Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-g7gxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-13T08:46:38.669Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On the representability of actions of Leibniz algebras and Poisson algebras

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 November 2023

Alan S. Cigoli
Affiliation:
Dipartimento di Matematica “Giuseppe Peano”, Università degli Studi di Torino, Torino, Italy ([email protected])
Manuel Mancini
Affiliation:
Dipartimento di Matematica e Informatica, Università degli Studi di Palermo, Palermo, Italy ([email protected]; [email protected])
Giuseppe Metere
Affiliation:
Dipartimento di Matematica e Informatica, Università degli Studi di Palermo, Palermo, Italy ([email protected]; [email protected])
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

In a recent paper, motivated by the study of central extensions of associative algebras, George Janelidze introduces the notion of weakly action representable category. In this paper, we show that the category of Leibniz algebras is weakly action representable and we characterize the class of acting morphisms. Moreover, we study the representability of actions of the category of Poisson algebras and we prove that the subvariety of commutative Poisson algebras is not weakly action representable.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on Behalf of The Edinburgh Mathematical Society.

1. Introduction

Internal object actions were defined in [Reference Borceux, Janelidze and Kelly1] by Borceux, Janelidze and Kelly in order to recapture categorically several algebraic notions of action, such as the action of a group G on another group H, the action of a Lie algebra $\mathfrak{g}$ on another Lie algebra $\mathfrak{h}$ and so on. In the same paper, the authors introduced the notion of representable action: an object X has representable actions if the functor $\operatorname{Act}(-,X)$, sending each object B to the set of actions of B on X, is representable (see $\S$2 for further details). In [Reference Borceux, Janelidze and Kelly2], action representability was extensively studied in the semi-abelian context and it was proved that, for example, the category of commutative associative algebras over a field is not action representable.

In [Reference Bourn and Janelidze3] Bourn and Janelidze introduced the weaker notion of action accessible category in order to include relevant examples that do not fit in the frame of action representable categories (such as rings, associative algebras and Leibniz algebras amongst others). Montoli proved in [Reference Montoli15] that all categories of interest in the sense of Orzech [Reference Orzech16] are action accessible. On the other hand, the paper [Reference Casas, Datuashvili and Ladra4] by Casas, Datuashvili and Ladra showed that a weaker notion of actor (namely, the universal strict general actor, USGA for short) is available for any category of interest $\mathcal{C}$.

Recently, Janelidze introduced in [Reference Janelidze10] the notion of weakly representable action: for an object X in a semi-abelian category $\mathcal{C}$, a weak representation of the functor $\operatorname{Act}(-,X)$ is a pair $(T,\tau)$, where T is an object of $\mathcal{C}$ and $\tau\colon\operatorname{Act}(-,X)\rightarrowtail\operatorname{Hom}_\mathcal{C}(-,T)$ is a monomorphism of functors. When such monomorphism exists, one says that X has weakly representable actions and T is a weak actor of X. In particular, when $\mathcal{C}$ is a category of interest and $\operatorname{USGA}(X)$ is an object of $\mathcal{C}$, then $\operatorname{Act}(-,X)$ has a weak representation (see Corollary 4.2).

A semi-abelian category $\mathcal{C}$ is said to be weakly action representable if every object X in $\mathcal{C}$ has a weak representation of actions. This is true, for instance, for the category $\mathbf{AAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ of associative algebras over a field $\mathbb{F}$ [Reference Janelidze10]. Notice that a category of interest needs not necessarily be weakly action representable, as observed by Gray in [Reference Gray9]. However, thanks to the results of [Reference Casas, Datuashvili and Ladra4], we get that, for every object X in a category of interest $\mathcal{C}$, there exists a monomorphism of functors $\operatorname{Act}(-,X)\rightarrowtail\operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal{C}_G}(-,\operatorname{USGA}(X))$, where $\mathcal{C}_G$ is a suitable category containing $\mathcal{C}$ as a full subcategory (see Proposition 4.1).

We analyse in details two specific cases: the category $\mathbf{LeibAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ of Leibniz algebras ($\S$3) and the category $\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ of Poisson algebras ($\S$5), where $\mathbb{F}$ is a fixed field with $\operatorname{char}(\mathbb{F})\neq 2$. We show that the first one is a weakly action representable category and we provide a complete description of acting morphisms, i.e. morphisms into a weak actor corresponding to internal actions, in this case and for associative algebras. Moreover, we study the representability of actions in the category $\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ by describing explicitly a universal strict general actor $[V]=\operatorname{USGA}(V)$, for any Poisson algebra V, and the corresponding monomorphism of functors:

\begin{equation*} \tau \colon \operatorname{Act}(-,V)\rightarrowtail\operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2}(-,[V]), \end{equation*}

where $\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2$ is the category of algebras over $\mathbb{F}$ with two not necessarily associative bilinear operations. Finally, we show that the subvariety $\mathbf{CPoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ of commutative Poisson algebras is not weakly action representable. We leave the general case of $\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ as an open problem.

2. Preliminaries

The notion of semi-abelian category was introduced in [Reference Janelidze, Márki and Tholen11] by Janelidze, Márki and Tholen, in order to provide a categorical setting which would capture algebraic properties of groups, rings and algebras. Let us recall that a category $\mathcal{C}$ is semi-abelian when it is finitely complete, Barr-exact, pointed, protomodular and has finite coproducts.

One notion which is central in the present article is that of split extension. Let $X,B$ be objects of a semi-abelian category $\mathcal{C}$; a split extension of B by X is a diagram:

in $\mathcal{C}$ such that $\alpha \circ \beta = \operatorname{id}_B$ and (X, k) is a kernel of α. Notice that protomodularity implies that the pair $(k,\beta)$ is jointly strongly epic, α is indeed the cokernel of k and diagram (2.1) represents an extension of B by X in the usual sense. Morphisms of split extensions are morphisms of extensions that commute with the sections. Let us observe that, again by protomodularity, a morphism of split extensions fixing X and B is necessarily an isomorphism. For an object X of $\mathcal{C}$, we define the functor:

\begin{equation*} \operatorname{SplExt}(-,X)\colon \mathcal{C}^{op} \rightarrow \textbf{Set}, \end{equation*}

which assigns to any object B of $\mathcal{C}$, the set $\operatorname{SplExt}(B,X)$ of isomorphism classes of split extensions of B by X, and to any arrow $f\colon B^{\prime}\to B$ the change of base function $f^*\colon \operatorname{SplExt}(B,X) \to \operatorname{SplExt}(B^{\prime},X)$ given by pulling back along f.

A feature of semi-abelian categories is that one can define a notion of internal action. If we fix an object X, actions on X give rise to a functor:

\begin{equation*} \operatorname{Act}(-,X)\colon \mathcal{C}^{op} \rightarrow \textbf{Set}. \end{equation*}

In fact, we will not describe explicitly internal actions, since there is a natural isomorphism of functors $\operatorname{Act}(-,X)\cong \operatorname{SplExt}(-,X)$, and split extensions are more handy to work with (we refer the interested reader to [Reference Borceux, Janelidze and Kelly2], where this isomorphism is described in detail). This justifies the terminology in the definition that follows.

Definition 2.1. A semi-abelian category $\mathcal{C}$ is action representable if for every object X in $\mathcal{C}$, the functor $\operatorname{SplExt}(-,X)$ is representable. This means that there exists an object $[X]$ of $\mathcal{C}$, called the actor of X, and a natural isomorphism:

\begin{equation*} \operatorname{SplExt}(-,X) \cong \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal{C}}(-,[X]). \end{equation*}

The prototype examples of action representable categories are the category Grp of groups and the category LieAlgR of Lie algebras over a commutative ring R. In the first case, it is well known that every split extension of B by X is represented by a homomorphism $B \rightarrow \operatorname{Aut}(X)$, where the actor $\operatorname{Aut}(X)$ of X is the group of automorphisms of the group X. In the case of Lie algebras, a split extension of B by X is represented by a homomorphism $B \rightarrow \operatorname{Der}(X)$, where $\operatorname{Der}(X)$ is the Lie algebra of derivations of X. Therefore, $\operatorname{Der}(X)$ is the actor of X.

However, the notion of action representable category has proven to be quite restrictive. For instance, in [Reference García-Martínez, Tsishyn, Van der Linden and Vienne8] the authors proved that, if a variety $\mathcal{V}$ of non-associative algebras (over a field $\mathbb{F}$ with $\operatorname{char}(\mathbb{F})\neq 2$) is action representable, then $\mathcal{V}=\mathbf{LieAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$.

In [Reference Janelidze10] Janelidze introduced a weaker notion for the representability of actions in a semi-abelian category $\mathcal{C}$.

Definition 2.2. A semi-abelian category $\mathcal{C}$ is weakly action representable if for every objext X in $\mathcal{C}$, the functor $\operatorname{SplExt}(-,X)$ admits a weak representation. This means that there exist an object T of $\mathcal{C}$ and a monomorphism of functors:

\begin{equation*} \tau\colon \operatorname{SplExt}(-,X) \rightarrowtail \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal{C}}(-,T). \end{equation*}

An object T as above is called weak actor of X; a morphism $\varphi\colon B \rightarrow T \in \operatorname{Im}(\tau_B)$ is called acting morphism.

