Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-vdxz6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-20T13:21:41.897Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bounded Ethicality and The Principle That “Ought” Implies “Can”

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 September 2015

Tae Wan Kim
Affiliation:
Carnegie Mellon University
Rosemarie Monge
Affiliation:
University of St. Thomas
Alan Strudler
Affiliation:
University of Pennsylvania

Abstract:

In this article we investigate a philosophical problem for normative business ethics theory suggested by a phenomenon that contemporary psychologists call “bounded ethicality,” which can be identified with the putative fact that well-intentioned people, constrained by psychological limitations, make ethical choices inconsistent with their own ethical beliefs and commitments. When one combines the idea that bounded ethicality is pervasive with the idea that a person morally ought to do something only if she can, it raises a doubt about the practical relevance of the moral principles that business ethics theory prescribes. We call this doubt the Radical Behavioral Challenge. It consists in the idea that people cannot generally conform to the normative ethical principles that business ethics theorists prescribe, and that these principles are therefore practically irrelevant. We answer the Radical Behavioral Challenge and explore normative implications of our answer.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Society for Business Ethics 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Altham, J. E. J. 1988. “Understanding the Logic of Obligation.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 62: 271–83.Google Scholar
American Institute of Certified Public Accountants (AICPA). 2014. “AICPA Code of Professional Conduct.” Code of Conduct. American Institute of Certified Public Accountants, Inc.http://www.aicpa.org/Research/Standards/CodeofConduct/DownloadableDocuments/2014December15ContentAsof2014Sept24CodeofConduct.pdf.Google Scholar
Arpaly, Nomy, and Schroeder, Timothy. 2014. In Praise of Desire. OUP USA Oxford Moral Theory.Google Scholar
Asch, Solomon E. 1956. “Studies of Independence and Conformity: I. A Minority of One against a Unanimous Majority.” Psychological Monographs: General and Applied 70(9): 170. doi:10.1037/h0093718.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, Robert, and Murphy, Patrick E. 2006. “The Many Faces of Integrity.” Business Ethics Quarterly 16(1): 321. doi:10.5840/beq20061615.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Austin, J. L. 1956. “A Plea for Excuses: The Presidential Address.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 57: 130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, Marcia. 2005. “Justifications and Excuses.” Ohio State Journal of Criminal Law 2: 387.Google Scholar
Bazerman, Max H. 2011. “Bounded Ethicality in Negotiations.” Negotiation and Conflict Management Research 4(1): 811. doi:10.1111/j.1750-4716.2010.00069.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bazerman, Max H., and Gino, Francesca. 2012. “Behavioral Ethics: Toward a Deeper Understanding of Moral Judgment and Dishonesty.” Annual Review of Law and Social Science 8: 85104. doi:10.1146/annurev-lawsocsci-102811-173815.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bazerman, Max H., Morgan, Kimberly P., and Loewenstein, George F. 1997. “The Impossibility of Auditor Independence.” MIT Sloan Management Review 38(4): 8994.Google Scholar
Bazerman, Max H., and Tenbrunsel, Ann E. 2011. Blind Spots: Why We Fail to Do What’s Right and What to Do about It. New Haven: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bennett, Jonathan. 1995. The Act Itself. 1st edition. Oxford : New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Berman, Mitchell N. 2003. “Justification and Excuse, Law and Morality.” Duke Law Journal 53(1): 177.Google Scholar
Bertrand, Marianne, Chugh, Dolly, and Mullainathan, Sendhil. 2005. “Implicit Discrimination.” The American Economic Review 95(2): 9498.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bertrand, Marianne, and Mullainathan, Sendhil. 2004. “Are Emily and Greg More Employable than Lakisha and Jamal? A Field Experiment on Labor Market Discrimination.” The American Economic Review 94(4): 9911013.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boatright, John R. 2007. “Reluctant Guardians: The Moral Responsibility of Gatekeepers.” Business Ethics Quarterly 17(4): 613–32. doi:10.5840/beq20071742.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowie, Norman E. 1991. “Challenging the Egoistic Paradigm.” Business Ethics Quarterly 1(1): 121. doi:10.2307/3857590.Google Scholar
Bowie, Norman E. 1998. “A Kantian Theory of Capitalism.” Business Ethics Quarterly, New Approaches to Business Ethics, Special Issue: 3760.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brenkert, George G. 1995. “‘The Environment, The Moralist, The Corporation and Its Culture.’” Business Ethics Quarterly 5(4): 675–97. doi:10.2307/3857409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brewer, Marilynn B. 1979. “In-Group Bias in the Minimal Intergroup Situation: A Cognitive-Motivational Analysis.” Psychological Bulletin 86(2): 307–24. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.86.2.307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brockner, Joel, and Rubin, Jeffrey Z. 1985. Entrapment in Escalating Conflicts. New York: Springer-Verlag. http://link.springer.com/10.1007/978-1-4612-5072-2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bryan, Christopher J., Adams, Gabrielle S., and Monin, Benoît. 2013. “When Cheating Would Make You a Cheater: Implicating the Self Prevents Unethical Behavior.” Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 142(4): 1001–5. doi:10.1037/a0030655.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chugh, Dolly, Bazerman, Max H., and Banaji, Mahzarin R. 2005. “Bounded Ethicality as a Psychological Barrier to Recognizing Conflicts of Interest.” In Conflicts of Interest: Challenges and Solutions in Business, Law, Medicine, and Public Policy, edited by Moore, Don A., Cain, Daylian M., Loewenstein, George, and Bazerman, Max H., 7495. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darley, John M., and Batson, C. Daniel. 1973. “‘From Jerusalem to Jericho’: A Study of Situational and Dispositional Variables in Helping Behavior.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 27(1): 100108. doi:10.1037/h0034449.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dasgupta, Nilanjana. 2004. “Implicit Ingroup Favoritism, Outgroup Favoritism, and Their Behavioral Manifestations.” Social Justice Research 17(2): 143–69. doi:10.1023/B: SORE.0000027407.70241.15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donagan, Alan. 1979. The Theory of Morality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Donaldson, Thomas. 1989. The Ethics of International Business. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Donaldson, Thomas. 1994. “When Integration Fails: The Logic of Prescription and Description in Business Ethics.” Business Ethics Quarterly 4(2): 157–69. doi:10.2307/3857487.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dressler, Joshua. 1987. “Reflections on Excusing Wrongdoers: Moral Theory, New Excuses and the Model Penal Code.” Rutgers Law Journal 19: 671.Google Scholar
Duska, Ronald F., and Duska, Brenda Shay. 2003. Accounting Ethics. Foundations of Business Ethics 2. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Epley, Nicholas, and Caruso, Eugene M. 2004. “Egocentric Ethics.” Social Justice Research 17(2): 171–87. doi:10.1023/B:SORE.0000027408.72713.45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feather, N. T., and Simon, J. G. 1971. “Causal Attributions for Success and Failure in Relation to Expectations of Success Based upon Selective or Manipulative Control.” Journal of Personality 39(4): 527–41. doi:10.1111/j.1467-6494.1971.tb00060.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feinberg, Joel. 1965. “The Expressive Function of Punishment.” The Monist 49(3): 397423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gino, Francesca, Moore, Don A., and Bazerman, Max H. 2008. “See No Evil: When We Overlook Other People’s Unethical Behavior.” SSRN Scholarly Paper ID 1079969. Rochester, NY: Social Science Research Network. http://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=1079969.Google Scholar
Goodpaster, Kenneth E. 2010. “Corporate Responsibility and Its Constituents.” In The Oxford Handbook of Business Ethics, edited by Brenkert, George G. and Beauchamp, Tom L., 126–57. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodpaster, Kenneth E. 2011. “Goods That Are Truly Good and Services That Truly Serve: Reflections on ‘Caritas in Veritate.’” Journal of Business Ethics 100 (S1): 916.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, Alexander R., Carney, Dana R., Pallin, Daniel J., Ngo, Long H., Raymond, Kristal L., Iezzoni, Lisa I., and Banaji, Mahzarin R. 2007. “Implicit Bias among Physicians and Its Prediction of Thrombolysis Decisions for Black and White Patients.” Journal of General Internal Medicine 22(9): 1231–38. doi:10.1007/s11606-007-0258-5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greenwald, Anthony G., Poehlman, T. Andrew, Uhlmann, Eric Luis, and Banaji, Mahzarin R. 2009. “Understanding and Using the Implicit Association Test: III. Meta-Analysis of Predictive Validity.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 97(1): 1741. doi:10.1037/a0015575.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffin, James. 1992. “The Human Good and the Ambitions of Consequentialism.” Social Philosophy and Policy 9(02): 118–32. doi:10.1017/S0265052500001436.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffin, James. 1996. Value Judgement: Improving Our Ethical Beliefs. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Haines, Nicolas. 1972. “Ought and Can.” Philosophy 47(181): 263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harrison, Jeffrey S., and Wicks, Andrew C. 2013. “Stakeholder Theory, Value, and Firm Performance.” Business Ethics Quarterly 23(1): 97124. doi:10.5840/beq20132314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holroyd, Jules. 2015. “Implicit Bias, Awareness and Imperfect Cognitions.” Consciousness and Cognition 33 (May): 511–23. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2014.08.024.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, Thomas M., and Felps, Will. 2013. “Shareholder Wealth Maximization and Social Welfare: A Utilitarian Critique.” Business Ethics Quarterly 23(2): 207–38. doi:10.5840/beq201323215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahneman, Daniel. 2011. Thinking, Fast and Slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. 1996a. The Metaphysics of Morals. Edited by Gregor, Mary J.. 2nd edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. 1996b. Practical Philosophy. Edited by Gregor, Mary J. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. 1999. Critique of Pure Reason. Edited and translated by Guyer, Paul and Wood, Allen W. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kim, Tae Wan. 2014. “Decent Termination: A Moral Case for Severance Pay.” Business Ethics Quarterly 24(2): 203–27. doi:10.5840/beq20145278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levy, David. 2008. “Ought Implies Can.” Edited by Kolb, Robert W. Encyclopedia of Business Ethics and Society. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.Google Scholar
Levy, Neil. 2014. “Consciousness, Implicit Attitudes and Moral Responsibility.” Noûs 48(1): 2140. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2011.00853.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loewenstein, George, and Thaler, Richard H. 1989. “Anomalies: Intertemporal Choice.” The Journal of Economic Perspectives 3(4): 181–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machery, Edouard. 2010. “The Bleak Implications of Moral Psychology.” Neuroethics 3(3): 223–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCall, John J. 2001. “Employee Voice in Corporate Governance: A Defense of Strong Participation Rights.” Business Ethics Quarterly 11(1): 195213. doi:10.2307/3857877.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCall, John J. 2003. “A Defense of Just Cause Dismissal Rules.” Business Ethics Quarterly 13(2): 151–75. doi:10.5840/beq200313211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Milgram, Stanley. 1974. Obedience to Authority: An Experimental View. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Moore, Don A., Tanlu, Lloyd, and Bazerman, Max H. 2010. “Conflict of Interest and the Intrusion of Bias.” Judgment and Decision Making 5(1): 3753.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phillips, Robert A. 2010. “Ethics and Network Organizations.” Business Ethics Quarterly 20(3): 533–43. doi:10.5840/beq201020333.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prentice, Robert. 2014. “Bounded Ethicality.” Ethics Unwrapped. http://ethicsunwrapped.utexas.edu/video/bounded-ethicality.Google Scholar
Radin, Tara J., and Werhane, Patricia H. 2003. “Employment-at-Will, Employee Rights, and Future Directions for Employment.” Business Ethics Quarterly 13(2): 113–30. doi:10.5840/beq200313212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reeves, Arin N. 2014. “Written in Black & White: Exploring Confirmation Bias in Racialized Perceptions of Writing Skills.” Yellow Paper Series. Chicago, IL: Nextions LLC. http://www.nextions.com/wp-content/files_mf/13972237592014040114WritteninBlackandWhiteYPS.pdf.Google Scholar
Robertson, Diana C. 1993. “Empiricism in Business Ethics: Suggested Research Directions.” Journal of Business Ethics 12(8): 585–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, Paul H. 2009. “A System of Excuses: How Criminal Law’s Excuse Defenses Do, and Don’t, Work Together to Exculpate Blameless (and Only Blameless) Offenders.” Texas Tech Law Review 42: 259.Google Scholar
Ross, Lee. 1977. “The Intuitive Psychologist and His Shortcomings: Distortions in the Attribution Process.” In Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, edited by Berkowitz, Leonard, 10:174221. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Ross, Lee, Greene, David, and House, Pamela. 1977. “The ‘false Consensus Effect’: An Egocentric Bias in Social Perception and Attribution Processes.” Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 13(3): 279301. doi:10.1016/0022-1031(77)90049-X.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rudman, Laurie A., and Ashmore, Richard D. 2007. “Discrimination and the Implicit Association Test.” Group Processes & Intergroup Relations 10(3): 359–72. doi:10.1177/1368430207078696.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saul, Jennifer. 2013. “Implicit Bias, Stereotype Threat, and Women in Philosophy.” In Women in Philosophy: What Needs to Change?, edited by Jenkins, Fiona and Hutchison, Katrina, 3960. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schreck, Philipp, van Aaken, Dominik, and Donaldson, Thomas. 2013.“Positive Economics and the Normativistic Fallacy: Bridging the Two Sides of CSR.” Business Ethics Quarterly 23(2): 297329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steinpreis, Rhea E., Anders, Katie A., and Ritzke, Dawn. 1999. “The Impact of Gender on the Reveiw of the Curricula Vitae of Job Applicants and Tenure Candidates: A National Empirical Study.” Sex Roles 41 (7/8): 509–428.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stern, Robert. 2004. “Does ‘Ought’ Imply ‘Can’? And Did Kant Think It Does?” Utilitas 16(01): 4261. doi:10.1017/S0953820803001055.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tenbrunsel, Ann E. 2005. “Commentary: Bounded Ethicality and Conflicts of Interest.” In Conflicts of Interest: Challenges and Solutions in Business, Law, Medicine, and Public Policy, edited by Moore, Don A., Cain, Daylian M., Loewenstein, George, and Bazerman, Max H., 96103. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tenbrunsel, Ann E., and Smith‐Crowe, Kristin. 2008. “Ethical Decision Making: Where We’ve Been and Where We’re Going.” The Academy of Management Annals 2(1): 545607. doi:10.1080/19416520802211677.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Treviño, Linda K., and Weaver, Gary R. 1994. “Business ETHICS/BUSINESS Ethics: One Field or Two?” Business Ethics Quarterly 4(2): 113–28. doi:10.2307/3857484.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Treviño, Linda K., Weaver, Gary R., and Reynolds, Scott J. 2006. “Behavioral Ethics in Organizations: A Review.” Journal of Management 32(6): 951–90. doi:10.1177/0149206306294258.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vohs, Kathleen D., and Schooler, Jonathan W. 2008. “The Value of Believing in Free Will: Encouraging a Belief in Determinism Increases Cheating.” Psychological Science 19(1): 4954.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vranas, Peter B. M. 2007. “I Ought, Therefore I Can.” Philosophical Studies 136(2): 167216. doi:10.1007/s11098-007-9071-6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weaver, Gary R., and Treviño, Linda K. 1994. “Normative And Empirical Business Ethics: Separation, Marriage Of Convenience, Or Marriage Of Necessity?” Business Ethics Quarterly 4(2): 129–43. doi:10.2307/3857485.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Werhane, Patricia H. 1994. “The Normative/Descriptive Distinction in Methodologies of Business Ethics.” Business Ethics Quarterly 4(2): 175–80. doi:10.2307/3857489.CrossRefGoogle Scholar