Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T23:49:06.351Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Deliberative Exchange, Truth, and Cognitive Division of Labour: A Low-Resolution Modeling Approach

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 January 2012

Abstract

This paper develops a formal framework to model a process in which the formation of individual opinions is embedded in a deliberative exchange with others. The paper opts for a low-resolution modeling approach and abstracts away from most of the details of the social-epistemic process. Taking a bird's eye view allows us to analyze the chances for the truth to be found and broadly accepted under conditions of cognitive division of labour combined with a social exchange process. Cognitive division of labour means that only some individuals are active truth seekers, possibly with different capacities. Both mathematical tools and computer simulations are used to investigate the model. As an analytical result, the Funnel Theorem states that under rather weak conditions on the social process, a consensus on the truth will be reached if all individuals possess an arbitrarily small capacity to go for the truth. The Leading the pack Theorem states that under certain conditions even a single truth seeker may lead all individuals to the truth. Systematic simulations analyze how close agents can get to the truth depending upon the frequency of truth seekers, their capacities as truth seekers, the position of the truth (more to the extreme or more in the centre of an opinion space), and the willingness to take into account the opinions of others when exchanging and updating opinions.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Bogdan, Radu J. (ed.) 1981. Keith Lehrer. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Douven, Igor. 2008. Simulating Peer Disagreements. Manuscript.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin I. 1999. Knowledge in a Social World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gustafsson, Johan and Peterson, Martin. 2008. A Computer Simulation of the Argument from Disagreement. Manuscript.Google Scholar
Hamblin, Charles L. 1970. Fallacies. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Hamblin, Charles L. 1971. “Mathematical Models of Dialogue.” Theoria 37(2): 130–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hegselmann, Rainer. 1985. Formale Dialektik – Ein Beitrag zu einer Theorie des rationalen Argumentierens. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.Google Scholar
Hegselmann, Rainer. 2004. “Opinion Dynamics – Insights by Radically Simplifying Models.” In Gillies, D. (ed.), Laws and Models in Science, pp. 1946. London: King's College Publications.Google Scholar
Hegselmann, Rainer and Krause, Ulrich. 2002. “Opinion Dynamics and Bounded Confidence – Models, Analysis, and Simulations.” Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation (JASSS) 5(3). http://jasss.soc.surrey.ac.uk/5/3/2.htmlGoogle Scholar
Hegselmann, Rainer and Krause, Ulrich. 2005. “Opinion Dynamics Driven by Various Ways of Averaging.” Computational Economics 25(4): 381405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hegselmann, Rainer and Krause, Ulrich. 2006. “Truth and Cognitive Division of Labor – First Steps Towards a Computer Aided Social Epistemology.” Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation (JASSS) 9(3). http://jasss.soc.surrey.ac.uk/9/3/10.htmlGoogle Scholar
Krause, Ulrich. 2009. “Compromise, Consensus, and the Iteration of Means.” Elemente der Mathematik 64: 18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kurz, Sascha and Rambau, Jörg. 2006. “On the Hegselmann-Krause Conjecture in Opinion Dynamics.” Bayreuth: Working paper.Google Scholar
Lehrer, Keith. 1975. “Social Consensus and Rational Agnoiology.” Synthese 31(1): 141–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lehrer, Keith. 1976. “When Rational Disagreement is Impossible.” Nous 10(3): 327–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lehrer, Keith. 1977. “Social Information.” The Monist 60: 473–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lehrer, Keith. 1981a. “A Self Profile.” In Bogdan, R. J. (ed.), Keith Lehrer, pp. 3104. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Lehrer, Keith. 1981b. “Replies.” In Bogdan, R. J. (ed.), Keith Lehrer, pp. 223–42. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Lehrer, Keith. 1985. “Consensus and the Ideal Observer.” Synthese 62(1): 109–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lehrer, Keith and Wagner, Carl G.. 1981. Rational Consensus in Science and Society: A Philosophical and Mathematical Study. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
List, Christian. 2005. “Group Knowledge and Group Rationality: A Judgement Aggregation Perspective.” Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology 2(1): 2538.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loewer, Barry. (ed.) 1985. Consensus. Synthese 62(1) (special issue).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malarz, Krzysztof. 2006. “Truth Seekers in Opinion Dynamic Models.” International Journal of Modern Physics C 17(10): 1521–4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar