Published online by Cambridge University Press: 03 April 2024
Why history?
The 18th-century jurist William Blackstone famously said: ‘It is better that ten guilty persons escape than one innocent suffer’ (Blackstone, 1803, IV.27). This is just one example of how the contemporary criminal trial is expressive of value judgements which, while made long ago, have since assumed the status of fundamental principles in modern criminal justice. Few criminal law scholars would deny that their territory is deeply normatively imbued. Indeed, much criminal law scholarship today is preoccupied with normative enquiry into the moral rationales for criminalising individual acts (Wertheimer, 2003; Duff, 2018; Green, 2020).
From where does the normative content of criminal law come, and how does it acquire weight and validity? This is first and foremost a historical question. As Alan Norrie argues, the normative contours of contemporary criminal law were ‘formed in a particular historical epoch [which Norrie identifies with 18th-century Enlightenment thought] and derived their characteristic shape from fundamental features of the social relations of that epoch’ (Norrie, 2014: 10). Lacey too emphasises the historical dimensions of criminal law, showing how conceptions of the criminal subject have varied over time and space so that ascriptions of criminal responsibility are best understood, not abstractly but contextually, in relation to ‘broader social, cultural, political and economic developments’ (Lacey, 2016: vii). By historicising and contextualising criminal law, Norrie and Lacey highlight the specificity of the ideas and perceptions of human relations which underpin modern criminal justice. Importantly, their work reveals not only that criminal law is normatively imbued, but also that the terms of normative engagement are historically derived, governed by conceptions of human nature, social relations and the role, functions and legitimacy of the state, which are now so well embedded in the criminal justice infrastructure as to appear beyond contest. ‘At the core of the philosophy behind criminal law’, Norrie comments, ‘is a moral individualism which proclaims that for the state to intervene against the individual, it must have a good and clear licence to do so’ (Norrie, 2014: 13). Both Norrie and Lacey set out to represent the liberal individualism of criminal law – the unchallenged and essentially unchallengeable foundation of the criminal justice edifice – as a social and historical construct which derives its weight and validity from the ‘ideas, interests and institutions’ (Lacey, 2016) that shaped its formation and development.
To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.