}\, \exists z\in f\, \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z,x,v). \end{align*}$$

By unpacking the definition, we must have $\breve a= (a\mathbf 0)_0\sim _{\sigma }(b\mathbf 0)_0=\breve b$ and

$$\begin{align*}\Vdash \exists z\in f\, \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z,x,\dot 0)\land \exists z\in f\, \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z,x,\dot 1), \end{align*}$$

where $x=\breve a^{\sigma }$ . From $\Vdash \operatorname {{\mathrm {Fun}}}(f)$ , we then obtain $\Vdash \dot 0=\dot 1$ , which implies $0=1$ , for the desired contradiction.

5 Far beyond Goodman’s theorem

Goodman [Reference Goodman18, Reference Goodman19] proved that intuitionistic finite type arithmetic $\mathsf {HA}^{\omega }$ augmented with the axiom of choice in all finite types $\mathsf {AC}_{\mathsf {FT}}$ is conservative over $\mathsf {HA}$ . This still holds in the presence of extensionality, that is, $\mathsf {HA}^{\omega }+\mathsf {EXT}+\mathsf {AC_{\mathsf {FT}}}$ is conservative over $\mathsf {HA}$ (cf. [Reference Beeson6, Reference Beeson7]). Since $\mathsf {HA}^{\omega }$ and $\mathsf {HA}^{\omega } +\mathsf {EXT}$ are easily seen to be conservative over $\mathsf{HA}$ (via the models ${\mathsf{HRO}}$ and $\mathsf {HEO}$ respectively; cf. [Reference Troelstra32]), Goodman’s theorem is the prototypical example of arithmetical conservativity of (some) choice over a given theory T. Goodman-type results have been proved for a variety of set theories and choice principles at finite types. Write $T=_{arith}S$ to convey that T and S prove the same arithmetic sentences.

Theorem 5.1. This much (as a minimum) is known:

  • $T =_{arith}T+\mathsf {CAC}_{\mathsf {FT}}+{\mathsf {DC}}_{\mathsf {FT}}$ for $T=\mathsf {IZF}$ and extensions of $\mathsf {IZF}$ by large set axioms; see [Reference Friedman and Ščedrov15, Theorem 5.1];

  • $T =_{arith}T+\mathsf {AC}_{\mathsf {FT}}$ for $T=\mathsf {CZF}$ and fragments thereof; see [Reference Gordeev20, p. 25].

We are going to further extend such results and in particular make good on the claim in [Reference Frittaion and Rathjen17] that extensional realizability may be used to show arithmetical conservativity of $\mathsf {AC}_{\mathsf {FT}}$ over $\mathsf {IZF}$ (as well as $\mathsf {CZF}$ ).

Theorem 5.2. Let T be any of the theories obtained by appending to either $\mathsf {CZF}$ or $\mathsf {IZF}$ some or all of the axioms $\mathsf { AC}_{\omega }$ , $\mathsf {DC}$ , $\mathsf {DC}^{\dagger }$ , $\mathsf {RDC}$ , $\mathsf {RDC}^{\dagger }$ , and $\mathsf {PAx}$ . Then:

  • $T =_{arith}T+{\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}^{\dagger }+{\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {RDC}^{\dagger } $ ;

  • $T +\mathsf {REA} =_{arith}T+\mathsf {REA}+{\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}^{\dagger }+ {\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {RDC}^{\dagger }$ .

One can allow type $1$ parameters. Namely, we have conservativity for sentences of the form

$$\begin{align*}\forall f_1\in\omega^{\omega}\cdots \forall f_n\in\omega^{\omega}\, \varphi(f_1,\ldots,f_n), \end{align*}$$

where $\varphi $ is arithmetic (relative to $f_1,\ldots ,f_n$ ).

Remark 5.3. Of course, some of the theories to the left reduce to $T+{\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}^{\dagger }$ and $T+\mathsf { REA}+{\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}^{\dagger }$ respectively.

Friedman and Ščedrov’s [Reference Friedman and Ščedrov15] versions of generic realizability and forcing only work for set theories without extensionality. We show how to adapt the argument to an extensional setting. Definition 5.4 fully specifies our forcing relation. It is a routine although tedious matter to check all the details. By the way, one should also prove that every theory T as above is self-validating with respect to forcing. This is not difficult to see.

It is convenient to work in a conservative extension S of T obtained by adding the constant symbol $\omega $ and an axiom saying that $\omega $ is the set of natural numbers.Footnote 7 Now, we can clearly identify number quantifiers with bounded quantifiers of the form $\forall x\in \omega $ and $\exists x\in \omega $ . On the other hand, every primitive recursive number-theoretic function and hence relation is canonically definable by a $\Sigma $ formula in the language of set theory (with just $\in $ as primitive).Footnote 8 We call such formulas primitive recursive. Kleene’s T-predicate $T(e,x,z)$ and the function $U(z)$ are among them. We then say that a formula is arithmetic if it is built up from primitive recursive formulas by using $\land $ , $\lor $ , $\neg $ , $\rightarrow $ , and number quantifiers $\forall x\in \omega $ and $\exists x\in \omega $ .

Proof of Theorem 5.2

We first consider the case without parameters. The goal is to show that for every arithmetic sentence $\varphi $ of S,

  • if $S+\Phi \vdash \varphi $ , then $S\vdash \varphi $ ,

  • if $S+\mathsf {REA}+\Psi \vdash \varphi $ , then $S+\mathsf {REA}\vdash \varphi $ ,

where $\Phi ={\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}^{\dagger }+{\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {RDC}^{\dagger }$ and $\Psi ={\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf {AC}^{\dagger }+{\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}\text {-}\mathsf { RDC}^{\dagger }$ .

Step 1. Let $S^g$ be the theory obtained from S by adjoining a new constant symbol g and an axiom saying the g is a partial function from $\omega $ to $\omega $ . Within $S^g$ , one can define extensional generic realizability $a=b\Vdash _{\omega } \varphi $ , where $a,b\in \omega $ and $\varphi $ is a formula of T with parameters in $\mathrm {V_{ext}}(\omega )$ , by using partial recursive application relative to the generic oracle g. To be precise, we use Kleene’s relativized T-predicate $T(e,x,z,f)$ , where f is a partial function from $\omega $ to $\omega $ . So, for example, the clause for implication reads as follows:

$$ \begin{align*} a=b&\Vdash_{\omega} \varphi\rightarrow\psi && \Leftrightarrow && \forall c,d\in\omega \, (c=d\Vdash_{\omega} \varphi\rightarrow \{a\}^g(c)=\{b\}^g(d)\Vdash_{\omega} \psi). \end{align*} $$

For $\land $ and $\lor $ , we may use a primitive recursive pairing function $(n,m)$ on natural numbers with primitive recursive projections $(n)_0$ and $(n)_1$ . So, for example, we let

$$ \begin{align*} a=b& \Vdash_{\omega} \varphi\land \psi && \Leftrightarrow && (a)_0=(b)_0\Vdash_{\omega} \varphi \land (a)_1=(b)_1\Vdash_{\omega} \psi. \end{align*} $$

One can lift the realizability interpretation to every formula $\varphi $ of S by interpreting $\omega $ with $\dot \omega \in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(\omega )$ . Here, $\dot \omega =\{\langle {n,n,\dot n}\rangle \mid n\in \omega \}$ , where $\dot n=\{\langle {m,m,\dot m}\rangle \mid m\in n\}$ .

One proves that

(1) $$ \begin{align} \text{if } S+\Phi\vdash\varphi, \text{ then } S^g\vdash \exists e\in\omega\, (e\Vdash_{\omega} \varphi). \end{align} $$

Similarly for $S+\mathsf {REA}+\Psi $ and $(S+\mathsf {REA})^g$ . This concludes the realizability part.

Step 2. Next, within S, given any definable set $\mathbb {P}$ of partial functions from $\omega $ to $\omega $ such that $0\in \mathbb {P}$ , one defines a forcing interpretation $p\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \varphi $ , where $p\in \mathbb {P}$ and $\varphi $ is a formula of T with parameters in $\mathrm {V}(\mathbb {P})$ . The universe $\mathrm {V}(\mathbb {P})$ is inductively defined by the clause:

  • if $x\subseteq \mathbb {P}\times \mathrm {V}(\mathbb {P})$ and $\langle {q,z}\rangle \in x$ whenever $\langle {p,z}\rangle \in x$ with $q\supseteq p$ , then $x\in \mathrm {V}(\mathbb {P})$ .

In $\mathrm {V}(\mathbb {P})$ , we have a canonical name $\mathring g$ for the generic g defined as

$$\begin{align*}\mathring g=\{ \langle{p,\langle{\check n,\check m}\rangle_{\mathbb{P}}}\rangle\mid p\in \mathbb{P}\land \langle{n,m}\rangle\in p\}, \end{align*}$$

where $\check n=\{\langle {p,\check m}\rangle \mid p\in \mathbb {P}\land m\in n\}$ , and $\langle {x,y}\rangle _{\mathbb {P}}$ is some suitable pairing function in $\mathrm {V}(\mathbb {P})$ . In particular, every natural number $n\in \omega $ has a canonical name $\check n$ in $\mathrm {V}(\mathbb {P})$ . A canonical name $\check \omega $ for $\omega $ is given by $ \check \omega =\{\langle {p,\check n}\rangle \mid p\in \mathbb {P}\land n\in \omega \}$ .

One can then extend the forcing interpretation $p\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \varphi $ to formulas of $S^g$ by interpreting g with $\mathring g$ and $\omega $ with $\check \omega $ . The basic idea however is that $p\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} g(\check n)=\check m$ iff $\langle {n,m}\rangle \in p$ . Moreover,

  • if $\{e\}^p(a)\simeq b$ , then $p\Vdash \{\check e\}^g(\check a)\simeq \check b$ ,

  • if $p\Vdash \{\check e\}^g(\check a)\simeq \check b$ , then for every $q\supseteq p$ , there is an $r\supseteq q$ such that $\{e\}^r(a)\simeq b$ .

Then one shows that

(2) $$ \begin{align} \text{if } S^g\vdash \varphi, \text{ then } S\vdash \forall p\, \exists q\supseteq p\, (q\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}}\varphi). \end{align} $$

Similarly for $S^g+\mathsf {REA}$ and $S+\mathsf {REA}$ . In particular, we must have that

$$\begin{align*}S\vdash \forall p\, \exists q\supseteq p\, (q\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \omega \text{ is the set of natural numbers}), \text{ and} \end{align*}$$
$$\begin{align*}S\vdash \forall p\, \exists q\supseteq p\, (q\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} g \text{ is a partial function from } \omega \text{ to } \omega). \end{align*}$$

Moreover, forcing is absolute for arithmetic sentences, namely,

(3) $$ \begin{align} S\vdash \forall p\, (\varphi\leftrightarrow (p\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}}\varphi)), \end{align} $$

for every arithmetic sentence $\varphi $ of S. This is the forcing part.

Finally, one shows that if $\varphi $ is an arithmetic sentence, then there exists a forcing notion $\mathbb {P}$ such that

(4) $$ \begin{align} S\vdash \forall p\, (p\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \forall a,b\in\omega\, ((a=b\Vdash_{\omega} \varphi)\rightarrow \varphi)). \end{align} $$

Step 3. By putting all together, the arguments run as follows. If $S+\Phi \vdash \varphi $ , with $\varphi $ arithmetic, let $\mathbb {P}$ be as in (4). By (1), $S^g\vdash \exists e\in \omega \, (e\Vdash _{\omega }\varphi )$ . By (2), $S\vdash \forall p\, \exists q\supseteq p\, (q\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \exists e\in \omega \, (e\Vdash _{\omega }\varphi ))$ . We now reason in S. By the soundness of forcing and (4), we can find $p\in \mathbb {P}$ such that $p\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \varphi $ . By (3), we finally obtain $\varphi $ .

Definition 5.4 (Forcing).

We define the relation $p\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \varphi $ , where $p\in \mathbb {P}$ and $\varphi $ is a formula of T with parameters in $\mathrm {V}(\mathbb {P})$ . The atomic cases are defined by transfinite recursion.

$$ \begin{align*} p &\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} x\in y && \Leftrightarrow && \exists z\in\mathrm{V}(\mathbb{P})\, (\langle{p,z}\rangle\in y\land p\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} x=z), \\ p & \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} x=y && \Leftrightarrow && \forall \langle q,z\rangle \in x\, (q\supseteq p\rightarrow \exists r\supseteq q\, (r\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} z\in y)) \text{ and } \\ &&&&& \forall \langle q,z\rangle \in y\, (q\supseteq p\rightarrow \exists r\supseteq q\, (r\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} z\in x)),\\ p& \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \varphi\land \psi && \Leftrightarrow && p\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \varphi \land p\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \psi, \\ p & \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \varphi\lor\psi && \Leftrightarrow && p\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \varphi \lor p\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \psi, \\ p &\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \neg\varphi && \Leftrightarrow && \forall q\supseteq p\, \neg (q\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \varphi), \\ p &\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \varphi\rightarrow\psi && \Leftrightarrow && \forall q\supseteq p\, (q\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \varphi\rightarrow \exists r\supseteq q\, (r\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \psi)), \\ p& \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \forall x\in y\, \varphi && \Leftrightarrow && \forall \langle{q,x}\rangle\in y\, (q\supseteq p\rightarrow \exists r\supseteq q\, (r\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \varphi)), \\ p &\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \exists x\in y\, \varphi && \Leftrightarrow && \exists x\in\mathrm{V}(\mathbb{P})\, (\langle{p,x}\rangle\in y\land p\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \varphi),\\ p& \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \forall x\, \varphi && \Leftrightarrow && \forall x\in\mathrm{V}(\mathbb{P})\, \forall q\supseteq p\, \exists r\supseteq q\, (r\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \varphi), \\ p & \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \exists x\, \varphi && \Leftrightarrow && \exists x\in\mathrm{V}(\mathbb{P})\, (p\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \varphi). \end{align*} $$

Forcing is monotone, that is, if $p\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \varphi $ and $q\supseteq p$ , then $q\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \varphi $ .

All the ingredients are in place to carry out a proof of (1)–(4). Here we give some clues.

On absoluteness

For every set x, define by transfinite recursion the name $\check x\in \mathrm {V}(\mathbb {P})$ by $\check x=\{\langle {p,\check y}\rangle \mid p\in \mathbb {P} \land y\in x\}$ . We set out to prove that for every arithmetic formula $\varphi (x_1,\ldots ,x_n)$ ,

(5) $$ \begin{align} S\vdash \forall x_1\in\omega \cdots \forall x_n\in\omega \, \forall p\, (\varphi(x_1,\ldots,x_n)\leftrightarrow p\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \varphi(\check x_1,\ldots,\check x_n)). \end{align} $$

The absoluteness of arithmetic sentences in the sense of (3) then follows.

It is an easy exercise to show that (5) is preserved under logical connectives and number quantifiers. It is thus sufficient to show that for every primitive recursive function $f(x_1,\ldots ,x_n)$ , the primitive recursive formula $\varphi _f(x_1,\ldots ,x_n,y)$ defining f satisfies (5). This is proved by (an external) induction on the generation of f.

For example, suppose $f(x_1,\ldots ,x_n,x)$ is defined by primitive recursion from $g(x_1,\ldots ,x_n)$ and $h(x_1,\ldots ,x_n,x,y)$ , namely,

$$ \begin{align*} f(x_1,\ldots,x_n,0)&=g(x_1,\ldots,x_n);\\ f(x_1,\ldots,x_n,x+1)&=h(x_1,\ldots,x_n,x,f(x_1,\ldots,x_n,x)). \end{align*} $$

Define $\varphi _f(x_1,\ldots ,x_n,x,y)$ as $\exists z\, (\psi (z) \land z(x)=y)$ , where $\psi (z)$ is

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{{\mathrm{Fun}}}(z)&\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{dom}}}(z) \in\omega \land (0\in\operatorname{{\mathrm{dom}}}(z)\rightarrow \varphi_g(x_1,\ldots,x_n,z(0))) \\ &\land \forall n\in\operatorname{{\mathrm{dom}}}(z)\, \forall m\in n\, (n=m+1\rightarrow \varphi_h(x_1,\ldots,x_n,n,z(m),z(n))). \end{align*} $$

(Note that $\varphi _f$ is equivalent to a $\Sigma $ formula if $\varphi _g$ and $\varphi _h$ are also $\Sigma $ definable.) One shows that (5) holds for $\varphi _f(x_1,\ldots ,x_n,x,y)$ , by assuming that it holds for $\varphi _g$ and $\varphi _h$ . The left-to-right direction of (5) requires some standard absoluteness arguments. For the right-to-left direction, one also uses the fact that, for every primitive recursive function $f(x_1,\ldots ,x_n)$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} S&\vdash \forall x_1\in\omega\cdots \forall x_n\in\omega\, (\exists y\in\omega \, \varphi_f(x_1,\ldots,x_n,y) \\ & \qquad \land \forall y_0\, \forall y_1\, (\varphi_f(x_1,\ldots,x_n,y_0)\land \varphi_f(x_1,\ldots,x_n,y_1)\rightarrow y_0=y_1)), \end{align*} $$

and thereby this is forced in S.

On forcing self-realizability

To obtain (4), one shows that for every arithmetic formula $\varphi (x_1,\ldots ,x_n)$ there is a $\mathbb {P}$ such that S proves:

  1. (i) there is $e\in \omega $ such that for every p there is a $q\supseteq p$ forcing

    $$ \begin{align*} & \forall a_1\in\omega\cdots\forall a_n\in\omega\, (\varphi(a_1,\ldots,a_n)\rightarrow \\ & \qquad\qquad\qquad \exists b\in\omega\, (\{\check e\}^g(a_1,\ldots,a_n,0)=b\land b\Vdash_{\omega} \varphi(\dot a_1,\ldots,\dot a_n))); \end{align*} $$
  2. (ii) for every p there is a $q\supseteq p$ forcing

    $$\begin{align*}\forall a_1\in\omega\cdots\forall a_n\in\omega\, \forall a,b\in\omega\, ((a=b\Vdash_{\omega} \varphi(\dot a_1,\ldots,\dot a_n))\rightarrow \varphi(a_1,\ldots,a_n)). \end{align*}$$

Here, $\{e\}^f(a,b)$ stands for $\{\{e\}^f(a)\}^f(b)$ , and so on and so forth. On a technical note, the dummy argument for $0$ is used to handle the case where $\varphi $ is closed.

Now, let $\varphi (x_1,\ldots ,x_n)$ be arithmetic. We define $\mathbb {P}$ as follows. First, let $\mathbb {Q}$ be the set of partial functions p from $\omega $ to $\omega $ such that $\operatorname {{\mathrm {dom}}}(p)$ is an image of a natural number. The point of this definition is just to make sure that, within $\mathsf {CZF}$ , the class $\mathbb {Q}$ exists as a set and the domain of every $p\in \mathbb {Q}$ is decidable, in the sense that

$$\begin{align*}\forall p\in\mathbb{Q}\, \forall x\in\omega\, (x\in\operatorname{{\mathrm{dom}}}(p)\lor x\notin\operatorname{{\mathrm{dom}}}(p)). \end{align*}$$

Note that if we are working in $\mathsf {IZF}$ , we can directly define the set $\mathbb {Q}$ of all partial functions from $\omega $ to $\omega $ with decidable domain. Enumerate all subformulas $\varphi _1,\ldots ,\varphi _k$ of $\varphi $ starting from the primitive recursive ones. Let $\mathbb {P}$ be the set of $p\in \mathbb {Q}$ such that for every subformula $\varphi _i(y_1,\ldots , y_{j}) $ of the form $\psi _0\lor \psi _1$ , for every $a_1,\ldots ,a_j\in \omega $ , if $a=(i,a_1,\ldots ,a_j)\in \operatorname {{\mathrm {dom}}}(p)$ , then $p(a)=0\land \psi _0(a_1,\ldots ,a_j)$ or $p(a)=1\land \psi _0(a_1,\ldots ,a_j)$ , and for every subformula $\varphi _i(y_1,\ldots ,y_j)$ of the form $\exists x\, \psi (x,y_1,\ldots ,y_j)$ , for every $a_1,\ldots ,a_j\in \omega $ , if $a=(i,a_1,\ldots ,a_j)\in \operatorname {{\mathrm {dom}}}(p)$ , then $\psi (p(a),a_1,\ldots ,a_j)$ .

One can write down a formula defining $\mathbb {P}$ as there are standard finitely many subformulas of $\varphi $ . Here, $(a_1,\ldots ,a_j)$ is a primitive recursive coding of sequences of natural numbers. One then shows (i) and (ii) for every subformula of $\varphi $ .

