Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T22:15:59.719Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

ACCESSIBILISM DEFINED

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 October 2016

Abstract

Accessibilism is a version of epistemic internalism on which justification is determined by what is accessible to the subject. I argue that misunderstandings of accessibilism have hinged on a failure to appreciate an ambiguity in the phrase ‘what is accessible to the subject’. I first show that this phrase may either refer to the very things accessible to the subject, or instead to the facts about which things are accessible to her. I then discuss Ralph Wedgwood's (2002: 350–2) argument that accessibilism absurdly implies that an infinite regress of facts, each more complex than the last, must be accessible to the subject. I show that this regress objection only threatens the ‘very things’ disambiguation of accessibilism, not the ‘facts about’ disambiguation. After this, I discuss the relationships between the motivations for accessibilism and these two disambiguations. We will see that these motivations appear to support each disambiguation. But I will argue this appearance depends on a mistake. Just as only the ‘facts about’ disambiguation escapes the regress objection, it is also the only disambiguation which enjoys genuine support from the motivations for accessibilism. For these reasons, I recommend that future discussions of accessibilism focus on the ‘facts about’ disambiguation.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Alston, W. 1989. Epistemic Justification: Essays in the Theory of Knowledge. London: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. 1973. Belief, Truth, and Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Audi, R. 1998. Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge. New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Ball, B. and Blome-Tillmann, M. 2013. ‘Indexical Reliabilism and the New Evil Demon.’ Erkenntnis, 78: 1317–36.Google Scholar
Bergmann, M. 2006. Justification without Awareness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Berker, S. 2008. ‘Luminosity Regained.’ Philosophers’ Imprint, 8: 122.Google Scholar
BonJour, L. 1980. ‘Externalist Theories of Empirical Knowledge.’ Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5: 5373.Google Scholar
BonJour, L. 1985. The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Broome, J. 2013. Rationality Through Reasoning. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Brown, J. 2007. ‘Externalism in Mind and Epistemology.’ In Goldberg, S. C. (ed.), Internalism and Externalism in Semantics and Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Carroll, L. 1895. ‘What the Tortoise Said to Achilles.’ Mind, 4: 278–80.Google Scholar
Cohen, S. 1984. ‘Justification and Truth.’ Philosophical Studies, 46: 279–95.Google Scholar
Conee, E. and Feldman, R. 2001. ‘Internalism Defended.’ American Philosophical Quarterly, 38: 118.Google Scholar
Fales, E. 2014. ‘Turtle Epistemology.’ Philosophical Studies, 169: 339–54.Google Scholar
Fumerton, R. 1995. Metaepistemology and Skepticism. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Gibbons, J. 2006. ‘Access Externalism.’ Mind, 115: 1939.Google Scholar
Ginet, C. 1975. Knowledge, Perception, and Memory. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. 1999. ‘Internalism Exposed.’ Journal of Philosophy, 96: 271–93.Google Scholar
Greco, D. 2014. ‘Could KK Be OK?Journal of Philosophy, 111: 169–97.Google Scholar
Kim, J. (ed.) 2002. Supervenience. Brookfield, VT: Ashgate Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Levin, J. 2013. ‘Functionalism.’ In Zalta, E. N. (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/functionalism/.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1986. On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. 1993. Warrant: The Current Debate. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pryor, J. 2001. ‘Highlights of Recent Epistemology.’ British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 52: 95124.Google Scholar
Schroeder, M. 2007. Slaves of the Passions. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schroeder, M. 2008. ‘Having Reasons.’ Philosophical Studies, 139: 5771.Google Scholar
Setiya, K. 2007. Reasons Without Rationalism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, M. 1987. ‘The Humean Theory of Motivation.’ Mind, 96: 3661.Google Scholar
Srinivasan, A. 2015. ‘Are We Luminous?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, XC: 294319.Google Scholar
Turri, J. 2010. ‘On the Relationship between Propositional and Doxastic Justification.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80: 312–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Cleve, J. 1990. ‘Supervenience and Closure.’ Philosophical Studies, 58: 225–38.Google Scholar
Wedgwood, R. 2002. ‘Internalism Explained.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65: 349–69.Google Scholar
Wedgwood, R. 2006. ‘The Normative Force of Reasoning.’ Noûs, 40: 660–86.Google Scholar
Wedgwood, R. 2007. The Nature of Normativity. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wedgwood, R. 2013. ‘Doxastic Correctness.’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Suppl. 87: 3854.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1995. ‘Internal Reasons and the Obscurity of Blame.’ In Making Sense of Humanity, pp. 3545. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. 2000. Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar