Introduction
Over the past several decades, courts and scholars in the United States and Europe have invested significant efforts in developing law in general—and private law, in particular—in line with a pluralistic view.Footnote 1 For example, pluralist conceptions of contract law are based on the notion that a single theoretical principle,Footnote 2 such as promise or efficiency, cannot encompass the entire realm of contract doctrines, or different contractual transactions between various parties. Similarly, while traditional theories of property rights conceived the notion of property on the basis of natural rights or utilitarian consequentialism,Footnote 3 today it is agreed that dimensional ‘monist’ theories cannot fully explain the value and limits of property law.Footnote 4 A comparable approach has been adopted in the study of tort law. For example, Izhak Englard has introduced the concept of complementarity—which reduces the conflict between corrective justice and distributive justice perspectives of tort law by seeking to harmonize those goals.Footnote 5 In light of all this, the lack of a comprehensive pluralist theory of corporate law seems puzzling, given that pluralist foundations of private law may, mutatis mutandis, also apply to the design of corporate governance regimes. To fill this gap, we call for designing the common law of corporations based on tailoring governance and control arrangements to firm-specific power relations resulting from agency conflicts and the unique aspects of the markets.
Generally, shareholders are perceived as the residual owners of the company who are entitled to receive the remaining returns after the company repays its obligations to its stakeholders.Footnote 6 However, as agency theory explains, the control over the company’s decision-making is in the hands of self-interested insiders who do not necessarily act to increase shareholders’ value.Footnote 7 For example, in companies with a concentrated ownership structure, blockholders have control over the firm’s business activities and can run them against the interests of minority shareholders.Footnote 8 As a result, corporate governance includes various mechanisms—such as board composition, executive pay, the market for corporate control, and gatekeepers—for redressing the costs resulting from agency relationships.Footnote 9
Nevertheless, the legal literature tends to capture the agency relationship between shareholders and management or controlling and minority shareholders in a unified fashion which does not consider the variation of power relations under the agency framework. The agency theory generally describes the consequences of insiders’ and outsiders’ interactions in the corporations’ field. However, it does not analyze the implications of differences in the power interplays between them as part of the agency relationship itself.
To design tailored corporate governance regimes as an expression of corporate laws’ diverse value, we employ the social systems theoryFootnote 10 and the framework of complexity which were developed by sociology scholars.Footnote 11 Sociological research maintains that organizations are a subset of social systems that exhibit considerable complexity in their form and features. They represent a sophisticated web of interconnectivity between human beings and their environment, by exhibiting non-linear behavior.Footnote 12 For the law to be able to predict and regulate a given behavior, it must examine the interactions between the constituent parts of the organization and its response to changes in their surroundings.Footnote 13 In conditions of complexity, the role of corporate law is to conceptualize the varied effect of participants’ heterogeneity and their interrelationships on outcomes and performance.Footnote 14 These personalized corporate governance regimes would supplement the authority of the corporations’ powerholders to independently design the mechanisms that guide their conduct as part of the private ordering approach.Footnote 15
This Essay proceeds as follows. In Part I, I differentiate between two special forms of pluralism. First, the plurality of law’s sources considers the coexistence of several systems and authoritative foundations—that some of them are not the product of the national state’s law-making—for regulating private interactions. Second, the plurality of law’s values, which reject the idea that ultimate principle can entirely explain or accommodate the richness of different doctrines in private or commercial law. In Part II, I lay the theoretical foundations for the plurality of corporate law’s values that stems from the complexity framework, and its application for studying societies and organizations. I argue that business organizations should be considered as complex adaptive systems that include constant interactions between different governance devices. To overcome the complexity involved in such interactions, courts should design internal and external corporate governance arrangements following a firm-specific view. In Part III and Part IV, I provide a legal map of the corporate governance ecosystem, by exploring the legal implications of our view for redesigning internal and external governance devices. In Part III, I discuss several governance arrangements for regulating the internal relationship between controlling and minority shareholders—such as the fiduciary duties of controlling shareholders, the regulation of related party transactions, and the officers’ duty of care. In Part IV, I analyze external governance arrangements that regulate the relationship of the company as a separate and distinct legal entity with a wide range of stakeholders and focus on the company’s goal debate. In Part V, I consider several challenges associated with implementing a firm-specific view in corporate law. I will then summarize my conclusions.
I. The Idea of Pluralism in Corporate Law
A. Pluralism in Law: A (Short) Introduction to the Literature
The traditional concept of pluralism in law was developed by legal anthropologists and sociologists who analyzed overlapping normative orders within societies that challenge the exclusive authority of the state in making and administering law.Footnote 16 It was initially related to a colonial context in which European countries placed their own legal systems on top of the indigenous system and traditions.Footnote 17 It captures the descriptive idea that in any conventional geographical boundaries of a state, there is more than one legal system. Thus, state law is not the only normative source for regulation and governance, as there are non-state systems of law that also apply for regulating the conduct of a population, community, or individual.Footnote 18 The existence of multiple and diverse systems of law that apply to a certain factual situation generates uncertainty because it involves “competing claims of authority [that] impose conflicting demands or norms … [and] may have different styles and orientations.”Footnote 19 As a result, individuals and societal groups cannot anticipate which legal regime will be applied to their conduct and lack the ability to determine the consequences of their actions in advance.
The plurality of normative orders opposes the monistic concept that regards the law as an exclusive product of the sovereign states’ actions. Pluralist scholars are motivated by the ambition to increase pluralism in the regulatory state by delegating policymaking responsibilities to private parties.Footnote 20 They consider the monistic concept to be hypothetical, and that it does not correspond to the pluralist reality of legal norms. As John Griffiths put it, “[l]egal pluralism is the fact. Legal centralism is a myth, an ideal, a claim, an illusion.”Footnote 21 Thus, scholars employ the distinction between ‘law as one’ and ‘law as many’ to capture the idea that law can only be understood as “a combination of conceptions rather than in a single conception, and in a range of linguistic forms rather than in any single form.”Footnote 22 Accordingly, pluralist theories acknowledge that there are overlapping state and non-state normative orders that are produced by a variety of actors to regulate commerce, trade, and finance.Footnote 23
Furthermore, this understanding of pluralism focuses on the interactions of the national legal orders with international normative arrangements, “whether these stem from ‘official’ sources or from unofficial sources such as transnational corporations, NGOs, [and] ‘private’ regulatory codes.”Footnote 24 These exchanges are the result of the globalization process that involves the removal of geographical and cultural distances between different societies, thereby challenging the local and national references of law. Accordingly, pluralism of law is related to exploring the relationship between ‘law’ and ‘space’ which postulates neither of them can exist without the other.Footnote 25 Therefore, any state’s support for monopoly over the creation and application of law within its geographical boundaries cannot be sustained.
While many scholars concentrated on the multiple systems of normative orders that co-exist in the private and public sphere, other scholars have explored the role of pluralism as part of articulating theoretical justifications for the normative orders themselves. For example, while monist theories of private or commercial law perceive normative institutions as a mechanism for accomplishing single or ultimate value or virtue, pluralist conceptions are grounded on the idea that a single principle cannot capture the richness of doctrines as applied to different parties, transactions, markets, and industries.Footnote 26
Because various principles provide valuable insights for comprehending the function of different legal doctrines, private law cannot be confined to a single overreaching theory or principle.Footnote 27 Diverse types of doctrines incorporate a different set of values derived from broad social theories and the exact balance between them indicates how legal institutions operate practically. Thus, private law generally encompasses values, principles, and concepts derived from law and economics, philosophy, sociology, and the behavioral sciences, and the special balance between these perspectives is accomplished through their application to “markets, risks, persons and organizations.”Footnote 28 By designing narrow rules that address specific actual interactions, doctrines’ theoretical justifications will be closely aligned with the specific factual characteristics. Put differently, by focusing on the importance of context, pluralist justifications could capture more accurately the diverse public policy issues involved in different private law doctrines.
To illustrate the last point, let us see how pluralism of values can be expressed in the specific branch of private law that is contract law. Pluralist interpretations of contract may be understood in at least three different forms. According to one view, right-based and efficiency-based perspectives best fit and justify contracting practices of different parties, such as ordinary individuals and business organizations. For example, Ethan Leib argued that types of contracts have a significant relevance for building a general theory of contracts. He demonstrated that the applicability of autonomy theories should be limited to contracts between individuals, and implantation of efficiency theories should be limited to contracts between business firms.Footnote 29
A second view posits that different theories of contract can explain and justify various kinds of transactions. Karl Llewellyn was among the first scholars to acknowledge the significance of context in interpretation and application of contract rules in specific settings, and urged for constructing specific rules for different types of transactions, such as sale, lease, or license, as well as between different types of contractors, such as merchant, consumer, minor, or arms-length parties.Footnote 30 More recently, Dagan and Heller articulated a novel pluralist theory that includes diverse types of contracts which entail different contract institutions for various social settings and commercial purposes.Footnote 31 Drawing on the work of Joseph Raz, they argue that extending autonomy should be the law’s primary concern, which requires the law to increase the range of contractual choices available.Footnote 32 Each contract institution—such as business transactions, consumer transactions, employment contracts, or family contracts—includes a distinct balance of values and thus should be governed by a separate regulative principle fit to its subject matter. Such a rich collection will enable people to freely choose their ends, principles, forms of life, and association.Footnote 33
A third view provides that different parts and doctrines of contract law are best described and justified by multiple contract theories. As explained by Eyal Zamir,
[N]otions such as respect for private will, maximization of aggregate social welfare, rectification of reliance losses and undoing of unjust enrichment, redistribution of power and wealth, fairness and equivalence of exchange, and paternalism—to name but some of the key concepts in a pluralistic contract law theory—are applicable to any modern, western system of contract law. Even if their significance and implications vary from one type of transaction to another and by different legal system, they are potentially relevant to any transaction in a great variety of systems.Footnote 34
Similarly, Prince Saprai argued, recently, that the shape, structure, and content of contract law in any particular jurisdiction should embrace a contingent attitude. Thus, instead of relying on ‘top-down’ deontic or consequentialist theory, which provides one correct answer to the entire realm of contract law, jurists should pay closer attention to the plurality of conflicting values embodied in each of the doctrines.Footnote 35
We discussed two primary forms of pluralism in law: numerous sources of law which are not restricted to national states’ geographical borders; and the richness of the theoretical justifications embodied in different private law doctrines. I argue below that the contractual perspective of corporate law and the strategies of private ordering correspond to the first perception of pluralism in law, namely the multiplicity of legitimate sources of law.
B. Private Ordering and the Plurality of Corporate Law’s Sources
Corporate law is regarded as a set of default terms that incorporators would have adopted if they could consider all possible eventualities and if transaction costs had not been prohibitive.Footnote 36 It is perceived to reduce the costs of bargaining and incorporation by providing rules that are generally efficient and are in the interest of the incorporators.Footnote 37 In particular, parties do not have to anticipate all eventualities that may arise in their relationship, because the default rules provide a nexus of contractual provisions that are available when eventualities materialize.Footnote 38 Accordingly, corporate law has an enabling function that minimizes the number of mandatory provisions, offers an optimal set of default rules, and enforces parties’ arrangements adopted in charters and bylaws.Footnote 39 Thus, various legal systems allow corporators to design governance mechanisms that differ from the standardized default rules provided by corporate statues.Footnote 40 These statues establish off-the-rack corporate rules that provide the freedom to opt-out (or in) by adopting tailored governance alternatives.Footnote 41 For instance, the board and shareholders can approve a special amendment to the corporation’s charter, such as adopting or abandoning cumulative voting, authorizing the board to amend the bylaws,Footnote 42 or waiving liability for directorial negligence.Footnote 43 By implementing a private ordering approach to varying degrees—based on myriad factors, such as firm size, product-market maturity, and industry regulations—different firms may accumulate diverse benefits.Footnote 44 In the following discussion, I focus on two examples of private ordering in corporate law.
Business Opportunities Waivers
Generally, the corporate opportunities doctrine that is embodied in the fiduciary duty of loyalty does not allow directors and officers to appropriate business opportunities that belong to the company without first revealing it to the corporation and receiving its approval to pursue it directly.Footnote 45 The formulation of the doctrine in the United States is associated with the case of Guth v. Loft,Footnote 46 that was further developed in the case of Broz v. Cellular Information Systems.Footnote 47 Accordingly, courts have to engage in a fact-intensive inquiry to identify corporate business opportunity according to four main tests:Footnote 48 (1) the line of business test, (2) the business interest or expectancy test, (3) the fairness test, and (4) the Miller two-step test, which considers both the line of business test and fairness test for determining whether an officer is allowed to allocate a corporate business opportunity to themself.Footnote 49 However, parties can avoid litigation on the allocation of business opportunity by stipulating ex-ante a waiver in the corporate charter.Footnote 50
Ex-ante waivers are considered to be efficiently preferable because they create contractual well-defined rules that clarify the allocation of business opportunity and reduce the litigation costs involved in the complex fiduciary standards of the Anglo-American law.Footnote 51 Following previous rulings that exemplified the difficulties of the undivided fiduciary model of corporate business opportunity and the benefit of allowing the company and its fiduciaries to design ex-ante contractual arrangements on the allocation of business opportunities,Footnote 52 the Delaware Assembly amended the state’s statutes by adding subsection (17) to section 122 of the Delaware General Corporation Law. It permits a corporation to
[r]enounce, in its certificate of incorporation or by action of its board of directors, any interest or expectancy of the corporation in, or in being offered an opportunity to participate in, specified business opportunities or specified classes or categories of business opportunities that are presented to the corporation or one or more of its officers, directors or stockholders.Footnote 53
Limitations on Shareholder Litigation
Scholars and practitioners argue that the law has to acknowledge certain limitations on shareholder litigation against corporations (or their directors and officers). These lawsuits are often driven by lawyers’ motivations to maximize chances of success despite the lack of a solid factual basis.Footnote 54 To overcome this difficulty, many companies in the United States adopted private ordering solutions in specific amendments to the charter and bylaws that place certain hurdles on shareholders’ ability to initiate litigation. The most prevalent provisions in this regard are forum selection clauses that restrict future litigation to the courts of a particular jurisdiction and fee-shifting provisions that impose on the losing plaintiffs an obligation to pay defendants’ attorneys’ fees.Footnote 55 In 2015, the Delaware legislature authorized forum selection provision in the charter or bylaws and prohibited any provision relating to shifting defense costs to the plaintiff.Footnote 56 These changes were made following rulings of Delaware courts that permitted bylaw provisions regarding a company’s freedom to choose the forum in which shareholder litigation will take place,Footnote 57 and upheld bylaw provisions that assign the defendant’s expenses and costs to the plaintiff if the suit is not approved.Footnote 58 However, it is important to note that the amendments to the Delaware General Corporation Law address internal corporate claims regarding the balance of power between investors and management that should be regulated by the state of incorporation. Thus, other types of shareholders claims, such as federal securities litigation, are potentially not subject to these amendments.Footnote 59
Generally, private ordering is considered to be an expression of law sources’ multiplicity because it is an important non-state governance system that regulates the conduct of business organizations and supplements the formal state system of corporate law. However, there are certain limitations on the ability of corporations and their insiders to engage in private ordering for regulating entire governance challenges.Footnote 60 First, while in theory corporate participants can control a company’s internal power relations through private ordering devices, in practice “specify[ing] all aspects of their relationship and accompanying rights and duties” entails high contracting costs.Footnote 61 Therefore, to be willing to engage with such a process, corporate participants compare between the ex-ante benefits of adhering to the default rules and the ex-ante costs of creating an extensive array of customized rules.Footnote 62 Second, courts have made clear that corporate law is not only an expression of private law but also aims to accomplish public policy goals, and private ordering devices that violate these purposes will not be enforceable.Footnote 63 For example, fiduciary obligations protect the interests of shareholders from managerial misconduct and entail a public benefit in the form of lowering the cost of raising capital to the firm. Without enforceable fiduciary duties, investors will demand higher returns in exchange for engaging with the company’s business activities, thereby increasing the firm’s capital cost.Footnote 64 Third, private ordering devices are produced by corporate insiders exclusively and, generally, stakeholders such as consumers and suppliers do not have a voice on the content of such arrangements. Therefore, there is a concern that the content of a private ordering arrangement will undermine stakeholders’ rights that are generally addressed by the doctrines of shareholders’ limited liability and corporate separate legal personality.Footnote 65 Moreover, private ordering devices should also be constrained when they are carried out in companies with concentrated ownership structure, because decision-making rights are generally allocated to controlling shareholders and their representatives on the board of directors who can act against the interests of minority shareholders.
By allowing the existence of non-state governance regimes, countries acknowledge the notion that numerous systems of law govern the conduct of business organizations, and regulation is an enterprise shared by public and private actors alike.Footnote 66 While private ordering mechanisms represent an important aspect of pluralism, they do not capture the unavoidable plurality of values embodied in governance rules that are solely a product of state law aiming to accomplish public goals.Footnote 67 Thus, the plurality of corporate laws’ sources is inherently limited because it does not reflect the richness of values embodied in governance rules that are not chosen by corporate organs but are instead imposed by courts following certain factual scenarios. The diversity of corporate laws’ values invites a discussion on whether the system of one-size-fits-all should be sustained or instead whether courts should have to produce nuanced rules that capture more accurately the substantial variations in the balance of power between insiders and outsiders, as well as the conditions of the relevant markets and industries.Footnote 68
II. The Plurality of Corporate Law’s Values—Theoretical Foundations
In this Part, we discuss the theoretical background generating the plurality of corporate law’s values. This framework is based on the social complex systems idea that was designed in line with chaos theory and networks theory in the field of natural sciences.Footnote 69 These theories are grounded on the assumption that individuals and organizations do not operate in isolation, but rather develop via interaction with their physical and social environment. We discuss the sociological understanding of complexity and social systems and its applications in the study of corporate law.Footnote 70
A. Social Systems Theory, and Its Implications for the Study of Business Organizations
The first formulation of systems theory in social science is associated with the work of Talcott Parsons, who developed a sociological systems theory whereby social systems are related either to the internal environment of other social systems, or to external, non-social environments.Footnote 71 Parsons distinguished between four possible formations of social systems:Footnote 72 adaptive systems (combining external reference and future orientation—e.g., the economy); goal-attainment systems (internal and future orientation—e.g., the polity); systems focused on integration of system elements (internal orientation, such as the community); and systems responsible for maintaining long-term patterns (present-time external references—e.g., cultural institutions in society).Footnote 73 These systems share several characteristics, such as adaptation (a system must adapt to its environment); goal attainment (a system must define and achieve its primary goals); integration (a system must maintain a relationship with its other parts); and latency (a system must maintain and renew the motivation of individual and cultural patterns that create and sustain that motivation).Footnote 74
One hallmark of Parsons’ theory is the notion that all systems and component subsystems are decomposable: every subsystem is a system in its own right, and must therefore be distinct in its terms and be free to develop subsystems of its own to be able to persist.Footnote 75 Social systems are sustained through sequences of linked individual-level behaviors,Footnote 76 and every social system must fulfill these four functions in order to survive, or to perform well.Footnote 77 Moreover, systems and subsystems are interrelated through the input and output of resources that are conveyed in exchange processes between systems.Footnote 78
Parsons’ systems theory maintains that each system encompasses several elements that make the system a functional whole.Footnote 79 Thus, each system must be considered in relation to the other systems that can cause a change or reaction within the primary system.Footnote 80 For example, according to systems theory, modern society includes separate subsystems of communication: the economic system, the political system, mass media, science, the education system, the legal system, and religion. These subsystems apply unique code and communicate it to other subsystems. For example, in the field of the law, the code applied is legal/illegal; in the economy, the relevant code is payment/nonpayment; in mass media, the code is information/noninformation; in religion, the code is sin/virtue.Footnote 81
This view was further developed by Walter F. Buckley, who formulated the idea of a complex adaptive system.Footnote 82 Complex adaptive systems are individual cases of complex systems.Footnote 83 They are complex in the sense they are diverse and composed of multiple, interconnected elements that can change and learn from experience.Footnote 84 Typical examples of complex adaptive systems are climate; cities; firms; markets; governments; industries; social networks; the brain; the immune system; and the cell.Footnote 85
There are two commonly observed features of complex systems: a large number of interacting elements, and emergent properties.Footnote 86 In particular, complex systems tend to comprise a large number of elements that interact with one another.Footnote 87 These interactions are usually linked to the presence of feedback mechanisms in the system—and these, in turn, introduce nonlinearities into the dynamics of the system.Footnote 88 Organizations are complex systems—in the sense that they are made of interactive, adaptive agents, groups, and departments—that communicate with one another through feedback mechanisms.Footnote 89 In addition to the existence of numerous interacting components, complex systems often exhibit emergent properties—i.e., the appearance of patterns due to the collective behavior of the system’s components.Footnote 90 One commonly cited example of an emergent property in thermodynamics is the temperature or pressure of a gas, from the large number of molecules striking each other.Footnote 91
There are several basic approaches that organizations can adopt to decide how to deal with increased environmental complexity.Footnote 92 One method is complexity reduction by means of a centralized and hierarchical structure of management that focuses exclusively on the manifestation of sole goal.Footnote 93 Under complexity conditions, members of hierarchical organizations reduce the number of agents and the various data inputs that influence their behavior and conduct.Footnote 94 Thus, an organization determines and prioritizes its goals, and then obtains and mobilizes resources to achieve them.Footnote 95
A second method is to allow organizations to absorb information in non-linear ways, through network relationships.Footnote 96 To consume vast data inputs and internally consider the increased range of risks and opportunities that they may be exposed to, firms should be composed of a network of decentralized decision-making structures that replace the centralized ones.Footnote 97 These decentralized structures are thought to be superior in dealing with the increased complexity of internal and external environments.Footnote 98 According to this view, the board of directors could distribute its functions to several sub-committees, which are responsible for managing complex data inputs in their respective field of expertise and executing the related decision-making process.Footnote 99
A third method focuses on the collaborative efforts and network connectivity within the judiciary system and between courts, legislators, and regulators.Footnote 100 In particular, studies on judicial hierarchy have crafted several models for explaining vertical and horizontal learning capabilities among judges. For example, David Klein explored how federal court judges in the United States decide cases when faced with unsettled law issues. Footnote 101 By employing quantitative and qualitative inquiries, he found that judges were often convinced by their colleagues’ reasoning, actions, prestige, expertise, and experience that lead judges “across circuits to agree on the proper rule more often than not.”Footnote 102 Moreover, when there are conflicts among judges’ reasoning and rulings’ outcomes, judges are more likely to support the reasoning favored by a majority of the circuits, implying that judges are engaged in vertical learning.Footnote 103 Given the intense connectivity within and between various legal institutions, information flow channels aiming to redress the complexity of the corporate governance system will emerge.
Since the complexity framework provides theoretical grounds for skepticism about uniform policies or structures of governance that are applicable in all contexts, courts have to break down the system of corporate governance regimes into its component parts, and examine how these parts relate to each other.Footnote 104 By analyzing the elements of corporate governance that interact with each other, the legal community—and the companies themselves—achieve a comprehensive perception of the field, which in turn affects business performance.
B. A Firm-Specific View of Corporate Governance Arrangements
Before elaborating on how corporate governance regimes must be designed at the firm level, we distinguish between internal and external corporate governance arrangements. Internal corporate governance regimes refer to arrangements regulating the specific power relations between a controlling shareholder and minority shareholders or between shareholders and management. These regulatory devices include controlling shareholders’ fiduciary duties, related party transactions regulations,Footnote 105 managerial incentives,Footnote 106 and directors’ fiduciary duties. External corporate governance mechanisms are arrangements that regulate the relationship between the company as a separate and independent legal entity, and third parties—such as the company goal;Footnote 107 the market for corporate control;Footnote 108 gatekeepers;Footnote 109 stakeholder activists;Footnote 110 proxy advisors;Footnote 111 rating organizations;Footnote 112 the media;Footnote 113 ethics; and culture.Footnote 114 As illustrated below, the complexity of the corporate governance eco-system is evident in the interactions between individual governance regimes. These continuous interactions produce extensive plurality in the values and principles that corporate law has to accomplish. Moreover, these special exchanges create normative implications that differ among numerous companies operating in various markets. For the law to be able to attain wide-ranging values, it has to design governance rules that are sensitive to the special features of firms and industries. As a result, adherence to a ‘one-size-fits-all’ approach prevents corporate law from meeting the challenge of complexity by crafting tailor-made law. Footnote 115
Consequently, to provide an expressive formulation of governance mechanisms, the law must be articulated in line with the balance of power between insiders and outsiders. The following discussion analyzes the primary manifestations of these power relations in concentrated and diffuse ownership structures of public companies.
1. Heterogeneity of Corporate Participants
To provide an expressive formulation of governance mechanisms at the firm level, we must first recognize that the group of shareholders that the law wishes to protect is not homogeneous in terms of their respective interests. Footnote 116 Shareholders may differ from each other in several respects—such as in the ratio of their holdings; the length of their investment;Footnote 117 their diversified or undiversified investment portfolios;Footnote 118 the rights and obligations attached to their shares;Footnote 119 and their social and political views. Footnote 120 In particular, courts must distinguish between five types of shareholders: controlling shareholders; retail investors; institutional investors; hedge funds; and index funds.Footnote 121
Controlling shareholders invest a considerable amount of their capital in a given corporation, and have an incentive to supervise the decision-making process of the company’s management.Footnote 122 They bear these costs because that structure enables them to execute long-term visions of the company’s business activities.Footnote 123 Due to the collective action problem and rational apathy, retail investors do not actively participate in the decision-making of corporations with regard to improving their internal governance practices.Footnote 124 However, increased engagement of institutional investors—such as pension funds and insurance companies—does have the potential to improve corporate decision-making, and provides protection against excessive risk-taking.Footnote 125 This positive influence is evident in the emergence of stewardship codes that aim to constrain board power by encouraging shareholders to exercise their legal rights and increase their level of participation.Footnote 126 In contrast, hedge funds are perceived to have a negative effect on the company’s decision-making process, because they use aggressive tactics to force the management to enhance share value only in the short term.Footnote 127 By using innovative investment instruments such as financial derivatives and security loan transactions, they hedge themselves against financial risks, while maintaining an active role in the company’s operations.Footnote 128 For example, they might pressure the management to distribute a dividend to shareholders,Footnote 129 or induce the company to sell business divisions, or reduce its research and development costs, and adopt various legal measures, with a view to seizing control of companies in financial distress.Footnote 130 Index funds are a type of mutual fund with a portfolio constructed to match or track the components of a financial market index.Footnote 131 Investment managers of index funds are considered to have little incentive to oversee the operations of the companies in their portfolio because they would only partly benefit from such oversight, while bearing the full costs involved.Footnote 132 Since investment managers seek to ensure future business activity with the company they are invested in, they will generally not undermine the management’s judgment or act against its position.Footnote 133 Consequently, the establishment of governance mechanisms for regulating firm-specific power relations cannot be made without analyzing the heterogeneous nature of corporate participants and their special interests and strategies.
2. Heterogeneity of Corporate’s Internal Power Relations
Generally speaking, the ownership structure of a public company is indicative of the inherent agency conflict that the law must address.Footnote 134 Empirical evidence demonstrates the multi-dimensionality effect of diffuse or concentrated ownership structure on enhancing firm performance and mitigating agency costs.Footnote 135 Specifically, it has been found that small levels of concentrated ownership control increase a company’s value, but when a certain threshold level is reached to the point that there is a substantial risk that controlling shareholders will seize corporate resources, the cost of that structure exceeds its benefits in reducing agency costs.Footnote 136 This suggests that a diffuse or concentrated structure in and of itself cannot exclusively explain a firm’s performance, which may be subjected to the complex effects of other internal and external factors.
In the following section, I suggest that for ownership structure to be an effective indicator of reduced agency costs, courts must apply a firm-specific perspective by considering the relative ratio of holdings between various shareholders, as well as the chances of creating an effective oppositional alliance of shareholders against the management or the controlling shareholder. The actual power relationship between insiders and outsiders may also be reflected in the composition and operation of the board. For example, the greater the holdings of minority shareholders in a concentrated ownership structure, the greater the chances that the board’s composition will have significant oversight impact on the controlling shareholder’s conduct. Another related factor for observing the formulation of an oppositional alliance is the extent of holdings by institutional investors, and the degree of dispersion of holdings among retail investors. Accordingly, the broader the distribution of shares by retail investors and the smaller the size of institutional investors’ holdings, the lower the chances of creating such an active opposition. Conversely, the narrower the distribution of shares by retail investors, and the larger the size of institutional investors’ holdings, the higher the chances of creating such an opposition.Footnote 137
3. Heterogeneity of Industries in Which Companies Operate
The company’s area of services—including its business condition—is also a relevant factor when assessing the power relationship between insiders and outsiders. In this regard, the law must design the legal arrangement that regulates such power relations, in a manner that helps maximize the company’s value. In the following, I discuss the implications of the company’s area of activities, including its business condition, on the extent of protection that law should provide to shareholders with regard to the legitimate interests of insiders.
(a) Protection of shareholders’ rights in research and development companies
Generally, an IPO is a common method for raising funds to expand company’s research and development undertakings, or to reduce its debt levels. Footnote 138 It involves the obligation of the listed company to comply with strict regulations regarding mandatory disclosure and preventing managerial misconduct.Footnote 139 These rules include listing requirements to determine whether a company is eligible to go public; disclosure and transparency guidelines to provide financial information to the market; and corporate governance requirements to ensure that the company’s affairs are managed in the interests of all shareholders.Footnote 140 This regulatory framework makes the process of an IPO significantly expensive, and includes various costs—such as the fees paid to investment banks, accountants, auditors, lawyers, and other service providers for advice and preparation of the registration statements, prospectus, and other relevant legal documents.Footnote 141
Since the early 1990s, the business landscape has shifted from large and public corporations to startups, entrepreneurial firms, and SMEs (small or medium-sized enterprises)—particularly in the technology sector.Footnote 142 In this respect, it has been argued that “these costly and lengthy regulatory barriers, together with sluggish IPO markets and their unavailability to smaller firms, have been reasons for high-tech companies and their shareholders to look for alternatives to IPOs.”Footnote 143
High-tech entrepreneurial firms are grounded on one basic vision, or project.Footnote 144 The riskiness of the project is extremely high; cannot be diversified; is often associated with a ‘winner-takes-it-all’; and has a high probability of failure and bankruptcy.Footnote 145 The starting point in analyzing corporate governance in entrepreneurial firms is the entrepreneur themself, who represents the firm’s owner-manager.Footnote 146 Entrepreneurial firms are strongly associated with the specific human capital, skills, and experience of the founder/owner-manager. These constitute the firm’s complementary assets, which are essential for its success.Footnote 147 In these conditions, the rules of corporate governance must be designed to give higher priority to the interests of the founder/owner-manager over the rights of other constituencies involved in the company’s operations—at least for a limited period. The reason for this is that, in the first years after these companies issue their shares, the entrepreneur holds the core technology and business knowledge necessary to the company’s continued development to the point where it becomes an established business. To encourage entrepreneurs to commit to the long-term prospects of their companies and to give them relative certainty concerning their continued engagement with its business, special corporate governance regimes should be adopted to incentivize entrepreneurs to list their companies on the stock exchange.
(b) Protection of shareholders’ rights in corporations whose operations affect the market’s financial stability
This criterion links the level of protection afforded to shareholders to the business environment and the company’s contribution to the overall financial stability of the capital market. The larger the impact a proposed transaction will have on the financial stability of the economy as a whole, the greater the restrictions that should be placed on insiders. The operations of financial institutions involve various risks—such as credit risks; liquidity risks; operational risks; legal risks; and market risks—all of which have an impact on overall financial stability. In this regard, adequate corporate governance arrangements are critical to the proper functioning of the banking sector, and the economy as a whole.Footnote 148 The Basel Committee’s revised corporate governance principles provide a framework that banks and supervisors should operate within to achieve robust and transparent risk management and decision-making, and to promote public trust in the safety and security of the banking system. Footnote 149
The conduct of a financial institution involves two different sets of agency costs.Footnote 150 One is a concern that the controlling shareholder of the institutional body will steer the company’s business operations in a manner that will allow them to pocket the private benefit of their control, at the expense of minority shareholders’ interests. The second agency problem is that investment managers have little incentive to address corporate governance issues that may eventually impair the corporate performance of companies in their portfolio, and consequently do not develop the expertise needed to engage in such activity, even if it would benefit their beneficiaries.Footnote 151 The reason for this is that under existing regulations, investment managers cannot charge their personnel and other management expenses related to stewardship of any single corporation directly to the portfolio.Footnote 152 Thus, if an investment manager would like to conduct a proxy fight against incumbent managers, it would have to cover these expenses itself, out of the fee income it receives from investors.Footnote 153 The tangential connection between these two agency costs lies in the importance of restraining insiders’ power to engage in related party transactions that have a bearing upon the corporation’s benefit and market stability.Footnote 154 This is especially required in times of global financial distress, such as the recent pandemic crisis, in which the entire economy bears the residual risks of the financial firm’s failure.Footnote 155 Unlike stakeholders who contracted with the firm, it cannot negotiate any contractual protections. In this scenario, the controlling shareholder is encouraged to increase the level of risks imposed on creditors by engaging in mistrusted transactions. This incentive can be even more compelling due to the promise of expensive public support in a manner of a “bailout to make sure that a really large bank does not inflict serious economic damage through its failure.” Footnote 156 Thus, during financial or social crises, courts have to impose further constraints on a controlling shareholder by considering society’s broader interests.
III. Firm-Specific View of Internal Corporate Governance Regimes
This Part demonstrates how courts should design internal corporate governance regimes with a firm-specific perspective—in particular, how the law on fiduciary duties of controlling shareholders, the regulation of related party transactions, and officers’ duty of care should be reconstructed.
A. Fiduciary Duties of Controlling Shareholders
Generally, shareholders’ duty of loyalty is founded on the principle of equality between the company and its shareholders, who hold an obligation to treat each other with equity and impartiality.Footnote 157 Under the conventional view of the Common Law, “[w]hen a shareholder is voting for or against a particular resolution, he is voting as a person owing no fiduciary duty to the company who is exercising his own right of property as he sees fit.”Footnote 158 A controlling shareholder has no particular duty of loyalty toward the minority shareholders, because it cannot be assumed that the controlling shareholder agreed, at any stage of its business operations, to subordinate their interests to the interests of the minority shareholders.Footnote 159 At the same time, each shareholder is still
required to respect a number of obligations which force him to take into account the interests of both his fellow shareholders and ‘the company’ itself. The shareholder is thus not completely free in how to exercise their voting rights, and cannot pursue purely selfish motives to an unlimited extent.Footnote 160
Accordingly, UK courts have dealt with the abuse of majority power primarily through the unfair prejudice action, now codified in section 994 of the Companies Act 2006 (UK).Footnote 161 While English law protects minority shareholders through ex-post equity-based judicial review,Footnote 162 American law incorporates equity consideration by ex-ante constraints on the exercise of shareholder rights and powers.Footnote 163 Under Delaware law, controlling shareholders (much like directors and executives) owe fiduciary duties to the companies they control and to their minority shareholders.Footnote 164 Historically, therefore, controlling shareholders’ transactions with their own companies have been subject to heightened entire fairness scrutiny, rather than the deferential business judgment rule review.Footnote 165 This implementation of ex-ante equity considerations “implies that the problem of abuse of power by controlling shareholders is generic and of a ‘fiduciary’ nature, such that fiduciary duties promise an apt resolution of it.”Footnote 166 A similar approach has been adopted in civil law countries.Footnote 167
Considering this state of affairs in light of the general principles of fiduciary law in Common Law legal systems is a puzzle. In general, American fiduciary law follows the structure of the ex-post common law adjudications and judge-made laws and is sharply different from civil law, which follows ex-ante codification.Footnote 168 However, the law of controlling shareholders fiduciary duties is more compatible with the ex-ante approach of civil law, rather than with the ex-post approach of English law. Recently, Miller has argued that the preference for fiduciary regulation in American equity—in marked contrast to the preference for the oppression doctrine in commonwealth jurisdictions—is questionable. In his view, such an approach can hardly be justified, because it involves an equity intervention that is not sensitive to the real sense of shareholder conflicts and consequent material inequities that are not amenable to effective resolution through general law.Footnote 169 To bridge between the American and English approaches, I propose that the law be designed to incorporate the firm-specific power relations between the controlling shareholder and minority shareholders by considering the possibility of forming an active oppositional alliance of shareholders or directors against the interests of controlling shareholders.
In instances where the controlling shareholder holds less than 50% of the share capital and the chances of forming such an alliance are high, comparing the relative holding rates indicates that minority shareholders stand to lose more than the controlling shareholder. In such instances, there is a concern that the controlling shareholder may be privy to private information about the proposed related-party actions that they do not wish to share with the minority shareholders. Thus, there is significant justification for imposing an ex-ante fiduciary obligation on the controlling shareholder. Conversely, when the controlling shareholder holds more than 50% of the voting rights in the company, and the chances of forming an active oppositional alliance are insignificant, the ex-post unfair prejudice doctrine should govern the relationship between controlling and minority shareholders. Though the proposed transaction is considered to benefit corporate’s interests and its shareholders, firm-specific power relations indicate that the controlling shareholder stands to lose more than minority shareholders if the transaction fails. Thus, there is no justification for preventing the controlling shareholder from looking after their legitimate business interests, provided that they do not violate minority shareholders’ rights. Since the controlling shareholder’s ability to deprive minority shareholders from direct participation in the decision-making process may be more observable, it is consistent with English case law, which provides relief for unfair prejudice causes of action in such circumstances.Footnote 170
B. Regulation of Related-Party Transactions
Historically, the United States has adopted a strict stance toward related-party transactions by setting a standard of entire fairness, which examines whether the terms of the transaction and its approval process are fair.Footnote 171 Recently, however, in the M&F Worldwide Corp ruling,Footnote 172 the Supreme Court of Delaware endorsed the business judgment review for going-private merger transactions in cases where dual procedural protections have been applied.Footnote 173 Specifically, it established that deference to company actions will be provided when the transaction is negotiated by a well-functioning special committee of independent directors and approved by a majority of minority shareholders.Footnote 174 However, for the courts to rely on the effectiveness of these mechanisms, the firm-specific perspective posits that they must consider them in light of the actual power relations between insiders and outsiders.Footnote 175
These power relations are reflected in the chances of creating an active oppositional alliance of shareholders that can prevail upon the board to conduct meaningful oversight. Accordingly, when the controlling shareholder’s holdings are less than 50% of the voting rights, and there is a high likelihood of organizing an oppositional alliance of shareholders, only a procedural judicial review—that focuses purely on the transaction’s approval process—should be applied. In such instances, the internal governance mechanisms themselves can ensure that the controlling shareholder does not derive private benefits of control. However, when the controlling shareholder holds more than 50% of the voting rights—and forming an active oppositional alliance of shareholders is therefore unlikely—the composition of the board may reflect the weakness of minority shareholders in impeding the controlling shareholder from obtaining private benefits of control. Thus, as the level of concentrated ownership increases, the effectiveness of independence directors’ oversight decreases.Footnote 176 Since the effectiveness of the board’s oversight is thought to be insubstantial in this case, an ex-post judicial examination of transactions’ fairness should be required as well.
C. Officers’ Duty of Care
All legal systems consider duty of care to be focused on the informed decision-making process, rather than on the substantive quality of the business decision itself.Footnote 177 However, courts have yet to develop a firm-specific duty of care view that designs the required decision-making process according to a company’s features, area of operations, and industry.Footnote 178 Consider, for example, the relevant standards of care required for achieving an informed decision-making process in entrepreneurial technology companies.Footnote 179 Research and development companies rely on the activity of entrepreneurs to fulfill the current technology demands of various international markets. Such enterprises are particularly risky, due to the difficulty in accurately assessing the scope and characteristics of the potential product market, the level of international competitiveness, and the uncertainty about the company’s ability to successfully develop the product and rapidly enter into the relevant market before its competitors. Even if the technological product in question is successfully produced, other events may intervene and derail the company’s plans and lead to its rapid demise—for example, when its massive investments over the years in developing the product are rendered moot, due to technological developments that were unforeseen by the company’s executives and directors. Such risks justify redesigning the standards of care, and the application of the business judgment rule, in a manner that facilitates entrepreneurial action.Footnote 180 Specifically, standards of care should be reformulated so as not to deter executives and directors from embracing risky decisions to venture into new markets that involve a high degree of uncertainty.Footnote 181
Since innovative conducts involve far more risk or uncertainty than non-innovative alternatives, judicial review of prohibitively risky decisions may subject innovation to doubts by ex-post second-guessing by the courts.Footnote 182 Considering the high risk and uncertainty involved in the high-tech industry, innovators may occasionally stake their entire personal wealth on a new idea when they are sufficiently enthusiastic about its potential, and believe that it can be highly profitable down the road. Thus, “[t]he entrepreneur’s idiosyncratic vision will often include elements that outsiders, including the firm’s minority shareholders, cannot observe or verify.”Footnote 183 Judicial review of such risk-taking innovative choices may undermine such entrepreneurship.Footnote 184
Another example concerns the duty of care of bank officers who are entrusted with the savings of the general public, and whose activities have an impact on the economy’s overall financial stability.Footnote 185 The activities of banks and financial institutions involve special risks that may give rise to unique corporate government arrangements.Footnote 186 The conventional view is that poorly managed financial firms can paralyze not only the firm itself, but the entire financial system, and therefore the economy as a whole.Footnote 187 This places unique demands on a financial institution’s board of directors, tasked with establishing effective risk oversight systems within the firm.Footnote 188 The significant differences between the characteristics of financial corporations and non-financial corporations justify the creation of special accountability regimes for managers and directors of financial institutions that extend beyond the benefit of the corporation itself, to encompass broad public goals.Footnote 189 Moreover, since poor management of financial institutions may cause damage that exceeds the harm inflicted on shareholders’ assets, the law must extend the obligations and duties imposed on executives and directors of such institutions.Footnote 190
Surprisingly, Delaware courts have adopted a different approach—one that is centered only on the consequences that the decision-making process had on the company, and whether there had been any ‘red flags’ that the directors should have been aware of and did not employ any remedial measures to counter.Footnote 191 Thus, the Caremark ruling posits that directors are liable for a failure of board oversight only where there is “sustained or systemic failure of the board to exercise oversight—such as an utter failure to attempt to assure a reasonable information and reporting system exists,” noting that this is a “demanding test.”Footnote 192 Several cases on fiduciary duties of the boards of financial institutions have extended the protection afforded to the risk oversight functions of directors.
For example, In re Citigroup Inc. Shareholder Derivative Litigation,Footnote 193 decided in 2009, the plaintiff asserted that the defendant directors of Citigroup had breached their fiduciary duties by not suitably monitoring business risks that Citigroup had incurred from subprime mortgage securities, and by ignoring specific ‘red flags’ that had been identified by press reports, revealing acute conditions in the credit markets.Footnote 194 The Court rejected these claims, reaffirming the “extremely high burden” plaintiffs confront in bringing a claim for personal liability for a failure to oversee business risk, and that a “sustained or systemic failure” to execute oversight is needed to confirm the absence of good faith that is a prerequisite condition for liability.Footnote 195
The Court failed to discuss the implications that the director liability regime has for ensuring the financial stability of the entire economy.Footnote 196 In particular, the Court considered the external economic conditions that the directors had to confront by focusing exclusively on the impact of such conditions on the company, without sufficiently considering the fact that the directors’ decisions also had a direct impact on the overall financial conditions of the markets as a whole.Footnote 197 Put differently, when considering the decision-making process of boards of financial institutions in fragile economic conditions, courts must analyze not only the implications of such a process on the company’s well-being, but also its consequences for the economy’s overall financial stability.Footnote 198
Interestingly, in Canada, directors of pension funds’ institutions may assume the fiduciary duties of plan administrators if the administrators have assigned them responsibility for pension oversight.Footnote 199 In this respect, Canadian case law has recognized that pension trustees are legally required to consider how their investment decisions will affect the stability of the financial system, and the direction of the economy.Footnote 200 In the case of Hodgkinson v. Simms, for example, the Canadian Supreme Court discussed several explanations for regulating the use of fiduciary authority with regard to financial services,Footnote 201 and stressed that fiduciary obligations in this industry are designed to serve public purposes and valuable social institutions.Footnote 202 More interestingly—based on the view that financial fiduciaries advance unique public goals—the Court has adopted a contextual approach to analyzing when fiduciary obligations arise, and the scope of these duties in various scenarios.Footnote 203
Nevertheless, even after the 2008 financial crisis, most countries have not yet developed nuanced standards of conduct for directors of financial institutions, or increased the duty of care.Footnote 204 This duty continues to be broadly the same for directors of financial institutions and of other firms. To eliminate excessive risk-taking by directors of financial entities,Footnote 205 corporate governance arrangements must strengthen the liability regimes of managers and directors.Footnote 206 Redesigning the standards of care imposed on such officers, and the extent of protection offered to their decisions under the business judgment rule, may recast the ongoing debate on the responsibilities and duties of directors in various public corporations.
IV. Firm-Specific View of External Corporate Governance Regimes
In this Part, I explore external corporate governance regimes by focusing on the company goal debate. I provide a micro-level perspective for articulating the company objective that is grounded on firm-specific features.Footnote 207 This understanding may demonstrate how this legal doctrine could be reformulated in accordance with companies’ actual needs and demands.
A. Cultural Norms and the Debate Over the Company’s Goal: A Theoretical Survey
Following the studies of La Porta et al. and the formation of an antidirector index for representing legal rules in the various legal systems,Footnote 208 the Law Matter school has argued that Anglo-American legal systems provide extensive protection of the rights of minority shareholders compared with the weaker protection provided by Continental legal systems.Footnote 209 Studies by Simeon Djankov et al. have also examined corporate laws of 72 countries, and confirmed that legal rules on shareholder protection have a measurable impact on financial development.Footnote 210 These studies have established that the quality of legal rules varied systematically with the ‘origin’ of a country’s legal system. In particular, it has been found that countries of English legal origin provided considerably better shareholder protection than those of other legal origins—especially those of Scandinavian legal origin.Footnote 211 However, these studies have been faulted in several respects. First, it has been argued that the Law and Finance school is wrong in its classification method of legal systems, insofar as it is inconsistent with the prevailing understanding in the comparative legal literature.Footnote 212
Moreover, to better understand the distinction between the different legal traditions, it is impossible to restrict the study to the quality of legal norms on their own without examining the culture of the legal system, which is not necessarily reflected in the statutory norm.Footnote 213 Second, it has been claimed that for the antidirector index to reliably represent legal rules in different legal systems, data coding must be transparent, consistent, and accurate.Footnote 214 Thus, subsequent studies that sought to reconstruct the findings of the Law and Finance school using more advanced statistical methods, did not find that Anglo-American legal systems necessarily provide better protection to minority shareholders’ rights than Continental legal systems, or that the scope of protection of minority shareholders makes it possible to predict market size, stock allocation, or economic growth.Footnote 215
However, the legal origin perspective would be considered to be only a limited description of corporate governance systems if it did not also combine the complementary role of the cultural environment of those systems.Footnote 216 Culture, as an open system, can address corporate governance issues that are likely to be regulated by the state.Footnote 217 Several studies have found that national corporate practices—such as accounting information disclosure, self-dealing, insider trading, and executive pay—are a function of cultural and historical orientations that are rooted in all societies.Footnote 218 Accordingly, culture, as a set of informal institutions, may affect diversity in corporate governance by supporting, constraining, or substituting the formal legal institutions.Footnote 219
One prominent example of the interaction between formal and informal social norms is evident in the dispute over the corporation’s primary objective.Footnote 220 The Anglo-American view posits that public companies have a general duty to maximize the wealth of their shareholders.Footnote 221 Since maximizing shareholder value is the only goal that companies must advance, considering the interests of other stakeholders is made instrumentally for the promotion of shareholders’ long-term interests alone.Footnote 222 In contrast, the civil legal system view is that focusing solely on increasing shareholder wealth may be directly detrimental to other stakeholders—such as employees, creditors, consumers, and suppliers—and consequently to the company itself.Footnote 223 Accordingly, the board of directors’ role is to coordinate the activities of all constituents who contribute to corporate production.Footnote 224 In Germany, the stakeholders’ governance view provides the employees with a significant role in advancing adequate and proper corporate governance practices:Footnote 225 its codetermination model promotes a democratic decision-making process by assigning similar weight to the financial and human-capital contribution to the company’s business.Footnote 226
Recently, Licht and Adams presented evidence on how personal and institutional factors collectively guide public company directors when exercising discretion in situations involving shareholder-stakeholder tensions.Footnote 227 In a sample of more than nine hundred directors from over fifty countries of origin, they confirm that directors universally hold a principled, quasi-ideological stance toward shareholders and stakeholders, called shareholderism. Moreover, they found that directors’ shareholderism correlates systematically not only with their personal values, but also with cultural norms that are consistent with entrepreneurship. Moreover, those informal norms appear to dominate the legal rules that shape directors’ shareholderism stances.Footnote 228 Thus, irrespective of how the law might determine the corporation’s objectives, board members may adopt strategies that deviate from that rule, and act according to their own values.Footnote 229 The broader implication of Licht and Adams’s study is that firm-specific features are the ones that govern corporate decision-making, and any legal construction of the company’s objective should at least be sensitive to firm-specific circumstances as a guidance for insiders’ conduct.
B. Firm-Specific View of the Company’s Goal Debate
The company’s business activities are generally based on the contribution of different stakeholders. For instance, while shareholders and creditors contribute financial capital to the company’s business, managers, directors, and employees provide human capital, and suppliers offer the physical capital necessary to its ongoing function. Recently, Belinfanti and Stout argued that the law should not confine the company’s activity to the fulfillment of merely one single objective, which is the promotion of shareholders wealth.Footnote 230 Often, the interests that the company seeks to achieve have a powerful interaction between them, so the law should avoid subordination of one goal to another.Footnote 231
In general, legal systems assume that a company should pursue a single goal that fits all kinds of corporations in the market.Footnote 232 However, the firm-specific strategy rejects this assumption. Due to profound differences in the features of companies, including their assets, the holdings of their capital share, the human capital diversification, and their dependency on the contribution of specific stakeholders, the law should refrain from articulating one single objective which suits all corporations.
The firm-specific view posits the structure, functions, and activities of the company should not be confined for increasing shareholders or stakeholders’ value as such but instead for promoting the separate and special interests of the firm to increase its own value and performance.Footnote 233 According to the firm-specific view, the interests of shareholders or stakeholders could be considered only if they correspond to the company’s sole interests. For instance, we can assume that a company whose principal activity is limited to the holding of several other companies has a remarkably different purpose to achieve than a company whose main production activity is highly dependent on the capital contribution of employees, creditors, and consumers.
To illustrate this idea, consider the example of dividend distribution. One of the central functions of any legal capital regime is to ensure that the creditors have preferential access to the company’s assets by restraining the company’s ability to make distributions to the shareholders.Footnote 234 From a stakeholders’ perspective, any distribution decreases the available assets they could reach for paying the company’s debts and thus it should be carried out only in special circumstances. This is especially true in certain industries that experience financial distress because of the pandemic and in which companies have to ensure their survival. Stakeholders who consider the company’s distribution policy to be an excessive one may refrain from providing resources required for increasing firm value. At the same time, because stockholders perceive dividend distribution to be an integral part of earning a return for their investment, a company that generally refrains from distributing profits will experience difficulties in raising equity in the stock markets.Footnote 235 Therefore, the balance between shareholders’ and stakeholders’ interests should be carried out from the perspective of the firm itself. The company has to balance the costs associated with the loss of stakeholder resources contributions because of an announced distribution and the expected increase of its capacity to raise valuable (and cheap) equity in capital markets. Consequently, the company should distribute dividends only when it considers the benefits involved to outweigh the costs imposed on the firm.Footnote 236
Furthermore, provided that the interests that should be considered are those of the company itself as distinct from any other stakeholder or stockholder, the goal that a company advances cannot remain constant throughout its lifecycle. Because companies’ business activities are subject to change over time, the objective that a company’s organs pursue may also change, in line with its business results and the respective contributions of various stakeholders to the company’s welfare. For example, one might argue that the purpose of a company immediately after its founding is significantly different from its objective long after its incorporation. This is because immediately after the incorporation of the company, it is highly dependent on capital investment to facilitate its initial operations. This is especially true when the company’s activities are conducted in markets with high barriers to entry. Therefore, at the startup stage, the law should construct the company’s goal solely in line with the interests of shareholders and creditors, who provide the initial capital it needs to start its operations. However, once the company’s business operations are established and recognized, the law should apply corporate governance rules to protect the interests of other stakeholders as well.
V. Further Challenges
The implementation of the firm-specific model requires addressing several challenges.
A. Toward Optimal Standardization of Corporate Law
Our model is based on formulating a corporate governance eco-system in terms of complexity, which is the result of the interactions between individual governance regimes. To be attentive to the wide-ranging values of the system, courts must produce governance arrangements that are sensitive to the special features of firms and industries. Recently, Henry E. Smith has also perceived private law in terms of complexity, though, following Herbert Simon’s writings, he understands it to be “nearly decomposable.”Footnote 237 Smith advances the idea of modularity as a mechanism to handle private law’s complexity that “permits complex behavior at lower cost,”Footnote 238 and allows one to “model the law without prejudging the degree of system.”Footnote 239
One can argue that our thesis calls the courts to produce fully customized governance arrangements on a case-by-case basis, thereby implying that corporate law should be seen as totally chaotic. Although courts should acknowledge the unique features of companies, industries, and markets in creating governance regimes, their discretion on how to do so is not unlimited. I provided specific criteria for formulating firm-specific power relations between insiders and outsiders that equally apply to a broad range of corporate disputes. Put differently, while I urge the courts to consider heterogeneity concerns, they are still required to strictly use detailed rules that provide enough simplicity and modularity, which “lead to improvement toward a local optimum.”Footnote 240 By creating a broader set of corporate governance regimes, the law can address variations among shareholders, transactions, corporations, and the unique market-based concerns, thereby producing ‘optimal standardization’ of corporate law.Footnote 241 Moreover, the legal community can anticipate that large normative categories that address firms’ shared characteristics relating to firm-specific power relations, industry, and market conditions will eventually emerge as part of the case law development. These categories will reduce the costs firms will have to bear in figuring out the future courts’ rulings. Therefore, the model presented in this paper does not suggest that corporate governance regimes are maximally connected in the sense that no substantive rules could provide explanation and legitimacy to the system, and fully firm-specific rules are in order.
B. Mitigating Delineation and Information Costs
According to this challenge, the firm-specific model (as opposed to a one-size-fits-all approach) increases courts’ delineation costs in observing the actual power relations between controlling and minority shareholders or between shareholders and management, and raises the information costs for insiders and stakeholders when they consider interacting with the company.Footnote 242 Certain aspects of the theoretical model, such as the relative ratio of holdings between shareholders and the industries in which companies operate, do not necessarily involve an increase in information and delineation costs because the required data on these aspects—and their commercial practices implications—are freely available to all players in the market. However, investigating the existence of an effective oppositional alliance that could undermine insiders’ control could carry out costs that have to be addressed.
First, because there is a clear connection between the size of shareholdings and the ability to create an effective oppositional alliance of outsiders, the available data in the market could assist in mitigating these costs.
Second, major changes in the size of shareholdings that affect the chances of creating an oppositional alliance of minority shareholders—and as a result alter the internal power relations—do not occur frequently, but rather occur mainly under influential developments and circumstances in the company’s business condition that alter its size and scope of operations. In these settings, any stakeholder who considers interacting with the company carries out comprehensive inquiries anyway.
Third, even if the delineation and information costs involved are substantial, they are generally reduced as the result of proxy advisors’ activities. Because governance conflicts are generally addressed by proxy advisors—who provide recommendations to institutional investors on how to cast votes at shareholder general meetings—they convey their assessment on who should be considered the company’s controller and whether there is an effective oppositional alliance of minority shareholders in the firm. Their detailed recommendations have the potential to reduce the costs that any stakeholders or stockholder will have to bear if they want to interact with the company.
VI. Conclusion
This Essay was devoted to exploring two main forms of pluralism, namely the plurality of corporate law’s sources and the plurality of corporate law’s values. These fundamental parts of corporate law pluralism indicate that courts should embrace rules that consider the specific actual interactions within and among business organizations, so the general normative arrangements are closely aligned with the factual characteristics. Accordingly, the effectiveness of a corporate governance ecosystem depends on considering the effect of the heterogeneous nature of its participants and the firm-specific power relations, in the design of internal and external governance arrangements. Moreover, by assigning the court the role of assessing firm-specific power relations and their implications for regulatory design, the court ‘mimics’ the governance arrangements that the parties would have chosen for themselves ex-ante if they could anticipate future disputes and business contingencies. Thus, rather than speaking about the common law of corporations generally, we should focus on the law as it pertains to individual companies. While this Essay was devoted to the theoretical construction of pluralist understating of corporate law, future empirical work has to be done to examine the effectiveness of such regimes in directing insiders’ conduct and increasing corporate value and performance in practice.
Acknowledgments
I wrote this paper while I was a Fellow at the Center for Advanced Studies on the Foundations of Law and Finance, Goethe University, Frankfurt am Main (April-June 2021). My genuine gratitude to Tobias Tröger for his continuing support, and to Martin Gelter, Bernard Sharfman, Adam Hofri-Winogradow, Barak Yarkoni, Casimiro Nigro, and Joseph Liptrap, for their exceptional comments. I am also thankful to the faculty members of IE Law School for important suggestions on earlier drafts of this paper. Lastly, I extend my sincere appreciation to the Journal’s Editor, Professor Andrew Botterell, and the reviewers of this piece for their remarkably excellent remarks and suggestions for improvements. All URLs were last accessed on 12 September 2021.