Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7fkt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T11:45:06.876Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

VOLUNTARY IMAGINATION: A FINE-GRAINED ANALYSIS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 June 2020

ILARIA CANAVOTTO
Affiliation:
INSTITUTE FOR LOGIC, LANGUAGE AND COMPUTATION UNIVERSITY OF AMSTERDAM 1098 XG AMSTERDAM, THE NETHERLANDSE-mail: [email protected]
FRANCESCO BERTO
Affiliation:
ARCHÉ UNIVERSITY OF ST. ANDREWS ST. ANDREWS KY16 9AJ, UNITED KINGDOM and INSTITUTE FOR LOGIC, LANGUAGE AND COMPUTATION UNIVERSITY OF AMSTERDAM 1098 XG AMSTERDAM, THE NETHERLANDSE-mail: [email protected]
ALESSANDRO GIORDANI
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY OF MILAN LARGO AGOSTINO GEMELLI 1, 20123 MILANO, ITALYE-mail: [email protected]

Abstract

We study imagination as reality-oriented mental simulation (ROMS): the activity of simulating nonactual scenarios in one’s mind, to investigate what would happen if they were realized. Three connected questions concerning ROMS are: What is the logic, if there is one, of such an activity? How can we gain new knowledge via it? What is voluntary in it and what is not? We address them by building a list of core features of imagination as ROMS, drawing on research in cognitive psychology and the philosophy of mind. We then provide a logic of imagination as ROMS which models such features, combining techniques from epistemic logic, action logic, and subject matter semantics. Our logic comprises a modal propositional language with non-monotonic imagination operators, a formal semantics, and an axiomatization.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Alchourrón, C. E., Gärdenfors, P., & Makinson, D. (1985). On the logic of theory change: Partial meet functions for contraction and revision. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 50, 510–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baltag, A., Moss, L. S., & Solecki, S. (1998). The logic of public announcements, common knowledge, and private suspicions. In Gilboa, I., editor. Proceedings of TARK 98. Evanston, IL: Morgan and Kaufmann, pp. 4356.Google Scholar
Baltag, A., & Smets, S. (2008). A qualitative theory of dynamic interactive belief revision. In Bonanno, G., van der Hoek, W., and Wooldridge, M., editors. Logic and the Foundations of Game and Decision Theory. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press, pp. 958.Google Scholar
Belnap, N., Perloff, M., & Xu, M. (2001). Facing the Future: Agents and Choices in Our Indeterministic World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Berto, F. (2018a). Aboutness in imagination. Philosophical Studies, 175, 18711886.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berto, F (2018b). Taming the runabout imagination ticket. Synthese, online first, doi: 10.1007/s11229--018--1751--6Google Scholar
Byrne, R. (2005). The Rational Imagination. How People Create Alternatives to Reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrne, R., & Girotto, V. (2009). Cognitive processes in counterfactual thinking. In Markman, K. D., Klein, W., and Suhr, J. A., editors. Handbook of Imagination and Mental Simulation. New York: Taylor and Francis, pp. 151160.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. (2002). Does conceivability entail possibility? In Gendler, T. S., & Hawthorne, J., editors. Conceivability and Possibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 145199.Google Scholar
Currie, G. (1990). The Nature of Fiction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, J., & Over, D. (2004). If. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, K. (2016). Angellic content. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 45(2), 199226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fraude-Koivisto, T. S., Wuerz, D., & Gollwitzer, P. M. (2009). Implementation intentions. In Markman, K. D., Klein, W., and Suhr, J. A., editors. Handbook of Imagination and Mental Simulation. New York: Taylor and Francis, pp. 6987.Google Scholar
Gendler, T. S. (2000). The puzzle of imaginative resistance. Journal of Philosophy, 97, 5581.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giordani, A. (2018). Ability and responsibility in general action logic. In Broersen, J. M., Condoravdi, C., Shyam, N., and Pigozzi, G., editors. Deontic Logic and Normative Systems – 14th International Conference (DEON 2018). London: College Publications, pp. 121138.Google Scholar
Giordani, A (2019). Axiomatizing the logic of iagination. Studia Logica, 107, 639657.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grove, A. (1988). Two modellings for theory change. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 17, 157170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and Belief. An Introduction to the Logic of the Two Notions. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Horty, J. F. (2001). Agency and Deontic Logic. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1984). Choices, values, and frames. American Psychologist, 39, 341350.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kind, A. (2016). Imagining under constraints. In Kind, A., and Kung, P., editors. Knowledge Through Imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 145159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kind, A., & Kung, P. (2016). Knowledge through Imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kosslyn, S., & Moulton, S. T. (2009). Mental imagery and implicit memory. In Markman, K. D., Klein, W., and Suhr, J. A., editors. Handbook of Imagination and Mental Simulation. New York: Taylor and Francis, pp. 3552.Google Scholar
Langland-Hassan, P. (2016). On choosing what to imagine. In Kind, A., and Kung, P., editors. Knowledge Through Imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 6184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lewis, D (1988). Relevant implication. Theoria, 54(3), 161174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Markman, K. D., Klein, W., & Surh, J. A. (2009). Handbook of Imagination and Mental Simulation. New York: Taylor and Francis.Google Scholar
Nichols, S., & Stich, S. P. (2003). Mindreading. An Integrated Account of Pretence, Self-Awareness, and Understanding Other Minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oaksford, M., & Chater, N. (2010). Cognition and Conditionals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In Rescher, N., editor. Studies in Logical Theory. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 98112.Google Scholar
Stanovich, K. E., & West, R. F. (2000). Individual differences in reasoning: Implications for the rationality debate? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23(5), 645665.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
van Benthem, J. (2007). Dynamic logic for belief revision. Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logic, 17, 129155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Leeuwen, N. (2016). The imaginative agent. In Kind, A., and Kung, P., editors. Knowledge Through Imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 85111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walton, K. (1990). Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of Representational Arts. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wansing, H. (2017). Remarks on the logic of imagination. A step towards understanding doxastic control through imagination. Synthese, 194(8), 28432861.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, T. (2007). The Philosophy of Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, T (2016). Knowing by imagining. In Kind, A., and Kung, P., editors. Knowledge Through Imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 113123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yablo, S. (1993). Is conceivability a guide to possibility? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 53, 142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yablo, S (2014). Aboutness. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar