Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-vdxz6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T19:57:38.230Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Schleiermacher's Metaphysical Critique of Miracles

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 January 2009

William A. Dembski
Affiliation:
Origins & Design 600 Davis St, 3 West Evanston, IU. 60201–4419

Extract

In The Christian Faith Schleierrmcher offers three critiques of miracles—a pragmatic, an epistemological, and a metaphysical critique. Of these three critiques, by far the most important is Schleiermacher's metaphysical critique. In his own day, it was this critique that decisively distinguished Schleiermacher's account of miracles from the traditional orthodox account. In contemporary theological debates over contingency and divine action, it is this critique that underlies much of the continued skepticism towards miracles. Now as then, Schleiermacher's metaphysical critique of miracles continues to be a live issue

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Scottish Journal of Theology Ltd 1996

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 443 note 1 Schleiermacher's pragmatic and epistemological critiques are found in Schleiermacher (1830, §14.3, pp. 71–73), whereas his metaphysical critique is found in Schleiermacher (1830, §47, pp. 178–84).

page 443 note 2 Cf. Wiles (1986).

page 444 note 3 Schleiermacher (1830, p. viii).

page 444 note 4 Schleiermacher (1830, § 4).

page 444 note 5 Schleiermacher (1830, §14.3, p. 71).

page 445 note 6 Schleiermacher (1830, §14.3, p. 71).

page 445 note 7 Schleiermacher (1830, $14.3, pp. 71–72).

page 446 note 8 Schleiermacher (1830, §99, p. 422 and §122, p. 566).

page 446 note 9 See for instance my article ‘On the Very Possibility of Intelligent Design’ in Moreland (1994, pp. 113–38).

page 447 note 10 Quoted in Loos (1966, p. 19, n. 1). The quote may be translated, ‘Of course no one was as skilled at veiling what in the end he really did and did not hold of miracles.’ The pun centers on the word translated ‘veiling’—Schleiermacher literally means ‘veil maker’.

page 448 note 11 See especially Schleiermacher (1830, §§11 and 100).

page 448 note 12 Schleiermacher (1830, §14.3, p. 72).

page 448 note 13 Schleiermacher (1830, §14.3, pp. 72–3), italics added. Though Schleiermacher seems in this passage to be granting more room to miracles than Spinoza, in point of fact Schleiermacher is agreeing with Spinoza that designating something a miracle constitutes an expression of ignorance. The locus dassicus for Spinoza's view of miracles is found in chapter 6 of Spinoza's Tractatus Theologico-Politicus—see Spinoza (1670, ch. 6).

page 449 note 14 Schleiermacher (1830, §47, p. 181).

page 449 note 15 Schleiermacher (1830, §47, p. 180).

page 449 note 16 Schleiermacher (1830, §14.3, p. 71).

page 450 note 17 Schleiermacher (1830, §47, pp. 181–2). Actually, Schleiermacher introduces an unnecessary subtlety here, distinguishing miracles in which something that was supposed to happen fails to happen (negative miracles) from miracles in which something that was not supposed to happen does happen (positive miracles). The logic is the same for both cases, however, since in either case something still happens (even the failure of some event happening constitutes an event).

page 452 note 18 Quoted from Brandt (1941, p. 214).

page 452 note 19 Newton (1958, p. 302).

page 452 note 20 Pearcey and Thaxton (1994, p. 90).

page 453 note 21 More than half of Newton's writings were concerned solely with religion and alchemy—see Gregory's introduction to Spinoza's Tractatus Theologico-Polilicus in Spinoza (1670, p. 9).

page 453 note 22 Locke (1690, p. 382). See also the paragraphs on miracles in Locke (1695).

page 453 note 23 Humc (1748, ch. 10).

page 453 note 24 Peter Lipton's model of Inference to the Best Explanation (IBE) might even make ‘divine intervention’ the best explanation for a given phenomenon—see Lipton (1991).

page 454 note 25 Bradleyand Swartz (1979, pp. 147–149).

page 454 note 26 Alan Richardson (1942, p. 127) takes this position in his discussion of Jesus' miracles: ‘Only those who came in faith understood the meaning of the acts of power. That is why any discussion of the Gospel miracles must begin, as we began, with a consideration of the biblical theology, with the faith which illuminates their character and purpose.’

page 455 note 27 Quoted in Brandt (1941, p. 36).

page 455 note 28 Schleiermacher (1799, p. 40).

page 455 note 29 Brandt (1941, p. 146, n. *).

page 456 note 30 Compare Spinoza (1677, bk. 1, def. 7) with Schleiermacher (1830, §81.2, p. 334).

page 456 note 31 Spinoza (1670, p. 124).

page 456 note 32 Spinoza (1670, p. 126).

page 457 note 33 For a helpful historical discussion of the traditional understanding of miracles, see Loos (1965, pp. 37–42).

page 458 note 34 See Loos (1965, p. 43).

page 458 note 35 Tennant (1925, p. 10).

page 459 note 36 Process theologians, for instance, do this all the time—see Case-Winters (1990, pt. 3).

page 459 note 37 Schleiermacher and Spinoza employ the language of ‘ordination’, ‘will’, and ‘decrees’ throughout their work, and use these terms synonymously. When applied to God this language signifies the necessity of what is determined coming to pass. See Schleiermacher (1830, §54, p. 211 ff.) and Spinoza (1670, ch. 6) for examples of how they use these terms.

page 461 note 38 Schleiermacher (1830, §47, p. 180).

page 461 note 38 Schleiermacher (1830, §47, p. 180).

page 461 note 40 By efficacious prayer I mean prayer which makes a difference in the sense that without the prayer being offered, things would have turned out differently. In the subsequent discussion of efficacious prayer I have been helped enormously by Nancey Murphy's article ‘Does Prayer Make a Difference?’—see Murphy (1989).

page 462 note 41 Cf. Schleiermacher's discussion of human responsibility for sin in Schleiermacher (1830, §81.2, p. 334).

page 462 note 42 Weatherford (1991, p. 28).