Notice that every action representable category $\mathcal{C}$ is weakly action representable. In this case, $T=[X]$ is the actor of X, τ is a natural isomorphism and every arrow $\varphi\colon B \rightarrow [X]$ is an acting morphism.

2.1. Associative algebras

The case of associative algebras over a field $\mathbb{F}$ is studied in [Reference Janelidze10]: the category $\mathbf{AAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ of associative algebras over $\mathbb{F}$ is weakly action representable. Let us recall the basic constructions.

Given an associative algebra X, a weak actor of X is the associative algebra:

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Bim}(X)= & \ \lbrace (f*-,-*f) \in \operatorname{End}(X)\times \operatorname{End}(X)^{op}\; \vert\cdots \\ & \cdots\vert \;f*(xy)=(f*x)y, (xy)*f=x(y*f), x(f*y)=(x*f)y, \; \forall x,y \in X \rbrace, \end{align*}

of bimultipliers of X (see [Reference Mac Lane13], where they are called bimultiplications). Moreover, the isomorphism classes of split extensions of an associative algebra B by X are in bijection with the class of morphisms:

\begin{equation*} B \rightarrow \operatorname{Bim}(X), \; \; a \mapsto (a*-,-*a),\; \; \forall a \in B, \end{equation*}

which satisfy the condition:

(2.2)\begin{equation} a*(x*b)=(a*x)*b, \; \; \forall a,b \in B, \; \forall x \in X, \end{equation}

i.e. the left multiplier $a * -$ and the right multiplier $-*b$ are permutable. Notice that $(a*-,-*a)$ can be considered respectively the left and the right components of the action of $a \in B$ on X.

Equation (2.2) can be used to characterize the class of acting morphisms in the category $\mathbf{AAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$. In [Reference Mac Lane13] Mac Lane described, for a ring Λ, the Λ-bimodule structures over an abelian group K in terms of ring morphisms from Λ to the ring of bimultipliers of K. The following is a straightforward generalization to actions on an object which is not necessarily abelian.

Proposition 2.3. Let B and X be associative algebras over $\mathbb{F}$ and let

\begin{equation*} \varphi \in \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{AAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}}(B,\operatorname{Bim}(X)) \end{equation*}

defined by:

\begin{equation*} \varphi(a)=(a*_{\varphi}-,-*_{\varphi}a), \; \; \forall a \in B. \end{equation*}

Then, φ is an acting morphism if and only if

\begin{equation*} a*_{\varphi}(x*_{\varphi}b)=(a*_{\varphi}x)*_{\varphi}b, \end{equation*}

for every $a,b \in B$ and for every $x \in X$.

Proof. We recall from [Reference Janelidze10] that a weak representation of an associative algebra X is given by a pair $(\operatorname{Bim}(X),\tau)$, where

\begin{equation*} \tau\colon \operatorname{SplExt}(-,X) \rightarrowtail \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{AAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}}(-,\operatorname{Bim}(X)), \end{equation*}

is the monomorphism of functors which associate with any split extension A of B by X, as in diagram (2.1), the morphism $\varphi \colon B \rightarrow \operatorname{Bim}(X)$ defined by:

\begin{equation*} \varphi(a) = (a*_{\varphi}-,-*_{\varphi}a)=(\beta(a) \cdot_A -, - \cdot_A \beta(a)), \end{equation*}

for every $a \in B$. It follows from the associativity of the algebra A that the left multiplier $a*_{\varphi}-$ and the right multiplier $-*_{\varphi}b$ are permutable, for every $a,b \in B$. Conversely, with any morphism $\varphi \colon B \rightarrow \operatorname{Bim}(X)$ satisfying:

\begin{equation*} a*_{\varphi}(x*_{\varphi}b)=(a*_{\varphi}x)*_{\varphi}b, \qquad \forall a,b \in B, \quad \forall x \in X, \end{equation*}

we can associative the split extension of B by X given by the semi-direct product $B \lt imes X$, as in the proof of [Reference Borceux, Janelidze and Kelly2, Proposition 2.1], i.e. $\varphi \in \operatorname{Im}(\tau_B)$.

2.2. Jordan algebras

An example of variety of non-associative algebras over a field $\mathbb{F}$ which is not a weakly action representable category is given by Jordan algebras. Recall that a Jordan algebra over a field $\mathbb{F}$ is a non-associative commutative algebra $(J, \cdot)$ over $\mathbb{F}$ which satisfies the Jordan identity:

\begin{equation*} (xy)(xx)=x(y(xx)), \qquad \forall x,y \in J. \end{equation*}

In [Reference Janelidze10], Janeldize showed that every weakly action representable category is action accessible (see [Reference Bourn and Janelidze3]). In fact the variety $\textbf{JordAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ of Jordan algebras over $\mathbb{F}$ is not action accessible (see [Reference Cigoli and Mantovani5]), hence it is not weakly action representable.

3. Leibniz algebras

We assume that $\mathbb{F}$ is a field with $\operatorname{char}(\mathbb{F})\neq2$.

Definition 3.1. ([Reference Loday12])

A (right) Leibniz algebra over $\mathbb{F}$ is a vector space $\mathfrak{g}$ over $\mathbb{F}$ endowed with a bilinear map (called commutator or bracket) $\left[-,-\right]\colon \mathfrak{g}\times \mathfrak{g} \rightarrow \mathfrak{g}$ which satisfies the (right) Leibniz identity

\begin{equation*} \left[\left[x,y\right],z\right]=\left[[x,z],y\right]+\left[x,\left[y,z\right]\right], \qquad \forall x,y,z\in \mathfrak{g}. \end{equation*}

Every Lie algebra is a Leibniz algebra and every Leibniz algebra with skew-symmetric commutator is a Lie algebra. In fact, the full inclusion $i\colon \mathbf{LieAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}\rightarrow \mathbf{LeibAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ has a left adjoint $\pi\colon \mathbf{LeibAlg}_{\mathbb{F}} \rightarrow \mathbf{LieAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ that associates, with every Leibniz algebra $\mathfrak{g}$, its quotient $\mathfrak{g}/\mathfrak{g}^{\operatorname{ann}}$, where $\mathfrak{g}^{\operatorname{ann}}=\langle \left[x,x\right] |\,x\in \mathfrak{g} \rangle$ is the Leibniz kernel of $\mathfrak{g}$. Note that $\mathfrak{g}^{\operatorname{ann}}$ is an abelian algebra.

We define the left and the right centre of a Leibniz algebra:

\begin{equation*} \operatorname{Z}_l(\mathfrak{g})=\left\{x\in \mathfrak{g} \,|\,\left[x,\mathfrak{g}\right]=0\right\},\qquad \operatorname{Z}_r(\mathfrak{g})=\left\{x\in \mathfrak{g} \,|\,\left[\mathfrak{g},x\right]=0\right\}, \end{equation*}

and we observe that they coincide when $\mathfrak{g}$ is a Lie algebra. The centre of $\mathfrak{g}$ is $\operatorname{Z}(\mathfrak{g})=\operatorname{Z}_l(\mathfrak{g})\cap \operatorname{Z}_r(\mathfrak{g})$. In general $\operatorname{Z}_r(\mathfrak{g})$ is an ideal of $\mathfrak{g}$, while the left centre may not even be a subalgebra.

3.1. Derivations and biderivations

The definition of derivation is the same as in the case of Lie algebras.

Definition 3.2. Let $\mathfrak{g}$ be a Leibniz algebra over $\mathbb{F}$. A derivation of $\mathfrak{g}$ is a linear map $d\colon \mathfrak{g} \rightarrow \mathfrak{g}$ such that:

\begin{equation*} d(\left[x,y\right])=\left[d(x),y\right]+\left[x,d(y)\right], \qquad \forall x,y\in \mathfrak{g}. \end{equation*}

The right multiplications of $\mathfrak{g}$ are particular derivations called inner derivations and an equivalent way to define a Leibniz algebra is to say that the (right) adjoint map $\operatorname{ad}_x=\left[-,x\right]$ is a derivation, for every $x\in \mathfrak{g}$. On the other hand the left adjoint maps are not derivations in general.

With the usual bracket $\left[d_1,d_2\right]=d_1\circ d_2 - d_2\circ d_1$, the set $\operatorname{Der}(\mathfrak{g})$ is a Lie algebra and the set $\operatorname{Inn}(\mathfrak{g})$ of all inner derivations of $\mathfrak{g}$ is an ideal of $\operatorname{Der}(\mathfrak{g})$. Furthermore, $\operatorname{Aut}(\mathfrak{g})$ is a Lie group and the associated Lie algebra is $\operatorname{Der}(\mathfrak{g})$.

The definitions of anti-derivation and biderivation for a Leibniz algebra were introduced by Loday in [Reference Loday12].

Definition 3.3. An anti-derivation of a Leibniz algebra $\mathfrak{g}$ is a linear map $D\colon \mathfrak{g} \rightarrow \mathfrak{g}$ such that:

\begin{equation*} D([x,y])=[D(x),y]-[D(y),x], \qquad \forall x,y \in \mathfrak{g}. \end{equation*}

One can check that, for every $x \in \mathfrak{g}$, the left multiplication $\operatorname{Ad}_x=[x,-]$ defines and anti-derivation. We observe that in the case of Lie algebras, there is no difference between a derivation and an anti-derivation.

Remark 3.4. The set of anti-derivations of a Leibniz algebra $\mathfrak{g}$ has a $\operatorname{Der}(\mathfrak{g})$-module structure with the multiplication:

\begin{equation*} d \cdot D = [D,d]= D \circ d - d \circ D, \end{equation*}

for every $d \in \operatorname{Der}(\mathfrak{g})$ and for every anti-derivation D.

Definition 3.5. Let $\mathfrak{g}$ be a Leibniz algebra. A biderivation of $\mathfrak{g}$ is a pair (d, D) where d is a derivation and D is an anti-derivation, such that:

\begin{equation*} [x,d(y)]=[x,D(y)], \qquad \forall x,y \in \mathfrak{g}. \end{equation*}

The set of all biderivations of $\mathfrak{g}$, denoted by $\operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{g})$, has a Leibniz algebra structure with the bracket:

\begin{equation*} [(d,D),(d^{\prime},D^{\prime})]=(d \circ d^{\prime} - d^{\prime} \circ d, D \circ d^{\prime} - d^{\prime} \circ D), \quad \forall (d,D),(d,D^{\prime}) \in \operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{g}), \end{equation*}

and it is possible to define a Leibniz algebra morphism:

\begin{equation*} \mathfrak{g} \rightarrow \operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{g}) \end{equation*}

by

\begin{equation*} x \mapsto (-\operatorname{ad}_x, \operatorname{Ad}_x), \; \; \forall x \in \mathfrak{g}. \end{equation*}

The pair $(-\operatorname{ad}_x, \operatorname{Ad}_x)$ is called inner biderivation of $\mathfrak{g}$ and the set of all inner biderivations forms a Leibniz subalgebra of $\operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{g})$. We refer the reader to [Reference Mancini, Albuquerque, Brox, Martínez and Saraiva14] for a complete classification of the Leibniz algebras of biderivations of low-dimensional Leibniz algebras over a general field $\mathbb{F}$ with $\operatorname{char}(\mathbb{F}) \neq 2$.

3.2. Split extensions of Leibniz algebras

By studying biderivations of a Leibniz algebra $\mathfrak{h}$, we can classify the split extensions with kernel $\mathfrak{h}$. This relies on the correspondence between actions and split extensions available in any semi-abelian category, as explained in $\S$2. Since the variety of Leibniz algebra is a category of interest (see [Reference Orzech16]), it is convenient here to describe internal actions in terms of the so-called derived actions.

Definition 3.6. Let

be a split extension of Leibniz algebras. The pair of bilinear maps

\begin{equation*} l\colon \mathfrak{g} \times \mathfrak{h} \rightarrow \mathfrak{h}, \; \; \; r\colon \mathfrak{h} \times \mathfrak{g} \rightarrow \mathfrak{h}, \end{equation*}

defined by

\begin{equation*} l_x(b)=[s(x),i(b)]_{\hat{\mathfrak{g}}}, \qquad r_y(a)=[i(a),s(y)]_{\hat{\mathfrak{g}}}, \quad \forall x,y \in \mathfrak{g}, \quad \forall a,b \in \mathfrak{h}, \end{equation*}

where $l_x=l(x,-)$ and $r_y=r(-,y)$, is called the derived action of $\mathfrak{g}$ on $\mathfrak{h}$ associated with the split extension (3.1).

Given a pair of bilinear maps

\begin{equation*} l\colon \mathfrak{g} \times \mathfrak{h} \rightarrow \mathfrak{h}, \qquad \; r\colon \mathfrak{h} \times \mathfrak{g} \rightarrow \mathfrak{h}, \end{equation*}

one can define a bilinear operation on the direct sum of vector spaces $\mathfrak{g} \oplus \mathfrak{h}$

\begin{equation*} [(x,a),(y,b)]_{(l,r)}=([x,y]_{\mathfrak{g}},[a,b]_{\mathfrak{h}}+l_x(b)+r_y(a)), \; \; \forall (x,a),(y,b) \in \mathfrak{g} \oplus \mathfrak{h}. \end{equation*}

By Theorem 2.4 in [Reference Orzech16], this defines a Leibniz algebra structure on $\mathfrak{g} \oplus \mathfrak{h}$ if and only if the pair (l, r) is a derived action of $\mathfrak{g}$ on $\mathfrak{h}$. This in turn is equivalent to a set of conditions on the pair (l, r), as explained in the following proposition, which is a special case of Proposition 1.1 in [Reference Datuashvili7].

Proposition 3.7. $(\mathfrak{g} \oplus \mathfrak{h}, [-,-]_{(l,r)})$ is a Leibniz algebra if and only if

  1. (L1) $r_x([a,b])=[r_x(a),b]+[a,r_x(b)]$;

  2. (L2) $l_x([a,b])=[l_x(a),b]-[l_x(b),a]$;

  3. (L3) $[a,r_x(b)+l_x(b)]=0$;

  4. (L4) $r_{[x,y]}=[r_y,r_x]=r_y \circ r_x - r_x \circ r_y$;

  5. (L5) $l_{[x,y]}=[r_y,l_x]=r_y \circ l_x - l_x \circ r_y$;

  6. (L6) $l_x \circ (l_y + r_y)=0$;

for every $x,y \in \mathfrak{g}$ and for every $a,b \in \mathfrak{h}$. The resulting Leibniz algebra is the semi-direct product of $\mathfrak{g}$ and $\mathfrak{h}$ and it is denoted by $\mathfrak{g} \lt imes \mathfrak{h}$.

Remark 3.8. Notice that, for any split extension (3.1) and the corresponding derived action (l, r), there is an isomorphism of Leibniz algebra split extensions:

where $i_1,i_2,\pi_1$ are the canonical injections and projection and $\theta \colon \mathfrak{g} \lt imes \mathfrak{h} \rightarrow \hat{\mathfrak{g}}$ is defined by $\theta(x,a)=s(x)+i(a)$, for every $(x,a) \in \mathfrak{g} \oplus \mathfrak{h}$.

Remark 3.9. The first three equations of Proposition 3.7 state that, for every $x \in \mathfrak{g}$, the pair

\begin{equation*} (-r_x,l_x) \end{equation*}

is a biderivation of the Leibniz algebra $\mathfrak{h}$. Moreover, from the equalities (L4)–(L5), we have that the linear map

\begin{equation*} \varphi\colon \mathfrak{g} \rightarrow \operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{h}) \end{equation*}

defined by

\begin{equation*} \varphi(x)=(-r_x,l_x), \qquad \forall x \in \mathfrak{g} \end{equation*}

is a Leibniz algebra morphism. Indeed

\begin{equation*} \varphi([x,y]_{\mathfrak{g}})=(-r_{[x,y]_{\mathfrak{g}}},l_{[x,y]_{\mathfrak{g}}})=(-[r_y,r_x],[r_y,l_x]) \end{equation*}

and

\begin{equation*} [\varphi(x),\varphi(y)]_{\operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{h})}=[(-r_x,l_x),(-r_y,l_y)]_{\operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{h})}=([-r_x,-r_y],[l_x,-r_y])= \end{equation*}
\begin{equation*} =([r_x,r_y],-[l_x,r_y])=(-[r_y,r_x],[r_y,l_x]). \end{equation*}

On the other hand, given a Leibniz algebra morphism

\begin{equation*} \varphi\colon \mathfrak{g} \rightarrow \operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{h}) \end{equation*}

with notation

\begin{equation*} \varphi(x)=([\![-,x]\!],[\![x,-]\!]), \qquad \forall x \in \mathfrak{g}, \end{equation*}

satisfying

\begin{equation*} [\![x,[\![y,a]\!]-[\![a,y]\!]]\!]=0, \qquad \forall x,y \in \mathfrak{g}, \quad \forall a \in \mathfrak{h}, \end{equation*}

we can associate the split extension:

where the Leibniz algebra structure of $\mathfrak{g} \oplus \mathfrak{h}$ is given by

\begin{equation*} [(x,a),(y,b)]_{\varphi}=([x,y]_{\mathfrak{g}},[a,b]_{\mathfrak{h}}+[\![x,b]\!]-[\![a,y]\!]), \qquad \forall (x,a),(y,b) \in \mathfrak{g} \oplus \mathfrak{h}. \end{equation*}

However a generic morphism from $\mathfrak{g}$ to $\operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{h})$ needs not give rise to a split extension, as the following example shows.

Example 3.10. [Reference Cigoli, Metere and Montoli6] Let $\mathfrak{g}=\mathbb{F}$ be the abelian one-dimensional algebra. Then the morphism $\varphi\colon \mathbb{F} \rightarrow \operatorname{Bider}(\mathbb{F})=\operatorname{End}(\mathbb{F})^2$ defined by:

\begin{equation*} \varphi(a)=(d_a,D_a), \end{equation*}

where

\begin{equation*} d_a(x)=-ax, \; D_a(x)=ax, \qquad \forall a,x \in \mathbb{F} \end{equation*}

does not define a split extension of $\mathbb{F}$ by itself. Indeed, in general

\begin{equation*} D_a(D_b(x)-d_b(x))=a(bx-(-bx))=2abx \neq 0. \end{equation*}

Example 3.11. (The (bi-)adjoint extension)

Let $\mathfrak{g}$ be a Leibniz algebra and consider the canonical action of $\mathfrak{g}$ on itself given by the pair of linear maps

\begin{equation*} r_x=\operatorname{ad}_x=[-,x], \qquad \forall x \in \mathfrak{g}, \end{equation*}
\begin{equation*} l_y=\operatorname{Ad}_y=[y,-], \qquad \forall y \in \mathfrak{g}. \end{equation*}

We have a split extension of $\mathfrak{g}$ by itself with associated morphism

\begin{equation*} \mathfrak{g} \rightarrow \operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{g}) \end{equation*}

defined by

\begin{equation*} x \rightarrow (-\operatorname{ad}_x,\operatorname{Ad}_x), \qquad \forall x \in \mathfrak{g}, \end{equation*}

which obviously satisfies the condition

\begin{equation*} \operatorname{Ad}_x \circ (\operatorname{Ad}_y+\operatorname{ad}_y)=0, \qquad \forall x,y \in \mathfrak{g}. \end{equation*}

Indeed, for every $z \in \mathfrak{g}$

\begin{equation*} [x,[y,z]+[z,y]]=[x,[y,z]]+[x,[z,y]]= \end{equation*}
\begin{equation*} =[[x,y],z]-[[x,z],y]+[[x,z],y]-[[x,y]z]=0 \end{equation*}

Thus the Leibniz algebra morphism which defines the inner biderivations of $\mathfrak{g}$ is associated with the canonical (bi-)adjoint extension of $\mathfrak{g}$ by itself.

Example 3.12. Let $\mathfrak{h}$ be a Leibniz algebra. It is well known that (see [Reference Casas, Datuashvili and Ladra4] for more details), if $\mathfrak{h}$ has trivial centre (i.e. $\operatorname{Z}(\mathfrak{h})=0$) or if $\mathfrak{h}$ is perfect (which means that $[\mathfrak{h},\mathfrak{h}]=\mathfrak{h}$), then for every $(d,D),(d^{\prime},D^{\prime}) \in \operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{h})$ we have

\begin{equation*} D(D^{\prime} (x)-d^{\prime} (x))=0, \qquad \forall x \in \mathfrak{h}. \end{equation*}

Thus, given any Leibniz algebra $\mathfrak{g}$, we can associate a split extension of $\mathfrak{g}$ by $\mathfrak{h}$ with any morphism

\begin{equation*} \mathfrak{g} \rightarrow \operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{h}) \end{equation*}

and $\operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{h})$ is the actor of $\mathfrak{h}$.

Remark 3.13. Let $\mathfrak{g}$ and $\mathfrak{h}$ be Lie algebras and let $\hat{\mathfrak{g}}$ be a Lie algebra split extension of $\mathfrak{g}$ by $\mathfrak{h}$. Then, as observed above, we have that

\begin{equation*} \hat{\mathfrak{g}} \cong (\mathfrak{g} \oplus \mathfrak{h}, [-,-]_r), \end{equation*}

where the Lie bracket is defined by

\begin{equation*} [(x,a),(y,b)]_r=([x,y]_{\mathfrak{g}},[a,b]_{\mathfrak{h}}-r_x(b)+r_y(a)), \quad \forall (x,a),(y,b) \in \mathfrak{g} \oplus \mathfrak{h}. \end{equation*}

In this case the left component of the action of $\mathfrak{g}$ on $\mathfrak{h}$ is defined by

\begin{equation*} l_x(b)=-r_x(b), \; \; \forall x \in \mathfrak{g}, \; \forall b \in \mathfrak{h}, \end{equation*}

thus the equation (L6) is automatically satisfied and every morphism

\begin{equation*} \mathfrak{g} \rightarrow \operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{h}), \; \; x \mapsto ([\![-,x]\!],[\![-,x]\!]), \qquad \forall x \in \mathfrak{g} \end{equation*}

represents a split extension of $\mathfrak{g}$ by $\mathfrak{h}$ in the category $\mathbf{LieAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$. Moreover the subalgebra of $\operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{h})$

\begin{equation*} \lbrace (d,d) \; | \; d \in \operatorname{Der}(\mathfrak{h}) \rbrace \end{equation*}

is a Lie algebra isomorphic to $\operatorname{Der}(\mathfrak{h})$.

We can now claim the following result.

Theorem 3.14. Let $\mathfrak{g}$ and $\mathfrak{h}$ be Leibniz algebras over $\mathbb{F}$.

  1. (i) The isomorphism classes of split extensions of $\mathfrak{g}$ by $\mathfrak{h}$ are in bijection with the Leibniz algebra morphisms

    \begin{equation*} \varphi\colon \mathfrak{g} \rightarrow \operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{h}), \qquad \varphi(x)=([\![-,x]\!],[\![x,-]\!]), \quad \forall x \in \mathfrak{g}, \end{equation*}

    which satisfy the condition

    (3.2)\begin{equation} [\![x,[\![y,a]\!]-[\![a,y]\!]]\!]=0, \qquad \forall x,y \in \mathfrak{g}, \quad \forall a \in \mathfrak{h}. \end{equation}
  2. (ii) The category $\mathbf{LeibAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ of Leibniz algebras over $\mathbb{F}$ is weakly action representable.

  3. (iii) A weak actor of an object $\mathfrak{h}$ in $\mathbf{LeibAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ is the Leibniz algebra $\operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{h})$.

  4. (iv) $\varphi \in \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{LeibAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}}(\mathfrak{g},\operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{h}))$ is an acting morphism if and only if it satisfies condition (3.2).

Proof.

  1. (i) The first statement follows from Remark 3.9.

  2. (ii) Given any Leibniz algebra $\mathfrak{h}$, we take $T=\operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{h})$ and we define τ in the following way: for every Leibniz algebra $\mathfrak{g}$, the component

    \begin{equation*} \tau_{\mathfrak{g}}\colon \operatorname{SplExt}(\mathfrak{g},\mathfrak{h}) \rightarrow \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{LeibAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}}(\mathfrak{g},\operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{h})) \end{equation*}

    is the morphism in Set which associates with any split extension:

    the morphism $\varphi_{(l,r)}\colon \mathfrak{g} \rightarrow \operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{h})$ defined by

    \begin{equation*} x \mapsto (-r_x,l_x), \qquad \forall x \in \mathfrak{g} \end{equation*}
    (see Remark 3.6). The transformation τ is natural. Indeed, for every Leibniz algebra morphism $f\colon \mathfrak{g}' \rightarrow \mathfrak{g}$, it is easy to check that the following diagram in Set:

    is commutative. Moreover, for every Leibniz algebra $\mathfrak{g}$, the morphism $\tau_{\mathfrak{g}}$ is an injection since every element of $\operatorname{SplExt}(\mathfrak{g},\mathfrak{h})$ is uniquely determined by the corresponding action of $\mathfrak{g}$ on $\mathfrak{h}$, i.e. by the pair of bilinear maps

    \begin{equation*} l \colon \mathfrak{g} \times \mathfrak{h} \rightarrow \mathfrak{h}, \qquad r\colon \mathfrak{h} \times \mathfrak{g} \rightarrow \mathfrak{h}\,. \end{equation*}

    Thus τ is a monomorphism of functors and the category $\mathbf{LeibAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ is weakly action representable.

  3. (iii) It follows immediately from (ii) that a weak actor of $\mathfrak{h}$ is the Leibniz algebra of biderivations $\operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{h})$.

  4. (iv) Finally $\varphi \in \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{LeibAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}}(\mathfrak{g},\operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{h}))$ is an acting morphism if and only if it defines a split extension of $\mathfrak{g}$ by $\mathfrak{h}$, i.e. if and only if it satisfies the condition

    \begin{equation*} [\![x,[\![y,a]\!]-[\![a,y]\!]]\!]=0, \qquad \forall x,y \in \mathfrak{g}, \; \forall a \in \mathfrak{h}. \end{equation*}

4. Categories of interest

The result of the previous section can be viewed as a particular case of Proposition 4.1 below, that is valid more in general for categories of interest. In [Reference Casas, Datuashvili and Ladra4] the authors studied the problem of representability of actions for a category of interest $\mathcal{C}$. They introduced a corresponding category $\mathcal{C}_G$ of objects satisfying a suitable smaller set of identities than $\mathcal{C}$, so that $\mathcal{C}$ becomes a subvariety of $\mathcal{C}_G$. They proved that, for every object X in $\mathcal{C}$, there exists an object $\operatorname{USGA}(X)$ of $\mathcal{C}_G$, called universal strict general actor of X, with the following property: for every object B in $\mathcal{C}$ and for every action ξ of B on X, there exists a unique morphism $\varphi\colon B \rightarrow \operatorname{USGA}(X)$ in $\mathcal{C}_G$ such that ξ is uniquely determined by the action of $\varphi(B)$ on X. It was clear from their investigation that categories of interest are not action representable in general. In fact, Gray showed in [Reference Gray9] that a category of interest may not even be weakly action representable. However, from the results in [Reference Casas, Datuashvili and Ladra4], we can deduce the following.

Proposition 4.1. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a category of interest and let X be an object of $\mathcal{C}$. Then there exists a monomorphism of functors

\begin{equation*} \tau \colon \operatorname{Act}(-,X) \rightarrowtail \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal{C}_G}(-,\operatorname{USGA}(X)). \end{equation*}

If moreover $\operatorname{USGA}(X)$ is an object of $\mathcal{C}$, then the pair $(\operatorname{USGA}(X),\tau)$ is a weak representation of $\operatorname{Act}(-,X)$.

Proof. By the above discussion, for every object B in $\mathcal{C}$, there exists an injection

\begin{equation*} \tau_B \colon \operatorname{Act}(B,X) \rightarrowtail \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal{C}_G}(B,\operatorname{USGA}(X)). \end{equation*}

We want to prove that the collection $\lbrace \tau_B \rbrace_{B \in \mathcal{C}}$ gives rise to a natural transformation τ.

Consider in $\mathcal{C}$ a morphism $f\colon B^{\prime} \rightarrow B$ and an action ξ of B on X. The naturality of τ is equivalent to saying that

\begin{equation*} \tau_{B^{\prime}} (f^*(\xi))=(\tau_B(\xi)) \circ f, \end{equation*}

for every such f and ξ, where $f^*=\operatorname{Act}(f,X)$. This follows immediately from Definition 3.6 of [Reference Casas, Datuashvili and Ladra4].

Since $\mathcal{C}$ is a full subcategory of $\mathcal{C}_G$, when $\operatorname{USGA}(X)$ belongs to $\mathcal{C}$, the pair $(\operatorname{USGA}(X),\tau)$ is a weak representation for the functor $\operatorname{Act}(-,X)$.

Corollary 4.2. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a category of interest. If $\operatorname{USGA}(X)$ is an object of $\mathcal{C}$ for every X in $\mathcal{C}$, then $\mathcal{C}$ is a weakly action representable category.

In view of the last results, an explicit description of the USGA in concrete cases is very useful. Two examples were studied in [Reference Casas, Datuashvili and Ladra4]:

  • the category $\textbf{AAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$, where $\operatorname{USGA}(X)=\operatorname{Bim}(X)$, for every associative algebra X;

  • the category $\textbf{LeibAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$, where $\operatorname{USGA}(\mathfrak{g})=\operatorname{Bider}(\mathfrak{g})$, for every Leibniz algebra $\mathfrak{g}$.

In the next section, we provide such description in the case of Poisson algebras.

5. Poisson algebras

The main goal of this section is to study the representability of actions of the category $\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ of Poisson algebras and to prove that the full subcategory $\mathbf{CPoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ of commutative Poisson algebra is not weakly action representable. We assume again that $\mathbb{F}$ is a field with $\operatorname{char}(\mathbb{F}) \neq 2$.

Definition 5.1. A Poisson algebra over $\mathbb{F}$ is a vector space P over $\mathbb{F}$ endowed with two bilinear maps

\begin{equation*} \cdot\colon P \times P \rightarrow P \end{equation*}
\begin{equation*} [-,-]\colon P \times P \rightarrow P \end{equation*}

such that $(P,\cdot)$ is an associative algebra, $(P,[-,-])$ is a Lie algebra and the Poisson identity holds:

\begin{equation*} [p,qt]=[p,q]t+q[p,t], \qquad \forall p,q,t \in P, \end{equation*}

i.e. the adjoint map $[p,-]\colon P \rightarrow P$ is a derivation of the associative algebra $(P,\cdot)$. A Poisson algebra P is said to be commutative if $(P, \cdot)$ is a commutative associative algebra.

Now, we recall the main properties of split extension of Poisson algebras.

Definition 5.2. Let

be a split extension of Poisson algebras. The triple of bilinear maps

\begin{equation*} l \colon P \times V \rightarrow V, \; \; \; r\colon V \times P \rightarrow V,\; \; \; [\![-,-]\!]\colon P \times V \rightarrow V \end{equation*}

defined by

\begin{equation*} p \ast y = s(p) \cdot_{\hat{P}} i(y), \quad x \ast q = i(x) \cdot_{\hat{P}} s(q), \quad [\![p,y]\!]=[s(p),i(x)]_{\hat{P}}, \quad \forall p,q \in P, \quad \forall x,y \in V, \end{equation*}

where $p \ast -=l(p,-)$ and $- \ast q=r(-,q)$, is called the derived action of P on V associated with the split extension (5.1).

As in the case of Leibniz algebras, given a triple of bilinear maps

\begin{equation*} l \colon P \times V \rightarrow V, \; \; \; r\colon V \times P \rightarrow V, \; \; \; [\![-,-]\!]\colon P \times V \rightarrow V, \end{equation*}

one can define two bilinear operations on $P \oplus V$

\begin{equation*} (p,x)\diamond(q,y)=(pq,x\cdot_V y + p \ast y + x \ast q), \end{equation*}

and

\begin{equation*} \{(p,x),(q,y)\}=([p,q],[x,y]_V+[\![p,y]\!]-[\![q,x]\!]), \end{equation*}

for every $(p,x),(q,y) \in P \oplus V$, and this defines a Poisson algebra structure on the vector space $P \oplus V$ if and only if the triple $(l,r,[\![-,-]\!])$ is a derived action of P on V.

This is equivalent to a set of conditions on $(l,r,[\![-,-]\!])$, as explained in the following proposition (again, see Theorem 2.4 in [Reference Orzech16] and Proposition 1.1 in [Reference Datuashvili7]).

Proposition 5.3. $(P \oplus V, \diamond, \{-,-\})$ is a Poisson algebra if and only if

  1. (P1) $(P \oplus V, \diamond)$ is an associative algebra, i.e. the following equalities hold

    • $p \ast (x \cdot_V y)=(p \ast x)\cdot_V y$;

    • $(x \cdot_V y) \ast p = x \cdot_V (y \ast p)$;

    • $x \cdot_V (p \ast y) = (x \ast p) \cdot_V y$;

    • $(p \ast x) \ast q = p \ast (x \ast q)$;

    • $(pq)\ast x = p \ast (q \ast x)$;

    • $x \ast (pq)= (x \ast p) \ast q$;

  2. (P2) $(P \oplus V, \{-,-\})$ is a Lie algebra, i.e.

    • $[\![p,[x,y]_V]\!]=[[\![p,x]\!],y]_V+[x,[\![p,y]\!]]_V$;

    • $[\![[p,q],x]\!]=[\![p,[\![q,x]\!]]\!] - [\![q,[\![p,x]\!]]\!]$;

  3. (P3) $[\![pq,x]\!]=p\ast [\![q,x]\!] + [\![p,x]\!]\ast q$;

  4. (P4) $[p,q] \ast x = p \ast [\![q,x]\!] - [\![q,p \ast x]\!]$;

  5. (P5) $x \ast [p,q]=[\![q,x]\!] \ast p - [\![q,x \ast p]\!]$;

  6. (P6) $p \ast [x,y]_V=[p \ast x, y]_V - [\![p,y]\!] \cdot_V x$;

  7. (P7) $[x,y]_V \ast p = [x \ast p,y]_V - x \cdot_V [\![p,y]\!]$;

  8. (P8) $[\![p,x \cdot_V y]\!] = [\![p,x]\!] \cdot_V y + x \cdot_V [\![p,y]\!]$;

for every $p,q \in P$ and for every $x,y \in V$. The resulting Poisson algebra is the semi-direct product of P and V and it is denoted by $P \lt imes V$.

Remark 5.4. We recall that, for any split extension (5.1), we have an isomorphism of split extensions:

where $i_1,i_2,\pi_1$ are the canonical injections and projection and $\theta \colon P \lt imes V \rightarrow \hat{P}$ is defined by $\theta(p,x)=s(p)+i(x)$, for every $(p,x) \in P \oplus V$.

