Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dlnhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T02:00:52.317Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Wittgenstein on Logic and Philosophical Method

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 May 2022

Oskari Kuusela
Affiliation:
University of East Anglia

Summary

This Element outlines Wittgenstein's early and later philosophies of logic, and explains Wittgenstein's views regarding the methodological significance of logic for philosophy. Wittgenstein's early philosophy of logic is presented as a further development of Frege's and Russell's accounts of logic, and Wittgenstein later philosophy as a response to problems with his early views, including confusions about idealization and abstraction in logic. The later Wittgenstein's novel logical methods, such as the method of language-games, are outlined, and the new kind of logical naturalism developed in his later philosophy described. I conclude by discussing the later Wittgenstein on names.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781108981125
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 23 June 2022

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Primary Sources

AWL Wittgenstein’s Lectures, Cambridge 1932–35. Ed. Ambrose, A.. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1979.Google Scholar
BB Preliminary Studies for the ‘Philosophical Investigations’ Generally Known as the Blue and Brown Books. Oxford: Blackwell, 1958.Google Scholar
BEE Wittgenstein’s Nachlass: The Bergen Electronic Edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.Google Scholar
BT The Big Typescript: TS 213. Oxford: Blackwell, 2005.Google Scholar
CL Ludwig Wittgenstein: Cambridge Letters. Oxford: Blackwell, 1997.Google Scholar
CV Culture and Value. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1998.Google Scholar
LW I Last Writings in the Philosophy of Psychology, Vol. 1. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1982.Google Scholar
NB Notebooks 1914–1916. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1961.Google Scholar
OC On Certainty. Oxford: Blackwell, 1993.Google Scholar
PG Philosophical Grammar. Oxford: Blackwell, 1974.Google Scholar
PI Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Wiley, 2009.Google Scholar
PPF Philosophy of Psychology – A Fragment. The second part of Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Wiley, 2009.Google Scholar
RC Remarks on Colour. Oxford: Blackwell, 1991.Google Scholar
RFM Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1998.Google Scholar
RLFSome Remarks on Logical Form’. In Philosophical Occasions 1912–1951. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1993, pp. 2835.Google Scholar
RPP I Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology, Vol. 1. Oxford: Blackwell, 1980.Google Scholar
RPP II Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology, Vol. 2. Oxford: Blackwell, 1980.Google Scholar
TLP Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Translated by C. K Ogden. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1951. Translated by B. F. McGuinness and D. Pears. London: Routledge, 2004.Google Scholar
VW with Waismann, Friedrich. The Voices of Wittgenstein: The Vienna Circle, Ludwig Wittgenstein and Friedrich Waismann. London: Routledge, 2003.Google Scholar
WVC Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1979.Google Scholar
Z Zettel. Oxford: Blackwell, 1967.Google Scholar

Secondary Sources

Anscombe, G. E. M. (1971). Introduction to Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. South Bend, IN: St Augustine’s Press.Google Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf (1947). The Formalization of Logic. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf (1959). ‘The Elimination of Metaphysics through Logical Analysis of Language’. In Ayer, A., ed., Logical Positivism. New York: The Free Press, pp. 6081.Google Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf (1963). ‘Intellectual Autobiography’. In Schlipp, P. A., ed., The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. La Salle, IL: Open Court, pp. 184.Google Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf (1967). The Logical Syntax of Language. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Carroll, Lewis (1895). ‘What the Tortoise Said to Achilles’, Mind, 4 (14): 278–80.Google Scholar
Conant, James and Bronzo, Silver (2017). ‘The Resolute Readings of the Tractatus’. In Glock, H.-J. and Hyman, J., eds., A Companion to Wittgenstein. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 175–94.Google Scholar
Evans, Gareth (1973). ‘The Causal Theory of Names’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 47: 187208.Google Scholar
Frege, Gottlob (1966a). ‘On Concept and Object’. In Geach, P. and Black, M., eds., Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 4255.Google Scholar
Frege, Gottlob (1966b). ‘On Sense and Reference’. In Geach, P. and Black, M., eds., Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 5678.Google Scholar
Frege, Gottlob (1972a). Conceptual Notation and Related Articles. Ed. Bynum, T. W.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Frege, Gottlob (1972b). ‘On the Aim of the “Conceptual Notation”’. In Bynum, T. W., ed., Conceptual Notation and Related Articles. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 90100.Google Scholar
Frege, Gottlob (1972c). ‘On the Scientific Justification of a Conceptual Notation’. In Bynum, T. W., ed., Conceptual Notation and Related Articles. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 83–9.Google Scholar
Frege, Gottlob (1979). Posthumous Writings. Ed. Hermes, H., Kambartel, F., and Kaulbach, F.. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Goldfarb, Warren (1997). ‘Metaphysics and Nonsense: On Cora Diamond’s The Realistic Spirit’. Journal of Philosophical Research, 22 (1): 5773.Google Scholar
Grattan-Guinness, Ivor (2000). The Search for Mathematical Roots 1870–1940: Logics, Set Theory and the Foundations of Mathematics from Cantor through Russell to Gödel. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. (1986). Insight and Illusion. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. (1996). Wittgenstein’s Place in Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. (2000). ‘Was He Trying to Whistle It’. In Crary, A. and Read, R., eds., The New Wittgenstein. London: Routledge, pp. 353–88.Google Scholar
Hanna, Robert (2006). Rationality and Logic. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hilmy, S. Stephen (1987). The Later Wittgenstein: The Emergence of a New Philosophical Method. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul (1981). Naming and Necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul (1982). Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Kuusela, Oskari (2008). The Struggle against Dogmatism: Wittgenstein and the Concept of Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kuusela, Oskari (2011). ‘The Development of Wittgenstein’s Philosophy’. In Kuusela, O. and McGinn, M., eds., The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 597619.Google Scholar
Kuusela, Oskari (2015). ‘Review of Penelope Maddy, The Logical Must’. Nordic Wittgenstein Review, 4 (1): 233–6.Google Scholar
Kuusela, Oskari (2016). ‘Wittgenstein and Consciousness’. In Leach, S. and Tartaglia, J., eds., Consciousness and the Great Philosophers. London: Routledge, pp. 199208.Google Scholar
Kuusela, Oskari (2019a). ‘On Wittgenstein’s and Carnap’s Conceptions of the Dissolution of Philosophical Problems, and against a Therapeutic Mix: How to Solve the Paradox of the Tractatus’. Philosophical Investigations, 42 (3): 213–40.Google Scholar
Kuusela, Oskari (2019b). ‘Wittgenstein and the Unity of Good’. European Journal of Philosophy, 28 (2): 428–44.Google Scholar
Kuusela, O. (2019c). Wittgenstein on Logic as the Method of Philosophy: Re-examining the Roots and Development of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuusela, Oskari (2019d). ‘Wittgenstein’s Reception of Socrates’. In Moore, C., ed., Brill’s Companion to the Reception of Socrates. Leiden: Brill, pp. 883907.Google Scholar
Kuusela, Oskari (2021). ‘Wittgenstein’s Grundgedanke as the Key to the Tractatus’. Teorema, 40 (2): 8399.Google Scholar
Kuusela, Oskari (forthcoming). ‘Wittgenstein’s Tractatus without Paradox: Propositions as Pictures’. Aurora Journal of Philosophy.Google Scholar
Maddy, Penelope (2014). The Logical Must: Wittgenstein on Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGinn, Marie (2006). Elucidating the Tractatus. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mercer, Michelle (2004). Footprints: The Life and Work of Wayne Shorter. New York: Tarcher/Penguin.Google Scholar
Noonan, Harold (2013). Kripke and Naming and Necessity. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Read, Rupert and Deans, Rob (2003). ‘Nothing is Shown: A “Resolute” Response to Mounce, Emiliani, Koethe and Vilhauer’. Philosophical Investigations, 26 (3): 239–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Read, Rupert and Deans, Rob (2011). ‘The Possibility of a Resolutely Resolute Reading of the Tractatus’. In Read, R. and Lavery, M., eds., Beyond the Tractatus Wars. London: Routledge, pp. 149–70.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand (1926). Our Knowledge of the External World: As a Field for Scientific Method in Philosophy. London: George Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand (1959). My Philosophical Development. London: George Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand (2001). The Problems of Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand (2010). The Philosophy of Logical Atomism. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Searle, John (1958). ‘Proper Names’. Mind, 67 (266): 166–73.Google Scholar
Strawson, Peter (2010). ‘On Referring’. In Logico-Linguistic Papers. Aldershot: Ashgate, pp. 127.Google Scholar
Waismann, Friedrich (1968). ‘Verifiability’. In Harré, R., ed., How I See Philosophy. London: Macmillan, pp. 3966.Google Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Wittgenstein on Logic and Philosophical Method
  • Oskari Kuusela, University of East Anglia
  • Online ISBN: 9781108981125
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Wittgenstein on Logic and Philosophical Method
  • Oskari Kuusela, University of East Anglia
  • Online ISBN: 9781108981125
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Wittgenstein on Logic and Philosophical Method
  • Oskari Kuusela, University of East Anglia
  • Online ISBN: 9781108981125
Available formats
×