If $\varphi $ is primitive recursive, then one can find a number e such that

$$ \begin{align*} S^g\vdash \forall a_1,\ldots,a_n\in\omega (\varphi(a_1,\ldots,a_n) \leftrightarrow \{e\}^g(a_1,\ldots,a_n)\Vdash_{\omega} \varphi(\dot a_1,\ldots,\dot a_n)), \end{align*} $$

where we identify e with the corresponding numeral. This fact can be gleaned from [Reference McCarty22, Chapter 4, Theorem 2.6] in the case of $\mathsf {IZF}$ . The same holds for $\mathsf {CZF}$ [Reference Rathjen30, Proposition 8.5]. We can then use the soundness of forcing to get (i) and (ii).

The index of complex subformulas is computed according to the following table. Let i be the number of the given subformula according to our enumeration. Write $\vec {a}$ for the tuple $a_1,\ldots ,a_j$ .

$$ \begin{align*} \{e_{\varphi\land\psi}\}^f(\vec a,0)&\simeq (\{e_{\varphi}\}^f(\vec a,0),\{e_{\psi}\}^f(\vec a,0)), \\ \{e_{\varphi\lor\psi}\}^f(\vec a,0)&\simeq \begin{cases} \{e_{\varphi}\}^f(\vec a,0), & \text{if } f(i,\vec a)=0, \\ \{e_{\psi}\}^f(\vec a,0),& \text{if } f(i,\vec a)=1, \end{cases} \\ \{e_{\forall x\in\omega\, \varphi(x)}\}^f(\vec a,0,b)&\simeq \{e_{\varphi}\}^f(\vec a,b,0),\\ \{e_{\exists x\in\omega\, \varphi(x)}\}^f(\vec a,0)&\simeq (f(i,\vec a),\{e_{\varphi}\}^f(\vec a,f(i,\vec a),0)). \end{align*} $$

By way of example, let us illustrate how to obtain (i) in the existential case. For simplicity, suppose we have a subformula of the form $\exists y\in \omega \, \varphi (x,y)$ . We work in S. We have already found an index $e_{\varphi }$ for $\varphi $ . So, let e be such that

$$\begin{align*}\{e\}^f(a,0)\simeq (f(i,a),\{e_{\varphi}\}^f(a,f(i,a),0)). \end{align*}$$

Let $p\in \mathbb {P}$ . We search for a $q\supseteq p$ such that

$$\begin{align*}q\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \forall a\in\omega\, (\exists y\in\omega\, \varphi(a,y)\rightarrow \{\check e\}^g(a,0)\Vdash_{\omega} \exists y\in\omega\, \varphi(\dot a,y)). \end{align*}$$

Notice that, within $S^g$ ,

$$\begin{align*}(a=b\Vdash_{\omega} \exists x\in\omega\, \varphi(x)) \leftrightarrow \exists n\in\omega\, ((a)_0=(b)_0=n\land (a)_1=(b)_1\Vdash_{\omega} \varphi(\dot n)), \end{align*}$$

and thereby this is forced in S. It is then enough to find an extension $q\supseteq p$ such that

(1) $$ \begin{align} q&\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \forall a\in\omega\, (\exists y\in\omega\, \varphi(a,y)\rightarrow \exists c\in\omega\, \exists b\in\omega\, (\{\check e\}^g(a,0)\simeq c \notag \\ &\qquad\qquad\qquad\qquad\qquad\qquad\qquad \land (c)_0=b \land (c)_1\Vdash_{\omega} \varphi(\dot a,\dot b))). \end{align} $$

We claim that p already satisfies (1). Let $a\in \omega $ , $q\supseteq p$ , and suppose $q\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \exists y\in \omega \, \varphi (\check a,y)$ . We are clear if we find $r\supseteq q$ such that

(2) $$ \begin{align} r&\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \exists c\in\omega\, \exists b\in\omega\, (\{\check e\}^g(\check a,0)\simeq c\land (c)_0=b \notag \\ & \qquad\qquad \land \forall x\, (i(\check a,x)\rightarrow (c)_1\Vdash_{\omega} \varphi(x,\dot b))), \end{align} $$

where the formula $i(x,y)$ expresses that $y=\dot x$ for $x\in \omega $ . By definition, there is a $b\in \omega $ such that $q\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \varphi (\check a,\check b)$ . By absoluteness, $\varphi (a,b)$ holds. Now, we can decide whether $(i,a)\in \operatorname {{\mathrm {dom}}}(q)$ . If not, we can take $q'=q\cup \{\langle {(i,a),b}\rangle \}$ . By the assumption on $e_{\varphi }$ , there is an $s\supseteq q'$ such that

(3) $$ \begin{align} & s\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \exists c_1\in\omega\, (\{\check e_{\varphi}\}^g(\check a,\check b,0)\simeq c_1 \notag \\ & \qquad\qquad\qquad \land \forall x\, \forall y\, (i(\check a,x)\land i(\check b,y) \rightarrow c_1\Vdash_{\omega} \varphi(x,y))). \end{align} $$

One can see that $s\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \{\check e\}^g(\check a,0)\simeq (\check b,\{\check e_{\varphi }\}^g(\check a,\check b,0))$ . By (3) and soundness, one can finally find an $r\supseteq s$ satisfying (2), as desired.

Adding parameters

We briefly discuss how to generalize such conservation result to arithmetic formulas with type $1$ parameters. For example, suppose $S+\Phi \vdash \forall f\in \omega ^{\omega }\, \varphi (f)$ . Then $(S+\Phi )_f\vdash \varphi (f)$ , where, in general, $T_f$ is obtained from T by adjoining a constant symbol f and an axiom saying that f is a function from $\omega $ to $\omega $ . It clearly suffices to show that $S_f\vdash \varphi (f)$ . If we do so, then $S\vdash \forall f\in \omega ^{\omega }\, \varphi (f)$

Now consider the theory $(S_f)^g$ obtained from $S_f$ by further extending the language with a constant symbol g and an axiom saying that g is a partial function from $\omega $ to $\omega $ . Within $(S_f)^g$ , consider extensional generic realizability $a=b\Vdash _{\omega } \varphi $ , where $a,b\in \omega $ and $\varphi $ is a formula of $S_f$ , by using partial recursive application relative to the oracle $f\oplus g=\{\langle {2n,f(n)}\rangle \mid n\in \omega \}\cup \{\langle {2n+1,g(n)}\rangle \mid n\in \operatorname {{\mathrm {dom}}}(g)\}$ . Use the name $\dot f=\{\langle {n,n,\langle {\dot n,\dot m}\rangle _{\omega }}\rangle \mid f(n)=m\}\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(\omega )$ to define realizability on formulas containing f. Note that we could extend the interpretation to every formula of $(S_f)^g$ by interpreting g with $\dot g$ , which is defined in a similar way as $\dot f$ . Show that

$$\begin{align*}\text{if } (S+\Phi)_f\vdash \psi, \text{ then } (S_f)^g\vdash \exists e\in\omega\, (e\Vdash_{\omega} \psi). \end{align*}$$

Similarly for $(S+\mathsf {REA}+\Psi )_f$ and $(S_f+\mathsf {REA})^g$ . In particular, we must have

$$\begin{align*}(S_f)^g\vdash \exists e\in\omega\, (e\Vdash_{\omega} f\colon\omega\to\omega). \end{align*}$$

This is the realizability part.

In $S_f$ , given any definable set $\mathbb {P}$ of partial functions from $\omega $ to $\omega $ , where now we can use the parameter f in defining $\mathbb {P}$ , we extend the forcing interpretation $p\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \varphi $ of Definition 5.4 to formulas of $(S_f)^g$ by interpreting g with $\mathring g$ , like before, and f with $\check f$ . Note that $\check f=\{\langle {p,\check z}\rangle \mid p\in \mathbb {P}\land z\in f\}=\{\langle {p,\langle {\check n,\check m}\rangle _{\mathbb {P}}}\rangle \mid p\in \mathbb {P}\land f(n)=m\}$ . The rest of the argument is roughly as before, but with everything relativized to the parameter f. In particular, one must show that arithmetic (in f) formulas are absolute for forcing. Finally, given $\varphi (f)$ , one defines $\mathbb {P}$ as before, but relative to f, and show that in $\mathrm {V}(\mathbb {P})$ , $\varphi (f)$ is self-realizing.⊣

6 Appendix

The proofs of Theorems 4.14 and 4.16 will rely on the following two facts.

Theorem 6.1 ( $\mathsf {CZF}$ ).

There is a formula $\vartheta (u,Y)$ , such that

$$\begin{align*}{\Pi}{\Sigma}\mathrm{I}=\{Y\mid \exists u\, \vartheta(u,Y)\}\ \ \text{and}\ \ \vartheta(u,Y)\leftrightarrow \bigvee_{i=0}^4 \vartheta_{i}(u,Y), \end{align*}$$

where

$$ \begin{align*} & \vartheta_0(u,Y) && \Leftrightarrow && Y\in\omega, \\ &\vartheta_1(u,Y) && \Leftrightarrow && Y=\omega, \\ &\vartheta_2(u,Y) && \Leftrightarrow && \exists X\, \exists F\, (\psi(u,X,F)\land Y={\Pi}(X,F)), \\ &\vartheta_3(u,Y) && \Leftrightarrow && \exists X\, \exists F\, (\psi(u,X,F)\land Y={\Sigma}(X,F)), \\ & \vartheta_4(u,Y) && \Leftrightarrow && \exists X\, (\exists v\in u\, \vartheta(v,X)\land \exists x\in X\, \exists y\in X\, (Y=\mathrm{I}(x,y))), \end{align*} $$

with $\psi (u,X,F)$ being a shorthand for

$$\begin{align*}\exists v\in u\, \vartheta(v,X)\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{Fun}}}(F) \land \operatorname{{\mathrm{dom}}}(F)=X\land \forall x\in X\, \exists v\in u\, \vartheta(v,F(x)). \end{align*}$$

Similarly, there is a formula $\vartheta ^*(u,Y)$ , such that

$$\begin{align*}{\Pi}{\Sigma}\mathrm{W}\mathrm{I}=\{Y\mid \exists u\, \vartheta^*(u,Y)\} \ \ \text{and}\ \ \vartheta^*(u,Y)\leftrightarrow \bigvee_{i=0}^5 \vartheta^*_{i}(u,Y), \end{align*}$$

where $\vartheta ^*_i$ for $i=0,\ldots ,4$ is defined in a similar fashion as $\vartheta _i$ , and

$$ \begin{align*} &\vartheta^*_5(u,Y) && \Leftrightarrow && \exists X\, \exists F\, (\exists v\in u\, \vartheta^*(v,X)\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{Fun}}}(F) \land \operatorname{{\mathrm{dom}}}(F)=X\land \\ &&&&& \forall x\in X\, \exists v\in u\, \vartheta^*(v,F(x))\land Y=\mathrm{W}(X,F)). \end{align*} $$

Theorem 6.2 ( $\mathsf {CZF}+\mathsf {REA}$ ).

If F is a function with domain X, then for every set Y,

$$ \begin{align*} Y&=\mathrm{W}(X,F) \leftrightarrow \forall y\, (y\in Y\leftrightarrow \exists x\in X\, \exists f\, (y=\langle{x,f}\rangle\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{Fun}}}(f)\land \\ & \qquad \qquad \operatorname{{\mathrm{dom}}}(f)=F(x)\land \forall u\in\operatorname{{\mathrm{dom}}}(f)\, (f(u)\in Y))). \end{align*} $$

Proof of Theorem 4.14

From now on, let

$$\begin{align*}F=F_{\sigma,i}=\{\langle{a,b,\langle{a^{\sigma},X_{\tau}}\rangle_{\!A}}\rangle\mid a\sim_{\sigma} b\land ia=\tau\}. \end{align*}$$

(i) A closed term $\mathbf o$ such that $\mathbf o\Vdash X_{\mathsf {N}}=\omega $ is given in the proof of Theorem 3.16. In fact, the set $X_{\mathsf {N}}=\dot \omega $ is the canonical name for $\omega $ used to realize infinity.

(ii) We aim for $\mathbf {fun}\Vdash \operatorname {{\mathrm {Fun}}}(F)\land \operatorname {{\mathrm {dom}}}(F) = X_{\sigma }$ . It suffices to look for closed terms $\mathbf r,\mathbf f, {\mathbf t}$ such that:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathbf r&\Vdash \forall z\in F\, \exists x\in X_{\sigma}\, \exists y\, \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z,x,y) \quad (\text{namely, } F\text{ is a relation }\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{dom}}}(F)\subseteq X_{\sigma}), \\ {\mathbf t}& \Vdash \forall x\in X_{\sigma}\, \exists y\, \exists z\in F\, \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z,x,y) \quad (\text{namely, } X_{\sigma}\subseteq \operatorname{{\mathrm{dom}}}(F)), \\ \mathbf f &\Vdash F \text{ is functional.} & \end{align*} $$

We can easily arrange for $\mathbf r$ and ${\mathbf t}$ . Let us find $\mathbf f$ . By unraveling the definition, we want $\mathbf f$ such that, if $a\sim _{\sigma } b $ , $\breve a\sim _{\sigma } \breve b$ and

$$\begin{align*}c=d\Vdash \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(\langle{a^{\sigma},X_{\tau}}\rangle_{\!A},x,y_0)\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(\langle{\breve a^{\sigma},X_{\breve\tau}}\rangle_{\!A},x,y_1), \end{align*}$$

where $ia=\tau $ and $i\breve a=\breve \tau $ , then $\mathbf fa\breve ac=\mathbf fb\breve bd\Vdash y_0=y_1$ . By the properties of pairing, from c and d as above we get $\Vdash a^{\sigma }=\breve a^{\sigma }$ . By Lemma 4.11, we must have $a\sim _{\sigma } \breve a$ . Since i is a family of types over $\sigma $ , $ia\sim i\breve a$ . That is, $\tau \sim \breve \tau $ . By Lemma 4.13, $X_{\tau }=X_{\breve \tau }$ . As in the proof of Theorem 4.17, by the properties of equality, there is a closed term $\mathbf q$ such that $\mathbf q c=\mathbf q d\Vdash y_0=y_1$ . We may let $\mathbf f=_{\mathrm {def}}\lambda a\breve ac. \mathbf q c$ .

(iii) We aim for $\mathbf {prod}\Vdash X_{{\Pi }_{\sigma } i}={\Pi }(X_{\sigma }, F)$ . We abbreviate

$$ \begin{align*} &\vartheta_r(f,X,F) && \Leftrightarrow && f\subseteq {\Sigma}(X,F)\\&&&\Leftrightarrow && \forall z\in f\, \exists x\in X\, \exists y\, \exists Z\in F\, \exists Y\, (\operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z,x,y)\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(Z,x,Y)\land y\in Y), \\&\vartheta_t(X,f) && \Leftrightarrow && X\subseteq\operatorname{{\mathrm{dom}}}(f) \\&&&\Leftrightarrow && \forall x\in X\, \exists z\in f\, \exists y\, \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z,x,y), \\&\vartheta_f(f) && \Leftrightarrow && f \text{ is functional}\\&&& \Leftrightarrow && \forall z_0\in f\, \forall z_1\in f\, \forall x\, \forall y_0\, \forall y_1\, (\operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z_0,x,y_0)\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z_1,x,y_1)\rightarrow y_0=y_1). \end{align*} $$

Let $\alpha ={\Pi }_{\sigma } i$ . For the direction left to right, it suffices to look for closed terms $\mathbf r$ , ${\mathbf t}$ , and $\mathbf f$ such that whenever $f\sim _{\alpha } g$ , then

(1) $$ \begin{align} \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \mathbf rf=\mathbf rg &\Vdash \vartheta_r(f^{\alpha},X_{\sigma},F), \end{align} $$
(2) $$ \begin{align} \ \ \ \ \ \mathbf tf=\mathbf tg &\Vdash \vartheta_t(X_{\sigma},f^{\alpha}), \end{align} $$
(3) $$ \begin{align} \mathbf ff=\mathbf fg &\Vdash \vartheta_f(f^{\alpha}). \end{align} $$

For the direction right to left, we look for a closed term $\mathbf c$ such that, for every $h\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ , if $c=d\Vdash \vartheta _r(h,X_{\sigma },F)\land \vartheta _t(X_{\sigma },h)\land \vartheta _f(h)$ , then $\mathbf c c=\mathbf c d\Vdash h\in X_{{\Pi }_{\sigma } i}$ .

Let us start with the forward direction.

(1) Let $f\sim _{\alpha } g$ , $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ , $ia=\tau $ , and $fa=e$ . We want

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf rfa=\mathbf rgb\Vdash \exists x\in X_{\sigma}\, \exists y\, \exists Z\in F\, \exists Y\, (\operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(\langle{a^{\sigma},e^{\tau}}\rangle_{\!A},x,y)\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(Z,x,Y)\land y\in Y).\end{align*}$$

We let $(\mathbf rfa)_0=a$ and set out for

$$\begin{align*}(\mathbf rfa)_1=(\mathbf rgb)_1\Vdash \exists Z\in F\, \exists Y\, (\operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(\langle{a^{\sigma},e^{\tau}}\rangle_{\!A},a^{\sigma},e^{\tau})\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(Z,a^{\sigma},Y)\land e^{\tau}\in Y).\end{align*}$$

We let $(\mathbf rfa)_{10}=a$ , $Y=X_{\tau }$ and set out for

$$\begin{align*}(\mathbf rfa)_{11}=(\mathbf rgb)_{11}\Vdash \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(\langle{a^{\sigma},e^{\tau}}\rangle_{\!A},a^{\sigma},e^{\tau})\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(\langle{a^{\sigma},X_{\tau}}\rangle_{\!A},a^{\sigma},X_{\tau})\land e^{\tau}\in X_{\tau}.\end{align*}$$

Let $(\mathbf rfa)_{110}=(\mathbf rfa)_{1110}={\mathbf v}$ , where ${\mathbf v}\Vdash \operatorname {{\mathrm {OP}}}(\langle {x,y}\rangle _{\!A},x,y)$ exists by Lemma 3.15. Let $(\mathbf rfa)_{1111}=\mathbf p(ca)\mathbf i$ , where $\mathbf i\Vdash \forall x\, (x=x)$ . Then $\langle {fa,gb,e^{\tau }}\rangle \in X_{\tau }$ and

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf r=_{\mathrm{def}}\lambda f\lambda a. \mathbf p a(\mathbf p a(\mathbf p {\mathbf v}(\mathbf p {\mathbf v}(\mathbf (fa)\mathbf i))))) \end{align*}$$

is as desired.

(2) Exercise.

(3) Let $f\sim _{\alpha } g$ . Let $a_j\sim _{\sigma } b_j$ , $ia_j=\tau _j$ , and $fa_j=e_j$ for $j=0,1$ . We wish to find $\mathbf f$ such that, if $c=d\Vdash \operatorname {{\mathrm {OP}}}(\langle {a_0^{\sigma },e_0^{\tau _0}}\rangle _{\!A},x,y_0)\land \operatorname {{\mathrm {OP}}}(\langle {a_1^{\sigma },e_1^{\tau _1}}\rangle _{\!A},x,y_1)$ , then $\mathbf ffa_0a_1c=\mathbf fgb_0b_1d\Vdash y_0=y_1$ , for all $x,y_0,y_1\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ . Suppose we have c and d as above. Then in particular $\Vdash a_0^{\sigma }=a_1^{\sigma }$ . By Lemma 4.11, it follows that $a_0\sim _{\sigma } a_1$ , and hence $\tau _0\sim \tau _1$ and $e_0\sim _{\tau _0} e_1$ . Thus by Lemma 4.11 again, $y=e_0^{\tau _0}=e_1^{\tau _1}$ . Then $c=d\Vdash \operatorname {{\mathrm {OP}}}(\langle {a_0^{\sigma },y}\rangle _{\!A},x,y_0)\land \operatorname {{\mathrm {OP}}}(\langle {a_1^{\sigma },y}\rangle _{\!A},x,y_1)$ . By soundness and the properties of pairing, $\mathbf q c=\mathbf qd\Vdash y_0=y_1$ , for some closed term $\mathbf q$ . Thus $\mathbf f=_{\mathrm {def}}\lambda f\lambda a_0\lambda a_1\lambda c. \mathbf qc$ is as desired.

Conversely, let $h\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ and suppose

(4) $$ \begin{align} c_0=d_0 &\Vdash \vartheta_r(h,X_{\sigma},F) & (\text{namely, } h\subseteq{\Sigma}(X_{\sigma},F)), \end{align} $$
(5) $$ \begin{align} c_{10}=d_{10} &\Vdash \vartheta_t(X_{\sigma},h) & (\text{namely, } X_{\sigma}\subseteq\operatorname{{\mathrm{dom}}}(h)), \end{align} $$
(6) $$ \begin{align} c_{11}=d_{11} &\Vdash \vartheta_f(h) & (\text{namely, } h\text{ is functional}). \end{align} $$

We wish to find $\mathbf c$ such that $\mathbf c c=\mathbf c d\Vdash h\in X_{{\Pi }_{\sigma } i}$ . We thus aim for $f=(\mathbf cc)_0\sim _{\alpha } (\mathbf cd)_0=g$ and $(\mathbf cc)_1=(\mathbf cd)_1\Vdash h=f^{\alpha }$ . Let us first find f and g. If $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ , then by (5) there are $z,y\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ such that

(7) $$ \begin{align} \langle{(c_{10}a)_0,(d_{10}b)_0,z}\rangle\in h, \end{align} $$
(8) $$ \begin{align} (c_{10}a)_1=(d_{10}b)_1\Vdash \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z,a^{\sigma},y). \end{align} $$

From (4) and (7), it follows that

$$\begin{align*}\breve{a}=(c_0(c_{10}a)_0)_0\sim_{\sigma} (d_0(d_{10}b)_0)_0=\breve{b}, \end{align*}$$
$$\begin{align*}\tilde{a}=(c_0(c_{10}a)_0)_{10}\sim_{\sigma} (d_0(d_{10}b)_0)_{10}=\tilde{b}, \end{align*}$$

and for some $\breve {y},Y\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ ,

(9) $$ \begin{align} (c_0(c_{10}a)_0)_{11}= (d_0(d_{10}b)_0)_{11}\Vdash \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z,\breve{a}^{\sigma},\breve{y})\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(\langle{\tilde{a}^{\sigma},X_{\tilde{\tau}}}\rangle_{\!A},\breve{a}^{\sigma},Y)\land \breve{y}\in Y, \end{align} $$

where $\tilde \tau =i \tilde {a}$ . Now, by (8) and (9) we obtain $\Vdash a^{\sigma }=\breve {a}^{\sigma }$ and $\Vdash \tilde {a}^{\sigma }=\breve {a}^{\sigma }$ , and hence by Lemma 4.11 we have $a\sim _{\sigma } \breve {a}\sim _{\sigma } \tilde {a}$ . Therefore, $a^{\sigma }=\breve a^{\sigma }$ , $\tau =ia\sim i\breve {a}=\breve {\tau }$ , and $X_{\tau }=X_{\breve {\tau }}$ . By the properties of pairing and equality, from (8) and (9) we obtain $\mathbf q ca=\mathbf q db\Vdash y\in X_{\tau }$ , for some closed term $\mathbf q$ . Hence

(10) $$ \begin{align} e=(\mathbf q ca)_0\sim_{\tau} (\mathbf qdb)_0, \end{align} $$
(11) $$ \begin{align} (\mathbf qca)_1=(\mathbf qdb)_1\Vdash y=e^{\tau}. \end{align} $$

Therefore, by (10), by letting $(\mathbf c c)_0=\lambda a.(\mathbf qca)_0$ , we have

$$\begin{align*}f=(\mathbf cc)_0\sim_{\alpha} (\mathbf cd)_0=g. \end{align*}$$

It remains to show $(\mathbf c c)_1=(\mathbf c d)_1\Vdash h=f^{\alpha }$ .

For the right to left inclusion, let $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ , $e=fa$ , and $\tau =ia$ . We want

$$\begin{align*}((\mathbf c c)_1a)_1= ((\mathbf c d)_1b)_1 \Vdash \langle{a^{\sigma},e^{\tau}}\rangle_{\!A}\in h. \end{align*}$$

By the foregoing discussion, we have that (7), (8), and (11) hold true for some $z,y\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ . By the properties of pairing and equality, it follows from (8) and (11) that $\mathbf rca=\mathbf rdb\Vdash \langle {a^{\sigma },e^{\tau }}\rangle _{\!A}=z$ , for some closed term $\mathbf r$ . We may then let $((\mathbf c c)_1a)_{1}=\mathbf p (c_{10}a)_0 (\mathbf rca)$ .

The left to right inclusion is treated in a similar manner. Suppose $\langle {\breve c,\breve d,\breve z}\rangle \in h$ . By (4), $a=(c_0\breve c)_0\sim _{\sigma } (d_0\breve d)_0=b$ , and for some $\breve y\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ , $(c_0\breve c)_{110}= (d_0\breve d)_{110}\Vdash \operatorname {{\mathrm {OP}}}(\breve z,a^{\sigma },\breve y)$ . As before, there are $z,y\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ such that (7), (8), and (11) hold true of a and b. On account of (6), it follows from (7), (8), and (11) that $\mathbf l c\breve c=\mathbf ld\breve d\Vdash \breve z=\langle {a^{\sigma },(fa)^{\tau }}\rangle _{\!A}$ , for some closed term $\mathbf l$ . Then $\mathbf c$ such that $((\mathbf c c)_1\breve c)_0=\mathbf p (c_0\breve c)_0 (\mathbf lc\breve c)$ does the job.

(iv) We aim for $\mathbf {sum}\Vdash X_{{\Sigma }_{\sigma } i}={\Sigma }(X_{\sigma }, F)$ . Let $\beta ={\Sigma }_{\sigma } i$ . For the direction from left to right, we ask for a closed term $\mathbf l$ such that

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf l\Vdash \forall z\in X_{{\Sigma}_{\sigma} i}\, \exists x\in X_{\sigma}\, \exists y\, \exists Y\, \exists Z\in F\, (\operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z,x,y)\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(Z,x,Y)\land y\in Y). \end{align*}$$

Let $a\sim _{\beta } b$ . We want

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf la=\mathbf l b\Vdash \exists x\in X_{\sigma}\, \exists y\, \exists Y\, \exists Z\in F\, (\operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(\langle{a_0^{\sigma},a_1^{\tau}}\rangle_{\!A},x,y)\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(Z,x,Y)\land y\in Y), \end{align*}$$

where $\tau =ia_0$ . By definition, $a_0\sim _{\sigma } b_0$ . Let $(\mathbf l a)_0=a_0$ . Then we aim for

$$\begin{align*}(\mathbf la)_1=(\mathbf lb)_1\Vdash \exists Z\in F\, (\operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(\langle{a_0^{\sigma},a_1^{\tau}}\rangle_{\!A},a_0^{\sigma},y)\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(Z,a_0^{\sigma},Y)\land y\in Y), \end{align*}$$

for some $y,Y\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ . Let $y=a_1^{\tau }$ , and $Y=X_{\tau }$ . Note that $\langle {a_0,b_0,\langle {a_0^{\sigma },X_{\tau }}\rangle _{\!A}}\rangle \in F$ . Set $(\mathbf la)_{10}=a_0$ . We thus want

$$\begin{align*}(\mathbf la)_{11}=(\mathbf lb)_{11}\Vdash \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(\langle{a_0^{\sigma},a_1^{\tau}}\rangle_{\!A},a_0^{\sigma},a_1^{\tau})\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(\langle{a_0^{\sigma},X_{\tau}}\rangle_{\!A},a_0^{\sigma},X_{\tau})\land a_1^{\tau}\in X_{\tau}. \end{align*}$$

By the properties of pairing, we just need to worry about the last conjunct. Now, $a_1\sim _{\tau } b_1$ , and thereby $\langle {a_1,b_1,a_1^{\tau }}\rangle \in X_{\tau }$ . Therefore, $\mathbf p a_1\mathbf i=\mathbf p b_1\mathbf i\Vdash a_1^{\tau }\in X_{\tau }$ , where $\mathbf i\Vdash \forall x\, (x=x)$ .

We now consider the converse direction. We look for a closed term $\mathbf r$ such that

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf r\Vdash \forall z\, \forall x\in X_{\sigma}\, \forall y\, \forall Z\in F\, \forall Y\, (\operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z,x,y)\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(Z,x,Y)\land y\in Y\rightarrow z\in X_{{\Sigma}_{\sigma} i}). \end{align*}$$

Let $z,y\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ and $\breve a\sim _{\sigma }\breve b$ . We want

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf r\breve a=\mathbf r\breve b\Vdash \forall Z\in F\, \forall Y\, (\operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z,\breve a^{\sigma},y)\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(Z,\breve a^{\sigma},Y)\land y\in Y\rightarrow z\in X_{{\Sigma}_{\sigma} i}). \end{align*}$$

Let $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ and $\tau =ia$ . We set out for

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf r\breve aa=\mathbf r\breve bb\Vdash \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z,\breve a^{\sigma},y)\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(\langle{a^{\sigma},X_{\tau}}\rangle_{\!A},\breve a^{\sigma},Y)\land y\in Y\rightarrow z\in X_{{\Sigma}_{\sigma} i}, \end{align*}$$

for every $Y\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ . Fix a $Y\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ and suppose

$$\begin{align*}c=d\Vdash \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z,\breve a^{\sigma},y)\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(\langle{a^{\sigma},X_{\tau}}\rangle_{\!A},\breve a^{\sigma},Y)\land y\in Y. \end{align*}$$

By the properties of pairing and equality, we have $\Vdash a^{\sigma }=\breve a^{\sigma }$ and

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf q c=\mathbf qd\Vdash \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(z,a^{\sigma},y)\land y\in X_{\tau}, \end{align*}$$

for some closed term $\mathbf q$ . By Lemma 4.11, we then obtain $a^{\sigma }=\breve a^{\sigma }$ . Therefore,

$$\begin{align*}\mathring c=(\mathbf q c)_{10}\sim_{\tau} (\mathbf q d)_{10}=\mathring d, \end{align*}$$
$$\begin{align*}(\mathbf q c)_{11}\sim_{\tau} (\mathbf q d)_{11} \Vdash y= \mathring c^{\tau}. \end{align*}$$

By the usual properties of pairing and equality, we have $\mathbf z c=\mathbf z d\Vdash z=\langle {a^{\sigma },\mathring c^{\tau }}\rangle _{\!A}$ , for some closed term $\mathbf z$ . Now, $\mathbf p a\mathring c\sim _{\beta }\mathbf p b\mathring d$ , and so $\langle {\mathbf p a\mathring c,\mathbf p b\mathring d, \langle {a^{\sigma },\mathring c^{\tau }}\rangle _{\!A}}\rangle \in X_{{\Sigma }_{\sigma } i}$ . Therefore,

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf p(\mathbf p a(\mathbf q c)_{10})(\mathbf z c)=\mathbf p(\mathbf p b(\mathbf q d)_{10})(\mathbf zd)\Vdash z\in X_{{\Sigma}_{\sigma} i}. \end{align*}$$

Then $\mathbf r$ such that $\mathbf r\breve a ac=\mathbf p(\mathbf p a(\mathbf q c)_{10})(\mathbf z c)$ does the job.

(v) We aim for $\mathbf {id}\Vdash X_{\mathrm {I}_{\sigma }(a,b)}=\mathrm {I}(a^{\sigma },b^{\sigma })$ . For the left to right direction, we want a closed term $\mathbf l$ such that whenever $\langle {c,d,z}\rangle \in X_{\mathrm {I}_{\sigma }(a,b)}$ , then $\mathbf {l}c=\mathbf ld\Vdash \nu (z)\land a^{\sigma }=b^{\sigma }$ , where $\nu (z)$ expresses that $z=0$ . Suppose $\langle {c,d,z}\rangle \in X_{\mathrm {I}_{\sigma }(a,b)}$ . By definition, $c=d=\mathbf 0$ , $z=0$ , and $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ . It is easy to find ${\mathbf t}$ such that ${\mathbf t}\Vdash \nu (0)$ . On the other hand, by Lemma 4.11, from $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ we obtain $a^{\sigma }=b^{\sigma }$ . Let $\mathbf l=_{\mathrm {def}}\lambda c.\mathbf p\mathbf q\mathbf i$ , where $\mathbf i\Vdash \forall x\, (x=x)$ .

For the right to left direction, we aim for a closed term $\mathbf r$ such that for every $z\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ , $\mathbf r\Vdash \nu (z)\land a^{\sigma }=b^{\sigma } \rightarrow z\in X_{\mathrm {I}_{\sigma }(a,b)}$ . Note that $\Vdash \nu (z)$ implies $z=0$ . By Lemma 4.11, $\Vdash a^{\sigma }=b^{\sigma }$ implies $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ . Thus let $\mathbf r=_{\mathrm {def}}\lambda c.\mathbf p\mathbf 0\mathbf i$ , where $\mathbf i$ is as before.

(vi) We aim for $\mathbf w\Vdash X_{\mathrm {W}_{\sigma } i}=\mathrm {W}(X_{\sigma },F)$ . Set $\delta =\mathrm {W}_{\sigma } i$ . By Theorem 6.2, it suffices to find closed terms $\mathbf l$ and $\mathbf r$ such that

$$ \begin{align*} \mathbf l &\Vdash \forall y\in X_{\delta}\, \exists x\in X_{\sigma}\, \exists f\, \vartheta(y,x,f), \\ \mathbf r &\Vdash \forall y\, (\exists x\in X_{\sigma}\, \exists f\, \vartheta(y,x,f)\rightarrow y\in X_{\delta}), \end{align*} $$

where $\vartheta (y,x,f) \Leftrightarrow \operatorname {{\mathrm {OP}}}(y,x,f)\land \vartheta _0(x,f)\land \vartheta _1(f)\land \vartheta _2(f)$ , with

$$ \begin{align*} &\vartheta_0(x,f) && \Leftrightarrow && f \text{ is a relation}\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{dom}}}(f)=F(x) \\ & && \Leftrightarrow && \forall Z\in F\, \forall X\, (\operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(Z,x,X)\rightarrow \forall v\in f\, \exists u\in X\, \exists z\, \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(v,u,z)\land \\ &&&&& \qquad\qquad\qquad\qquad\qquad\qquad\qquad \forall u\in X\, \exists z\, \exists v\in f\, \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(v,u,z)),\\ &\vartheta_1(f) && \Leftrightarrow && f \text{ is functional} \\ &&& \Leftrightarrow && \forall v_0\in f\, \forall v_1\in f\, \forall u\, \forall z_0\, \forall z_1\, (\operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(v_0,u,z_0)\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(v_1,u,z_1)\rightarrow z_0=z_1), \\ &\vartheta_2(f) && \Leftrightarrow && \operatorname{{\mathrm{ran}}}(f)\subseteq X_{\delta} \\ &&& \Leftrightarrow && \forall v\in f\, \forall u\, \forall z\, (\operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(v,u,z)\rightarrow z\in X_{\delta}). \end{align*} $$

Remember that

$$ \begin{align*} F&=F_{\sigma,i}=\{\langle{a,b,\langle{a^{\sigma},X_{ia}}\rangle_{\!A}}\rangle\mid a\sim_{\sigma} b\}, \\ X_{\delta}&=\{\langle{c,d,c^{\delta}}\rangle\mid c\sim_{\delta} d\}, \\ c^{\delta}&=\langle{c_0^{\sigma},f_c}\rangle_{\!A}, \ \ \text{where } f_c=\{\langle{p,q,\langle{p^{ic_0},(c_1p)^{\delta}}\rangle_{\!A}}\rangle\mid p\sim_{ic_0} q\}, \\ c\sim_{\delta} d&\leftrightarrow c_0\sim_{\sigma} d_0\land \forall p\, \forall q\, (p\sim_{ic_0}q\rightarrow c_1p\sim_{\delta} d_1q). \end{align*} $$

From left to right, note that if $c\sim _{\delta } d$ , then $c_0\sim _{\sigma } d_0$ . Let $(\mathbf lc)_0=c_0$ . We then want $(\mathbf lc)_1=(\mathbf ld)_1\Vdash \exists f\, \vartheta (c^{\delta },c_0^{\sigma },f)$ . The obvious candidate for f is $f_c$ . The details are tedious but straightforward.

Let us consider the slightly more interesting direction. Let $y\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ and suppose

(16) $$ \begin{align} a=b\Vdash \exists x\in X_{\sigma}\, \exists f\, \vartheta(y,x,f). \end{align} $$

The goal is to find $\mathbf r$ such that $\mathbf ra=\mathbf rb\Vdash y\in X_{\delta }$ . By undoing (16), we obtain

(17) $$ \begin{align} a_0\sim_{\sigma} b_0\ \ \text{and}\ \ a_1=b_1\Vdash \vartheta(y,a_0^{\sigma},f), \end{align} $$

for some $f\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ . It follows from the second half of (17) that $a_{10}=b_{10}\Vdash \operatorname {{\mathrm {OP}}}(y,a_0^{\sigma },f)$ . Also, we can find closed terms $\mathbf q_0,\mathbf q_1,\mathbf q_2$ such that $\mathbf q_0a=\mathbf q_0b\Vdash \vartheta _0(a_0^{\sigma },f)$ and $\mathbf q_ia=\mathbf q_ib\Vdash \vartheta _i(f)$ for $i=1,2$ . Because $a_0\sim _{\sigma } b_0$ by the first half of (17), we can apply $\mathbf q_0$ and obtain

(18) $$ \begin{align} \mathbf q_0aa_0=\mathbf q_0bb_0\Vdash \forall X\, (\operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(\langle{a_0^{\sigma},X_{ia_0}}\rangle_{\!A},a_0^{\sigma},X)\rightarrow \psi_0(f,X)), \end{align} $$

where

$$ \begin{align*} \psi_0(f,X) && \Leftrightarrow && \forall v\in f\, \exists u\in X\, \exists z\, \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(v,u,z)\land \forall u\in X\, \exists z\, \exists v\in f\, \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(v,u,z). \end{align*} $$

By the properties of pairing with $X=X_{ia_0}$ , it follows from (18) that

(19) $$ \begin{align} \mathbf ta={\mathbf t} b\Vdash \psi_0(f,X_{ia_0}), \end{align} $$

for some closed term ${\mathbf t}$ . Suppose $p\sim _{ia_0} q$ . By (19), $(\mathbf ta)_1p=({\mathbf t} b)_1q\Vdash \exists z\, \exists v\in f \operatorname {{\mathrm {OP}}}(v,p^{ia_0},z)$ , and hence for some $z,v\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ ,

(20) $$ \begin{align} \langle{((\mathbf ta)_1p)_0, (({\mathbf t} b)_1q)_0,v}\rangle\in f, \end{align} $$
(21) $$ \begin{align} ((\mathbf ta)_1p)_1= (({\mathbf t} b)_1q)_1\Vdash \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(v,p^{ia_0},z). \end{align} $$

Write $\langle {\breve p,\breve q,v}\rangle $ for $\langle {((\mathbf ta)_1p)_0, (({\mathbf t} b)_1q)_0,v}\rangle $ . Now, $\mathbf q_2a=\mathbf q_2b\Vdash \vartheta _2(f)$ . It then follows from (20) that

(22) $$ \begin{align} \mathbf q_2a\breve p=\mathbf q_2b\breve q\Vdash \forall u\, \forall z\, (\operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(v,u,z)\rightarrow z\in X_{\delta}). \end{align} $$

By (21) and (22), we get $\mathbf q_2a\breve p((\mathbf ta)_1p)_1=\mathbf q_2b\breve q(({\mathbf t} b)_1q)_1 \Vdash z\in X_{\delta }$ , and so we can construct a closed term $\mathbf f$ such that

$$\begin{align*}(\mathbf fap)_0\sim_{\delta} (\mathbf fbq)_0 \ \ \text{and} \ \ (\mathbf fap)_1= (\mathbf fbq)_1\Vdash z=(\mathbf fap)_0^{\delta}.\end{align*}$$

The foregoing discussion also shows that, if we let $(\mathbf ra)_0=\mathbf p a_0(\lambda p.(\mathbf fap)_0)$ , then $c= (\mathbf ra)_0\sim _{\delta } (\mathbf rb)_0=d$ . We then wish to find $\mathbf r$ such that $(\mathbf ra)_1=(\mathbf rb)_1\Vdash y=c^{\delta }$ . For this one needs to show that $\mathbf ha=\mathbf hb\Vdash f=f_c$ for some closed term $\mathbf h$ . Since this is similar to the proof of the right to left direction of (iii), we leave the details to the reader.

Proof of Theorem 4.16

We have to provide closed terms $\mathbf i$ and ${\mathbf e}$ such that

$$\begin{align*}c=d\Vdash X\in {\Pi}{\Sigma}\mathrm{I} \ \ \text{implies} \ \ \sigma=\mathbf ic\sim\mathbf id\ \ \text{and}\ \ \mathbf ec={\mathbf e} d\Vdash X=X_{\sigma}, \end{align*}$$

for every $X\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ . The same task for ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}$ -sets.

Let $\vartheta (u,Y)$ be as in Theorem 6.1. Thus ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {I}=\{Y\mid \exists u\, \vartheta (u,Y)\}$ . We want $\mathbf i$ and ${\mathbf e}$ such that for every $u,Y\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ ,

$$\begin{align*}c=d\Vdash \vartheta(u,Y)\ \ \text{implies}\ \ \sigma=\mathbf ic\sim \mathbf id\ \ \text{and}\ \ \mathbf ec={\mathbf e} d\Vdash Y=X_{\sigma}. \end{align*}$$

The closed terms $\mathbf i$ and ${\mathbf e}$ are obtained by means of the recursion theorem for pca’s. The verification is done by induction on u. First, by soundness, there is a closed term $\mathbf {t}$ such that $c=d\Vdash \vartheta (u,Y)$ implies

$$\begin{align*}{\mathbf t} c={\mathbf t} d\Vdash \bigvee_{i=0}^4 \vartheta_{i}(u,Y). \end{align*}$$

By using the definition by cases combinator $\mathbf d$ , we can find closed terms $\mathbf {c}$ and ${\mathbf t}_i$ for $i<4$ such that if $c=d\Vdash \vartheta (u,Y)$ , then for some $i<5$ ,

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf{c} c=\mathbf{c} d=\bar i\ \ \text{and}\ \ {\mathbf t}_ic={\mathbf t}_id\Vdash \vartheta_{i}(u,Y). \end{align*}$$

Case 0. If $\mathbf c c=\mathbf 0$ , then ${\mathbf t}_0 c={\mathbf t}_0 d\Vdash Y\in \omega $ . By Theorem 4.14, we have a closed term $\mathbf o$ such that $\mathbf o\Vdash X_{\mathsf {N}}=\omega $ . By soundness, there is a closed term ${\mathbf v}_0$ such that ${\mathbf v}_0c={\mathbf v}_0d\Vdash Y\in X_{\mathsf {N}}$ . This means that, for some $n\in \omega $ , $({\mathbf v}_0c)_0=({\mathbf v}_0d)_0=\bar n$ and $({\mathbf v}_0c)_1=({\mathbf v}_0d)_1\Vdash Y=\dot n$ . Now, $\mathsf {N}_n=\mathbf p \mathbf 0\bar n$ and $X_{\mathsf {N}_n}=\dot n$ . Therefore, in this case, meaning $\mathbf c c=\mathbf 0$ , we look for $\mathbf i$ and ${\mathbf e}$ such that $\mathbf ic=\mathbf p\mathbf 0({\mathbf v}_0c)_0$ and $\mathbf ec=({\mathbf v}_0c)_1$ .

Case 1. If $\mathbf cc={\mathbf 1}$ , then ${\mathbf t}_1c={\mathbf t}_1d\Vdash Y=\omega $ . As before, by soundness, there is a closed term ${\mathbf v}_1$ such that ${\mathbf v}_1c={\mathbf v}_1d\Vdash Y=X_{\mathsf {N}}$ . Therefore, in this case, meaning $\mathbf cc={\mathbf 1}$ , we look for $\mathbf i$ and ${\mathbf e}$ such that $\mathbf ic=o$ and $\mathbf ec={\mathbf v}_1c$ .

Case 2. Suppose $\mathbf c c=\mathbf 2$ . We are in the case where

(1) $$ \begin{align} {\mathbf t}_2 c={\mathbf t}_2 d&\Vdash \exists v\in u\, \vartheta(v,X)\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{Fun}}}(F) \land \operatorname{{\mathrm{dom}}}(F)=X\land \nonumber \\ & \qquad \forall x\in X\, \exists v\in u\, \vartheta(v,F(x))\land Y={\Pi}(X,F), \end{align} $$

for some $X,F\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ . By undoing (1), we get that for some $\langle {\mathring {c},\mathring {d},v}\rangle \in u$ , $({\mathbf t}_2 c)_{01}=({\mathbf t}_2 d)_{01} \Vdash \vartheta (v,X)$ . By induction, we can assume

(2) $$ \begin{align} \sigma=\mathbf i ({\mathbf t}_2 c)_{01}\sim\mathbf i ({\mathbf t}_2 d)_{01}=\tau, \end{align} $$
(3) $$ \begin{align} {\mathbf e}({\mathbf t}_2 c)_{01}={\mathbf e} ({\mathbf t}_2 d)_{01} \Vdash X=X_{\sigma}. \end{align} $$

By the properties of equality, on account of (1) and (3), we can find closed terms $\mathbf q_0,\mathbf q_1,\mathbf q_2$ such that

(4) $$ \begin{align} \mathbf q_0{\mathbf e} c=\mathbf q_0\mathbf ed & \Vdash \operatorname{{\mathrm{Fun}}}(F)\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{dom}}}(F)=X_{\sigma}, \end{align} $$
(5) $$ \begin{align} \ \ \ \ \mathbf q_1\mathbf ec=\mathbf q_1\mathbf ed &\Vdash \forall x\in X_{\sigma}\, \exists v\in u\, \vartheta(v,F(x)), \end{align} $$
(6) $$ \begin{align} \mathbf q_2\mathbf ec=\mathbf q_2\mathbf ed &\Vdash Y={\Pi}(X_{\sigma},F). \qquad\qquad \end{align} $$

Suppose $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ . By using (4), we can obtain a closed term $\mathbf r$ such that

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf r\mathbf ec=\mathbf r\mathbf ed\Vdash \forall x\in X_{\sigma}\, \exists Z\, \exists \mathring{X}\, (Z\in F\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(Z,x,\mathring{X})). \end{align*}$$

Therefore, there are $Z,\mathring {X}\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ such that $\mathbf r\mathbf eca=\mathbf r\mathbf edb\Vdash Z\in F\land \operatorname {{\mathrm {OP}}}(Z,a^{\sigma },\mathring {X})$ . On the other hand, it follows from (5) that

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf q_1\mathbf eca=\mathbf q_1\mathbf edb\Vdash \exists v\in u\, \forall Z\, \forall \mathring{X}\, (Z\in F\land \operatorname{{\mathrm{OP}}}(Z,a^{\sigma},\mathring{X})\rightarrow \vartheta(v,\mathring X)). \end{align*}$$

In particular, for some $\langle {\mathring c,\mathring d,v}\rangle \in u$ , $(\mathbf q_1\mathbf eca)_1(\mathbf r\mathbf eca)=(\mathbf q_1\mathbf edb)_1(\mathbf r\mathbf edb)\Vdash \vartheta (v,\mathring {X})$ . To ease notation, let $r({\mathbf e},c,a)=(\mathbf q_1\mathbf eca)_1(\mathbf r\mathbf eca)$ . By induction, we can assume that $\rho =\mathbf i r({\mathbf e},c,a)\sim \mathbf i r({\mathbf e},d,b)$ and ${\mathbf e} r({\mathbf e},c,a)={\mathbf e} r({\mathbf e},d,b)\Vdash \mathring X=X_{\rho }$ . We have just shown that if $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ then $ia\sim jb$ , where $i=\lambda a.\mathbf i r({\mathbf e},c,a)$ and $j=\lambda b.\mathbf i r({\mathbf e},d,b)$ . By (2), we thus have ${\Pi }_{\sigma } i\sim {\Pi }_{\tau } j$ .

Let $\mathbf {prod}$ be as in Theorem 4.14. That is, $\mathbf {prod}\Vdash X_{{\Pi }_{\sigma } i}={\Pi }(X_{\sigma },F_{\sigma ,i})$ . We aim to show that for some closed term $\mathbf f$ , $\mathbf f \mathbf ec=\mathbf f \mathbf ed\Vdash F=F_{\sigma ,i}$ . If we do so, owing to the soundness, we can cook up, by using (6) and $\mathbf {prod}$ , a closed term ${\mathbf v}_2$ such that ${\mathbf v}_2\mathbf ec={\mathbf v}_2\mathbf ed\Vdash Y=X_{{\Pi }_{\sigma } i}$ . In this case, meaning $\mathbf c c=\mathbf 2$ , we thus want $\mathbf i$ and ${\mathbf e}$ such that

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf ic={\Pi}_{\mathbf i ({\mathbf t}_2 c)_{01}}(\lambda a.\mathbf i (\mathbf q_1\mathbf eca)_1(\mathbf r\mathbf eca))\ \ \text{and}\ \ \mathbf ec={\mathbf v}_2\mathbf ec. \end{align*}$$

Let us show how to find $\mathbf f$ . By Theorem 4.14, $\mathbf {fun}\Vdash \operatorname {{\mathrm {Fun}}}(F_{\sigma ,i})\land \operatorname {{\mathrm {dom}}}(F)=X_{\sigma }$ . By (4), it then suffices to look for a closed term $\mathbf {h}$ such that

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf h \mathbf ec=\mathbf h \mathbf ed \Vdash \forall Z\in F_{\sigma,i}\, (Z\in F). \end{align*}$$

Let $a\sim _{\sigma } b$ . We aim for $\mathbf h \mathbf eca=\mathbf h \mathbf edb\Vdash \langle {a^{\sigma },X_{\rho }}\rangle _{\!A}\in F$ , where $\rho =i a$ . As before, we know that for some $Z,\mathring X\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ , $\mathbf r\mathbf eca=\mathbf r\mathbf edb \Vdash Z\in F\land \operatorname {{\mathrm {OP}}}(Z,a^{\sigma },\mathring {X})$ and ${\mathbf e} r({\mathbf e},c,a)={\mathbf e} r({\mathbf e},d,b) \Vdash \mathring X=X_{\rho }$ . By the properties of equality and pairing, we can easily arrange for such $\mathbf h$ .

Case 3. The case $\mathbf c c=\mathbf 3$ is treated similarly.

Case 4. Suppose $\mathbf cc={\mathbf 4}$ . In this case,

(7) $$ \begin{align} {\mathbf t}_4 c={\mathbf t}_4 d&\Vdash \exists v\in u\, \vartheta(v,X)\land \exists x\in X\, \exists y\in X\, (Y=\mathrm{I}(x,y)), \end{align} $$

for some $X\in \mathrm {V_{ext}}(A)$ . As in Case 2, we can assume

$$\begin{align*}\sigma=\mathbf i ({\mathbf t}_4 c)_{01}\sim\mathbf i ({\mathbf t}_4 d)_{01}=\tau, \end{align*}$$
(8) $$ \begin{align} {\mathbf e}({\mathbf t}_4 c)_{01}={\mathbf e} ({\mathbf t}_4 d)_{01} \Vdash X=X_{\sigma}. \end{align} $$

By the properties of equality, owing to (7) and (8), we thus have a closed term $\mathbf q$ such that $\mathbf q\mathbf ec=\mathbf q\mathbf ed\Vdash \exists x\in X_{\sigma }\, \exists y\in X_{\sigma }\, (Y=\mathrm {I}(x,y))$ . By unfolding the definition, we obtain

$$\begin{align*}a=(\mathbf q\mathbf ec)_0\sim_{\sigma} (\mathbf qed)_0=\breve a, \end{align*}$$
$$\begin{align*}b=(\mathbf q\mathbf ec)_{10}\sim_{\sigma} (\mathbf q\mathbf ed)_{10}=\breve b, \end{align*}$$
$$\begin{align*}(\mathbf q\mathbf ec)_{11}=(\mathbf q\mathbf ed)_{11}\Vdash Y=\mathrm{I}(a^{\sigma},b^{\sigma}). \end{align*}$$

By using $\mathbf {id}\Vdash X_{\mathrm {I}_{\sigma }(a,b)}=\mathrm {I}(a^{\sigma },b^{\sigma })$ from Theorem 4.14, we then obtain by soundness a closed term ${\mathbf v}_4$ such that ${\mathbf v}_4\mathbf ec={\mathbf v}_4\mathbf ed\Vdash Y=X_{\mathrm {I}_{\sigma }(a,b)}$ . In this case, meaning $\mathbf c c={\mathbf 4}$ , we thus want $\mathbf i$ and ${\mathbf e}$ such that

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf ic=\mathrm{I}_{\mathbf i ({\mathbf t}_4 c)_{01}}((\mathbf q\mathbf ec)_0,(\mathbf q\mathbf ec)_{10})\ \ \text{and}\ \ \mathbf ec={\mathbf v}_4\mathbf ec. \end{align*}$$

In the ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}$ case, one considers $\vartheta ^*(u,Y)$ as in Theorem 6.1. Thus ${\Pi }{\Sigma }\mathrm {W}\mathrm {I}=\{Y\mid \exists u\, \vartheta ^*(u,Y)\}$ . The proof then proceeds exactly as before, except that now we also need to deal with $\mathrm {W}$ -types. On the other hand, the treatment of $\mathrm {W}$ -types is completely analogous to that of ${\Pi }$ -types and ${\Sigma }$ -types. The reader can easily fill in the gaps using Case 2 as template.

Acknowledgment

The author’s research was funded by the Alexander von Humboldt foundation.

Footnotes

1 $\mathsf { CAC}_{\mathsf {FT}}$ is the schema $\forall n\, \exists y^{\tau }\, \varphi (n,y)\rightarrow \exists f^{0\to \tau }\, \forall n\,\varphi (n,f(n))$ , while $\mathsf {DC}_{\mathsf {FT}}$ stands for $\forall x^{\sigma }\,\exists y^{\sigma }\,\varphi (x,y)\rightarrow \forall x^{\sigma }\, \exists f^{0\to \sigma }\, (f(0)=x\land \forall n\,\varphi (f(n),f(n+1)))$ .

2 The name “generic” for this kind of realizability is due to McCarty [Reference McCarty22, p. 31].

3 Extensional notions of realizability have been mainly considered in the context of arithmetic and finite type arithmetic (see [Reference Troelstra33] for more information, and [Reference van den Berg and van Slooten8, Reference Frittaion16] for recent applications). Versions of extensional realizability in the context of both arithmetic and set theory can be found in [Reference Gordeev20].

4 In Aczel [Reference Aczel3], a set X is said to be a base if ${\Pi }(X,F)$ is inhabited, whenever F is a function with domain X and $F(x)$ is inhabited for all $x\in X$ , where a set X is inhabited if $\exists x\, (x\in X)$ . Over $\mathsf {CZF}$ , the two definitions are equivalent.

5 The axiom $\mathsf {RDC}$ is simply dubbed $\mathsf {DC}$ in [Reference Aczel1Reference Aczel3].

6 Let $\mathbf p=\lambda xyz.zxy$ , $\mathbf {p_0}=\lambda x.x\mathbf k$ , and $\mathbf {p_1}=\lambda x.x\bar {\mathbf k}$ , where $\bar {\mathbf k}=\lambda xy.y$ . For our purposes, projections $\mathbf {p_0}$ and $\mathbf {p_1}$ need not be total.

7 All axioms and rules apply to the formulas of the expanded language. In the case of bounded or $\Delta _0$ separation, where the collection of formulas is syntactically defined, we enlarge the stock of bounded formulas accordingly. These are built up from atomic formulas in the new language by closing under logical connectives and bounded quantifiers of the form $\forall x\in t$ and $\exists x\in t$ , where t is a term not containing x. Needless to say, as long as we add only constants, since parameters are allowed, bounded separation in the enriched language is equivalent to bounded separation in the primitive language with $\in $ and $=$ only.

8 A formula is $\Sigma $ if it is built up from bounded formulas by means of $\land $ , $\lor $ , bounded quantifiers $\forall x\in y$ and $\exists x\in y$ , and unbounded existential quantifiers $\exists x$ .

References

Aczel, P., The type theoretic interpretation of constructive set theory , Logic Colloquium ’77 (A. Macintyre, L. Pacholski, and J. Paris, editors), Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 96, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1978.Google Scholar
Aczel, P., The type theoretic interpretation of constructive set theory: Choice principles , The L. E. J. Brouwer Centenary Symposium (A. S. Troelstra and D. van Dalen, editors), Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 110, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1982, pp. 140.Google Scholar
Aczel, P., The type theoretic interpretation of constructive set theory: Inductive definitions , Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, VII (Salzburg, 1983) (R. Barcan Marcus, G. J. W. Dorn, and P. Weingartner, editors), Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 114, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1986, pp. 1749.Google Scholar
Aczel, P. and Rathjen, M., Notes on Constructive Set Theory, 2010. Available at http://www1.maths.leeds.ac.uk/~rathjen/book.pdf.Google Scholar
Beeson, M. J., Continuity in intuitionistic set theories , Logic Colloquium ’78 (M. Boffa, D. van Dalen, and K. McAloon, editors), Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 97, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1979, pp. 152.Google Scholar
Beeson, M. J., Goodman’s theorem and beyond . Pacific Journal of Mathematics , vol. 84 (1979), no. 1, pp. 116.10.2140/pjm.1979.84.1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beeson, M. J., Foundations of Constructive Mathematics , Ergebnisse der Mathematik und ihrer Grenzgebiete (3) [Results in Mathematics and Related Areas (3)], vol. 6, Springer, Berlin, 1985.10.1007/978-3-642-68952-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van den Berg, B. and van Slooten, L., Arithmetical conservation results . Indagationes Mathematicae , vol. 29 (2018), no. 1, pp. 260275.10.1016/j.indag.2017.07.009CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bishop, E., Foundations of Constructive Analysis , vol. 60 , McGraw-Hill, New York, 1967.Google Scholar
Curry, H. B., Grundlagen der kombinatorischen Logik . American Journal of Mathematics , vol. 51 (1930), pp. 363384.10.2307/2370728CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Diaconescu, R., Axiom of choice and complementation . Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society , vol. 51 (1975), no. 1, pp. 176178.10.1090/S0002-9939-1975-0373893-XCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feferman, S., A language and axioms for explicit mathematics , Algebra and Logic (J. N. Crossley, editor), Springer, Berlin, 1975, pp. 87139.10.1007/BFb0062852CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feferman, S., Constructive theories of functions and classes , Logic Colloquium ’78 (M. Boffa, D. van Dalen, and K. McAloon, editors), Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1979, pp. 159224.Google Scholar
Friedman, H., Some applications of Kleene’s methods for intuitionistic systems , Cambridge Summer School in Mathematical Logic (A. R. D. Mathias and H. Rogers, editors), Springer, Berlin, 1973, pp. 113170.10.1007/BFb0066773CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, H. and Ščedrov, A., Large sets in intuitionistic set theory . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 27 (1984), pp. 124.10.1016/0168-0072(84)90033-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frittaion, E., On Goodman realizability . Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic , vol. 60 (2019), no. 3, pp. 523550.10.1215/00294527-2019-0018CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frittaion, E. and Rathjen, M., Extensional realizability for intuitionistic set theory . Journal of Logic and Computation , vol. 31 (2021), no. 2, pp. 630653.10.1093/logcom/exaa087CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodman, N. D., The theory of the Gödel functionals, this Journal, vol. 41 (1976), no. 3, pp. 574–582.Google Scholar
Goodman, N. D., Relativized realizability in intuitionistic arithmetic of all finite types, this Journal, vol. 43 (1978), no. 1, pp. 23–44.Google Scholar
Gordeev, L., Proof-theoretical analysis of weak systems of functions and classes . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 38 (1988), pp. 1121.10.1016/0168-0072(88)90055-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kreisel, G. and Troelstra, A. S., Formal systems for some branches of intuitionistic analysis . Annals of Mathematical Logic , vol. 1 (1970), pp. 229387.10.1016/0003-4843(70)90001-XCrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCarty, D. C., Realizability and recursive mathematics , Ph.D. thesis, The University of Edinburgh, 1985.Google Scholar
McCarty, D. C., Realizability and recursive set theory . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 32 (1986), no. 2, pp. 153183.10.1016/0168-0072(86)90050-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Myhill, J., Constructive set theory, this Journal, vol. 40 (1975), no. 3, pp. 347–382.Google Scholar
van Oosten, J., Extensional realizability . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 84 (1997), no. 3, pp. 317349.10.1016/S0168-0072(96)00050-4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Oosten, J., Realizability: An Introduction to Its Categorical Side , Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 152, Elsevier, Amsterdam, 2008.Google Scholar
Rathjen, M., Constructive set theory and Brouwerian principles . Journal of Universal Computer Science , vol. 11 (2005), no. 12, pp. 20082033.Google Scholar
Rathjen, M., Choice principles in constructive and classical set theories , Logic Colloquium ’02 (Z. Chatzidakis, P. Koepke, and W. Pohlers, editors), Lecture Notes in Logic, vol. 27, Association for Symbolic Logic, La Jolla, 2006, pp. 299326.Google Scholar
Rathjen, M., The formulae-as-classes interpretation of constructive set theory , Proof Technology and Computation (H. Schwichtenberg and K. Spies, editors), NATO Science Series, III: Computer and Systems Sciences, vol. 200, IOS, Amsterdam, 2006, pp. 279322.Google Scholar
Rathjen, M.. Realizability for constructive Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory , Logic Colloquium ’03 (J. Väänänen, editor), Lecture Notes in Logic, vol. 24, Association for Symbolic Logic, La Jolla, 2006, pp. 282314.10.1201/9781439865835-14CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schönfinkel, M., Über die Bausteine der mathematischen Logik . Mathematische Annalen , vol. 92 (1924), pp. 305316.10.1007/BF01448013CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Troelstra, A. S., Metamathematical Investigation of Intuitionistic Arithmetic and Analysis , Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 344, Springer, Berlin, 1973.10.1007/BFb0066739CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Troelstra, A. S., Realizability , Handbook of Proof Theory (S. R. Buss, editor), Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 137, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1998, pp. 407473.10.1016/S0049-237X(98)80021-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Troelstra, A. S. and van Dalen, D., Constructivism in Mathematics: An Introduction , vol. II , Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, 123, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1988.Google Scholar