The category $\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ has two obvious forgetful functors to the categories $\mathbf{AAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ and $\mathbf{LieAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$. Now, the category of Lie algebras is action representable: any split extension of a Lie algebra P by another Lie algebra V corresponds to a Lie algebra morphism $\varphi\colon P \rightarrow \operatorname{Der}(V)$. On the other hand, we know that $\mathbf{AAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ is a weakly action representable category and a split extension of an associative algebra P by another associative algebra V corresponds to an associative algebra morphism $\varphi\colon P \rightarrow \operatorname{Bim}(V)$. Notice that $\operatorname{Der}(V)$ is an actor, while $\operatorname{Bim}(V)$ is only a weak actor (see $\S$2), in fact they are both universal strict general actors in the sense of [Reference Casas, Datuashvili and Ladra4]. It is not clear whether the category $\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ is weakly action representable, therefore in this section, we start by describing a universal strict general actor $\operatorname{USGA}(V)$, when V is a Poisson algebra. As explained in $\S$4, in general $\operatorname{USGA}(V)$ lies in a larger category $\mathcal{C}_G$, which in this case is the category $\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2$ of algebras over $\mathbb{F}$ with two not necessarily associative bilinear operations. Thus, we look for a suitable subspace

\begin{equation*} [V] \leq \operatorname{Bim}(V) \times\operatorname{Der}(V) \end{equation*}

and this must be endowed with two bilinear operations

\begin{equation*} \cdot_{[V]},[-,-]_{[V]} \colon [V] \times [V] \rightarrow [V] \end{equation*}

such that we can associate with every split extension of P by V in $\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ a morphism

\begin{equation*} \phi\colon P \rightarrow [V] \end{equation*}

in $\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2$, defined by:

\begin{equation*} \phi(p)=(p \ast -, - \ast p, [\![p,-]\!]), \qquad \forall p \in P. \end{equation*}

Thus

\begin{equation*} \phi(pq)=\phi(p) \cdot_{[V]} \phi(q) \end{equation*}

and

\begin{equation*} \phi([p,q])=[\phi(p),\phi(q)]_{[V]}. \end{equation*}

In other words, by using Proposition 5.3, the operations in $[V]$ must satisfy the following two conditions:

  • $\matrix{{(p * - , - * p,[[p, - ]]){ \cdot _{[V]}}(q * - , - * q,[[q, - ]]) = } \hfill \cr { = ((pq) * - , - * (pq),p * [[q, - ]] + [[p, - ]] * q)} \hfill \cr } $

  • $\matrix{ {{{[(p* - , - *p,[[p, - ]]),(q* - , - *q,[[q, - ]])]}_{[V]}} = } \hfill \cr { = (p*[[q, - ]] - [[q,p* - ]],[[q, - ]]*p - [[q, - *p]],[[p,[[q, - ]]]] - [[q,[[p, - ]]]])} \hfill \cr } $,

for every $p,q \in P$.

We define $[V]$ as the subspace of all triples $(f,F,d)$ of $\operatorname{Bim}(V) \times \operatorname{Der}(V)$ satisfying the following set of equations:

  1. (V1) $f([x,y]_V)=[f(x),y]_V-d(y)\cdot_V x$;

  2. (V2) $F([x,y]_V)=[F(x),y]_V-x \cdot_V d(y)$;

  3. (V3) $d(x \cdot_V y) = d(x) \cdot_V y + x \cdot_V d(y)$;

for every $x,y \in V$.

Remark 5.5. The subspace $[V]$ is not empty, since

\begin{equation*} (x \cdot_V -, - \cdot_V x, [x,-]_V) \in [V] \end{equation*}

for every $x \in V$. This triples are called inner multipliers of V.

Now we are ready to enunciate and prove the following.

Theorem 5.6. Let $(V,\cdot_V,[-,-]_V)$ be a Poisson algebra.

  1. (i) The space $[V]$ with the bilinear operations

    \begin{equation*} (f,F,d) \cdot_{[V]} (f^{\prime},F^{\prime},d^{\prime})=(f \circ f^{\prime}, F^{\prime} \circ F, f \circ d^{\prime} + F^{\prime} \circ d) \end{equation*}
    \begin{equation*} [(f,F,d),(f^{\prime},F^{\prime},d^{\prime})]_{[V]}=(f \circ d^{\prime}-d^{\prime} \circ f, F \circ d^{\prime}-d^{\prime} \circ F, d \circ d^{\prime} - d^{\prime} \circ d) \end{equation*}

    is an object of $\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2$;

  2. (ii) The set $\operatorname{Inn}(V)$ of all inner multipliers of V is a subalgebra of $[V]$ and it is a Poisson algebra itself;

  3. (iii) For every object $(P,\cdot,[-,-])$ in $\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$, the set of isomorphism classes of split extension of P by V are in bijection with the morphisms

    \begin{equation*} \phi=(\phi_1,\phi_2,\phi_3)\colon P \rightarrow [V] \end{equation*}

    in $\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2$, such that $(\phi_1,\phi_2)\colon P \rightarrow \operatorname{Bim}(V)$ is an acting morphism in the category $\mathbf{AAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$.

  4. (iv) There exists a monomorphism of functors

    \begin{equation*} \tau\colon \operatorname{SplExt}(-,V) \rightarrowtail \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2}(-,[V]), \end{equation*}

    such that an arrow $(\phi \colon P \rightarrow [V]) \in \operatorname{Im}(\tau_P)$ if and only if $(\phi_1,\phi_2) $ is an acting morphism in $\mathbf{AAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$.

  5. (v) If $([V], \cdot_{[V]}, [-,-]_{[V]})$ is a Poisson algebra, then the pair $([V],\tau)$ becomes a weak representation for the functor $\operatorname{SplExt}(-,V)$.

Proof.

  1. (i) In order to show that $[V]$ is an object of $\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2$, we have to prove that the bilinear operations are well defined. We observe that

    \begin{equation*} (f \circ d^{\prime} - d^{\prime} \circ f, F \circ d^{\prime} - d^{\prime} \circ F) \in \operatorname{Bim}(V) \end{equation*}

    and

    \begin{equation*} f \circ d^{\prime} + F^{\prime} \circ d \in \operatorname{Der}(V), \end{equation*}

    for every $(f,F,d),(f^{\prime},F^{\prime},d^{\prime}) \in [V]$. This follows from equations (V1)–(V3), since

    \begin{equation*} (f \circ d^{\prime} - d^{\prime} \circ f)(x \cdot_V y)=(f \circ d^{\prime} - d^{\prime} \circ f)(x) \cdot_V y, \end{equation*}
    \begin{equation*} (F \circ d^{\prime} - d^{\prime} \circ F)(x \cdot_V y)=x \cdot_V (F \circ d^{\prime} - d^{\prime} \circ F)(y), \end{equation*}
    \begin{equation*} x \cdot_V (f \circ d^{\prime} - d^{\prime} \circ f)(y)=(F \circ d^{\prime} - d^{\prime} \circ F)(x) \cdot_V y \end{equation*}

    and

    \begin{equation*} (f \circ d^{\prime} + F^{\prime} \circ d)([x,y]_V)= \end{equation*}
    \begin{equation*} =[(f \circ d^{\prime} + F^{\prime} \circ d)(x),y]_V+[x,(f \circ d^{\prime} + F^{\prime} \circ d)(y)]_V, \end{equation*}

    for every $x,y \in V$. Moreover the resulting triples:

    \begin{equation*} (f \circ f^{\prime}, F^{\prime} \circ F, f \circ d^{\prime} + F^{\prime} \circ d), \end{equation*}
    \begin{equation*} (f \circ d^{\prime}-d^{\prime} \circ f, F \circ d^{\prime}-d^{\prime} \circ F, d \circ d^{\prime} - d^{\prime} \circ d), \end{equation*}

    belong to $[V]$, i.e. they satisfy equations (V1)–(V3). Here we show this statement only for the second triple, since for the first triple the computations are similar. We have that:

    \begin{equation*} (f \circ d^{\prime} - d^{\prime} \circ f)[x,y]_V= \end{equation*}
    \begin{equation*} =f([d^{\prime} (x),y]_V+[x,d^{\prime} (y)]_V)-d^{\prime} ([f(x),y]_V-d(y)\cdot_V x)= \end{equation*}
    \begin{equation*} =[f(d^{\prime} (x)),y]_V-d(d^{\prime} (y)) \cdot_V x - [d^{\prime} (f(x)),y]_V+d^{\prime} (d(y)) \cdot_V x= \end{equation*}
    \begin{equation*} =[(F \circ d^{\prime} - d^{\prime} \circ F)(x),y]_V-(d \circ d^{\prime}-d^{\prime} \circ d)(y) \cdot_V x. \end{equation*}

    In the same way, one can check that

    \begin{equation*} (F \circ d^{\prime} - d^{\prime} \circ F)[x,y]_V=[(F \circ d^{\prime} - d^{\prime} \circ F)(x),y]_V-x \cdot_V (d \circ d^{\prime} -d^{\prime} \circ d)(y). \end{equation*}

    Finally

    \begin{equation*} (d \circ d^{\prime} -d^{\prime} \circ d)(x \cdot_V y)= \end{equation*}
    \begin{equation*} =d(d^{\prime} (x) \cdot_V y +x \cdot_V d^{\prime} (y)) - d^{\prime} (d(x) \cdot_V y +x \cdot_V d(y))= \end{equation*}
    \begin{equation*} =d(d^{\prime} (x))\cdot_V y + x \cdot_V d(d^{\prime} (y)) - d^{\prime} (d(x)) \cdot_V y - x \cdot_V d^{\prime} (d(y)) = \end{equation*}
    \begin{equation*} = (d \circ d^{\prime} -d^{\prime} \circ d)(x) \cdot_V y + x \cdot_V (d \circ d^{\prime} -d^{\prime} \circ d)(y). \end{equation*}

    Thus, $[V]$ is an object of $\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2$.

  2. (ii) The subspace $\operatorname{Inn}(V)$ is precisely the image of the morphism:

    \begin{equation*} \operatorname{Inn} \colon V \rightarrow [V] \end{equation*}

    defined by:

    \begin{equation*} x \mapsto (x \cdot_V -, - \cdot_V x, [x,-]_V), \qquad \forall x \in V. \end{equation*}
  3. (iii) We associate with any split extension.

    in the category $\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ the morphism:

    \begin{equation*} P \rightarrow [V] \end{equation*}

    in $\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2$, defined by:

    \begin{equation*} p \rightarrow (p \ast -, - \ast p, [\![p,-]\!]), \qquad \forall p \in P, \end{equation*}

    where the bimultiplier $(p \ast -, - \ast p)$ and the derivation $[\![p,-]\!]$ are as in Remark 5.2. Since $\hat{P}$ is also a split extension of $(P,\cdot)$ by $(V, \cdot_V)$ in the category $\mathbf{AAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$, we have that

    \begin{equation*} p \ast (x \ast q) = (p \ast x) \ast q, \end{equation*}

    for every $p,q \in P$ and $x \in V$. Conversely, given a Poisson algebra P and a morphism $\phi=(\phi_1,\phi_2,\phi_3) \in \operatorname{Hom}_{\textbf{NAlg}^2_{\mathbb{F}}}(P,[V])$ defined by:

    \begin{equation*} \phi(p)=(p*_{\phi}-,-*_{\phi}p,[\![p,-]\!]_{\phi}), \qquad \forall p \in P, \end{equation*}

    such that $(\phi_1,\phi_2)\colon P \rightarrow \operatorname{Bim}(V)$ is an acting morphism in $\mathbf{AAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$, we can associate with ϕ the split extension of Poisson algebras:

    where

    \begin{equation*} (p,x) \diamond_{(\phi_1,\phi_2)} (q,y) = (pq, x \cdot_V y + p*_{\phi}y + x*_{\phi}q) \end{equation*}

    and

    \begin{equation*} \{(p,x),(q,y)\}_{\phi_3}=([p,q],[x,y]_V + [\![p,y]\!]_{\phi}-[\![q,x]\!]_{\phi}), \end{equation*}

    for every $(p,x),(q,y) \in P \oplus V$. One can check that these bilinear operations define a Poisson algebra structure on $P \oplus V$.

  4. (iv) We define

    \begin{equation*} \tau\colon \operatorname{SplExt}(-,V) \rightarrowtail \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2}(-,[V]) \end{equation*}

    in the following way: for every object P in $\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$, τP associates with any split extensions of P by V the morphism:

    \begin{equation*} P \rightarrow [V] \end{equation*}

    defined as in (iii). By the description of split extensions in Remark 5.2, each component τP is injective since every morphism which belongs to $\operatorname{Im}(\tau_P)$ determines a unique split extension of P by V. One can check that the family of injections:

    \begin{equation*} \tau_P\colon \operatorname{SplExt}(P,V) \rightarrowtail \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2}(P,[V]), \end{equation*}

    is natural in P. By (iii), an arrow $\phi=(\phi_1,\phi_2,\phi_3) \in \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2}(P,[V])$ belongs to $\operatorname{Im}(\tau_P)$ if and only if $(\phi_1,\phi_2) \in \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{AAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}}(P,\operatorname{Bim}(V))$ is an acting morphism.

  5. (v) The last statement follows from Proposition 4.1, since $[V]=\operatorname{USGA}(V)$.

The following example shows that $([V], \cdot_{[V]}, [-,-]_{[V]})$ is not in general a Poisson algebra.

Example 5.7. Let $V=\mathbb{F}^2$ be the the abelian two-dimensional algebra (i.e. $x \cdot_V y=[x,y]_V=0$, for every $x,y \in V$). It turns out that

\begin{equation*} [V]=\operatorname{End}(V)^3 \cong \operatorname{M}_2(\mathbb{F})^3, \end{equation*}

as vector spaces, since every linear endomorphism of V is represented by a $2 \times 2$ matrix with respect to a fixed basis. Then the bilinear operations of $[V]$ can be represented as:

\begin{equation*} (A,B,C) \cdot_{[V]} (A^{\prime},B^{\prime},C^{\prime})=(AA^{\prime}, B^{\prime}B, AC^{\prime}+B^{\prime}C), \end{equation*}
\begin{equation*} [(A,B,C),(A^{\prime},B^{\prime},C^{\prime})]_{[V]}=(AC^{\prime}-C^{\prime}A, BC^{\prime}-C^{\prime}B, CC^{\prime}-C^{\prime}C), \end{equation*}

for every $(A,B,C),(A^{\prime},B^{\prime},C^{\prime}) \in \operatorname{M}_2(\mathbb{F})^3$ and one can check that $[V]$ is not a Poisson algebra since, for instance, the bracket $[-,-]_{[V]}$ is not skew-symmetric.

By Theorem 3.9 of [Reference Casas, Datuashvili and Ladra4], we can deduce that the category $\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ is not action representable. Indeed, since for a Poisson algebra V, $\operatorname{USGA}(V)$ is not in general a Poisson algebra, then V does not admit an actor.

The following remark shows that there are special cases where τ becomes a natural isomorphism.

Remark 5.8. Let $(V,\cdot_V,[-,-]_V)$ be a Poisson algebra such that the annihilator

\begin{equation*}\operatorname{Ann}(V)=\lbrace x \in V \; | \; x \cdot_V y = y \cdot_V x = 0, \; \forall y \in V \rbrace\end{equation*}

of the associative algebra $(V,\cdot_V)$ is trivial or $(V^2,\cdot_V)=(V,\cdot_V)$. In this case we have that

(5.2)\begin{equation} f \circ F^{\prime} = F^{\prime} \circ f, \end{equation}

for every $(f,F),(f^{\prime},F^{\prime}) \in \operatorname{Bim}(V)$ (see [Reference Casas, Datuashvili and Ladra4] for more details). It follows that, for any other Poisson algebra P, every arrow

\begin{equation*} \phi \colon P \rightarrow [V] \end{equation*}

belongs to $\operatorname{Im}(\tau_P)$ and we have a natural isomorphism

\begin{equation*} \operatorname{SplExt}(-,V) \cong \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2}(-,[V]). \end{equation*}

Notice that the conditions $\operatorname{Ann}(V)=0$ and $V^2=V$ are not necessary to obtain equation (5.2). For instance, if $V=\mathbb{F}$ is the abelian one-dimensional algebra, then $\operatorname{Ann}(V)=V$, $V^2=0$, $[V] \cong \mathbb{F}^3$ as vector spaces (every linear endomorphism of V is of the form $\varphi_{a} \colon x \mapsto a x$, with $a\in \mathbb{F}$) and every left multiplier of V commutes with every right multiplier. Moreover, it turns out that

\begin{equation*} (\varphi_{a},\varphi_{b},\varphi_{c}) \cdot_{[V]} (\varphi_{a^{\prime}},\varphi_{b^{\prime}},\varphi_{c^{\prime}}) = (\varphi_{aa^{\prime}},\varphi_{b^{\prime}b},\varphi_{ac^{\prime}+b^{\prime}c}), \end{equation*}

is an associative product and

\begin{equation*} [(\varphi_{a},\varphi_{b},\varphi_{c}), (\varphi_{a^{\prime}},\varphi_{b^{\prime}},\varphi_{c^{\prime}})]_{[V]}= (0,0,0). \end{equation*}

Thus, $[V]$ is a Poisson algebra and

\begin{equation*} \operatorname{SplExt}(-,V) \cong \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}}(-,[V]), \end{equation*}

i.e. $[V]$ is the actor of V. This is a special case of the following more general result.

Theorem 5.9. Let V be a Poisson algebra such that equation (5.2) holds. The following statements are equivalent:

  1. (i) $[V]$ is a Poisson algebra;

  2. (ii) the functor $\operatorname{SplExt}(-,V)$ admits a weak representation;

  3. (iii) $[V]$ is the actor of V, hence $\operatorname{SplExt}(-,V)$ is representable.

Proof. (i) $\Rightarrow$ (iii). If $[V]$ is an object of $\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$, we have a natural isomorphism

\begin{equation*}\operatorname{SplExt}(-,V) \cong \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}}(-,[V]).\end{equation*}

(iii) $\Rightarrow$ (ii). If $[V]$ is the actor of V, then the pair $([V],\tau)$ is trivially a weak representation of $\operatorname{SplExt}(-,V)$.

(ii) $\Rightarrow$ (i). Finally, if we suppose that the functor $\operatorname{SplExt}(-,V)$ admits a weak representation $(M,\mu)$, then, by composition, we have a monomorphism of functors:

\begin{equation*} i^{\ast} \circ \mu \circ \tau^{-1}\colon \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2}(-,[V]) \rightarrowtail \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2}(-,M), \end{equation*}

where τ is the natural transformation defined in Theorem 5.6 and

\begin{equation*} i^{\ast}\colon \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}}(-,M) \rightarrowtail \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2}(-,M) \end{equation*}

is given by the full inclusion of the category $\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ in $\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2$. From the Yoneda Lemma, it follows that $[V]$ is a subobject of M in the category $\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2$. But M is also an object of $\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$, thus $[V]$ is a Poisson algebra.

Now, if we suppose that the category $\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ is weakly action representable, then the functor $\operatorname{SplExt}(-,V)$ admits a weak representation for every Poisson algebra V. By the last theorem, $[V]$ would be an object of $\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$, for any Poisson algebra V satisfying equation (5.2). Thus an explicit example of a Poisson algebra V of this kind such that $[V]$ is not an object of $\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ would prove that the category is not weakly action representable. This is a result that we obtain for the subvariety $\mathbf{CPoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ of commutative Poisson algebras.

If V is a commutative Poisson algebra, then we define $[V]_c$ as the algebra of all pairs $(f,d) \in \operatorname{M}(V) \times \operatorname{Der}(V)$, where

\begin{equation*} \operatorname{M}(V)=\lbrace f \in \operatorname{End}(V) \; | \; f(xy)=f(x)y, \; \forall x,y \in V \rbrace, \end{equation*}

is the associative algebra of multipliers of V, such that:

  1. (V1) $f([x,y]_V)=[f(x),y]_V-d(y)\cdot_V x$;

  2. (V2) $d(x \cdot_V y) = d(x) \cdot_V y + x \cdot_V d(y)$;

endowed with the two bilinear operations

\begin{equation*} (f,d) \cdot_{[V]_c} (f^{\prime},d^{\prime})=(f \circ f^{\prime}, f \circ d^{\prime} + f^{\prime} \circ d), \end{equation*}
\begin{equation*} [(f,d),(f^{\prime},d^{\prime})]_{[V]_c}=(f \circ d^{\prime}-d^{\prime} \circ f, d \circ d^{\prime} - d^{\prime} \circ d), \end{equation*}

for every $(f,d),(f^{\prime},d^{\prime}) \in [V]_c$. One can check that $[V]_c$ is isomorphic to the subalgebra of $[V]$ of triples of the form $(f,f,d)$.

Using the notation of Theorem 5.6, one can associate, with any split extension of P by V in $\mathbf{CPoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$, a morphism:

\begin{equation*} \phi \colon P \rightarrow [V]_c, \; \; p \mapsto (p \ast -, [\![p,-]\!]), \qquad \forall p \in P, \end{equation*}

in $\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2$. Conversely, if P and V are commutative Poisson algebras, every morphism $\phi \colon P \rightarrow [V]_c$ in $\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2$ defines a commutative Poisson algebra split extension. Indeed, by (iii) of Theorem 5.6, such $\phi \in \operatorname{Im}(\tau_P)$ if and only if $p \mapsto p \ast -$ defines an action in the category $\mathbf{CAAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ of commutative associative algebra over $\mathbb{F}$, and moreover $\operatorname{Act}_{\mathbf{CAAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}}(-,V) \cong \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{AAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}}(-,\operatorname{M}(V))$ (see [Reference Borceux, Janelidze and Kelly2]). Thus there exists a natural isomorphism:

\begin{equation*} \operatorname{SplExt}(-,V) \cong \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2}(-,[V]_c), \end{equation*}

and we have the following characterization whose proof is similar to the one of Theorem 5.9.

Theorem 5.10. Let V be a commutative Poisson algebra. The following statements are equivalent:

  1. (i) $[V]_c$ is a commutative Poisson algebra;

  2. (ii) the functor $\operatorname{SplExt}(-,V)$ admits a weak representation;

  3. (iii) $[V]_c$ is the actor of V, hence $\operatorname{SplExt}(-,V)$ is representable.

This allows us to conclude with the following.

Remark 5.11. The category $\mathbf{CPoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ of commutative Poisson algebras is not weakly action representable. Otherwise the functor $\operatorname{SplExt}(-,V)$ would admit a weak representation, for any object V in $\mathbf{CPoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$. By Theorem 5.10, this would be equivalent to saying that $[V]_c$ is a commutative Poisson algebra. We get a contradiction since, if for example $V=\mathbb{F}^2$ is the two-dimensional abelian algebra, then

\begin{equation*} [V]_c=\operatorname{M}(V) \times \operatorname{Der}(V)=\operatorname{End}(V)^2, \end{equation*}

as a vector space, and it is easy to check that the bilinear operation:

\begin{equation*} (f,d) \cdot_{[V]_c} (f^{\prime},d^{\prime})=(f \circ f^{\prime}, f \circ d^{\prime} + f^{\prime} \circ d), \end{equation*}

is not commutative.

Open problem

Eventually, our investigation does not clarify whether the category $\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ of all Poisson algebras over $\mathbb{F}$ is weakly action representable or not. A key point in the proof of Theorem 5.9 is the fact that equation (5.2) is equivalent to saying that the monomorphism of functors:

\begin{equation*} \tau\colon \operatorname{SplExt}(-,V) \rightarrowtail \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathbf{NAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}^2}(-,[V]), \end{equation*}

is a natural isomorphism. Since in the commutative case equation (5.2) is always satisfied, we were able to find the counterexample of Remark 5.11.

Thanks to Theorem 5.9, finding a concrete counterexample of a Poisson algebra V satisfying equation (5.2) and such that $[V]$ is not a Poisson algebra would prove that $\mathbf{PoisAlg}_{\mathbb{F}}$ is not weakly action representable.

Funding statement

This work is supported by University of Palermo, University of Turin and the “National Group for Algebraic and Geometric Structures, and their Applications” (GNSAGA-INdAM).

References

Borceux, F., Janelidze, G. and Kelly, G. M., Internal object actions, Comment. Math. Univ. Carolin. 46(2) (2005), 235255.Google Scholar
Borceux, F., Janelidze, G. and Kelly, G. M., On the representability of actions in a semi-abelian category, Theory Appl. Categ. 14 (1) (2005), 244286.Google Scholar
Bourn, D. and Janelidze, G., Centralizers in action accessible categories, Cah. Topol. Géom. Différ. Catég. 50(3) (2009), 211232.Google Scholar
Casas, J. M., Datuashvili, T. and Ladra, M., Universal strict general actors and actors in categories of interest, Appl. Categ. Structures 18(1) (2010), 85114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cigoli, A. S. and Mantovani, S., Action accessibility via centralizers, J. Pure Appl. Algebra 216 (8-9) (2012), 18521865.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cigoli, A. S., Metere, G. and Montoli, A., Obstruction theory in action accessible categories, J. Algebra 385 (3) (2013), 2746.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Datuashvili, T., Cohomologically trivial internal categories in categories of groups with operations, Appl. Categ. Structures 3(3) (1995), 221237.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
García-Martínez, X., Tsishyn, M., Van der Linden, T. and Vienne, C., Algebras with representable representations, Proc. Edinb. Math. Soc. 64(2) (2021), 555573.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gray, J. R. A., A note on the relationship between action accessible and weakly action representable categories, (2022), Preprint, available at https://arXiv:2207.06149.Google Scholar
Janelidze, G., Central extensions of associative algebras and weakly action representable categories, Theory Appl. Categ. 38 (36) (2022), 13951408.Google Scholar
Janelidze, G., Márki, L. and Tholen, W., Semi-abelian categories, J. Pure Appl. Algebra 168(2) (2002), 367386.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loday, J. -L., Une version non commutative des algèbres de Lie: les algebres de Leibniz, Enseign. Math. 39(3-4) (1993), 269293.Google Scholar
Mac Lane, S., Extensions and obstructions for rings, Illinois J. Math. 2(3) (1958), 316345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mancini, M.. Biderivations of low-dimensional Leibniz algebras, in Non-Associative Algebras and Related Topics. NAART 2020, Springer Proceedings in Mathematics & Statistics, (eds. Albuquerque, H., Brox, H.J., Martínez, H.J.C., Saraiva, H.J.C.P.), (Cham: Springer, 2023), pp. pp. Vol 427(8).Google Scholar
Montoli, A., Action accessibility for categories of interest, Theory Appl. Categ. 23 (1) (2010), 721.Google Scholar
Orzech, G., Obstruction theory in algebraic categories, I, J. Pure Appl. Algebra 2(4) (1972), 287314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar