Hostname: page-component-6587cd75c8-rlsgg Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-04-23T21:47:56.691Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Against Realist Ideology Critique

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 January 2025

Matt Sleat*
Affiliation:
Department of Politics and International Relations, University of Sheffield, UK

Abstract

Is it possible to do ideology critique without morality? In recent years a small group of theorists has attempted to develop such an account and, in doing so, makes claim to a certain sort of “radical realism” distinguished by the ambition to ground political judgments and prescriptions in nonmoral values, principles, or concepts. This essay presents a twofold critique of this realist ideology critique (RIC) by first offering an internal critique of the approach and then arguing that the very attempt to do political theory generally—and ideology critique more specifically—in a way that abjures morality is misguided. In doing so, I contribute both to current debates around “new” ideology critiques and to contested questions about what it means to do political theory realistically.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© 2025 Social Philosophy & Policy Foundation. Printed in the USA

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Article purchase

Temporarily unavailable

References

1 See Aytac, Ugur and Rossi, Enzo, “Ideology Critique without Morality: A Radical Realist Approach,” American Political Science Review 117, no. 4 (2023): 1215–27CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Prinz, and Rossi, Enzo, “Political Realism as Ideology Critique,” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 20, no. 3 (2017): 348–65CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Rossi, Enzo and Argenton, Carlo, “Property, Legitimacy, Ideology: A Reality Check,” Journal of Politics 83, no. 3 (2021): 1046–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Enzo Rossi, “Critical Responsiveness: How Epistemic Ideology Critique Can Make Normative Legitimacy Empirical Again,” elsewhere in this volume.

2 Lest this is mistaken as a common feature of all forms of realist thought, as it often is, it is important to stress immediately that not all realists share this commitment to doing political theory with nonmoral materials. More shall be said about this below; I flag now that I shall take issue with this understanding of realism in the final section of this essay.

3 Rossi, Enzo, “Being Realistic and Demanding the Impossible,” Constellations 26, no. 4 (2019): 640 CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For similar understandings of what is meant by a “realistic” political theory, see Burelli, Carlo, “Political Normativity and the Functional Autonomy of Politics,” European Journal of Political Theory 21, no. 4 (2022): 627–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Burelli, Carlo and Destri, Chiara, “The Sources of Political Normativity: The Case for Instrumental and Epistemic Normativity in Political Realism,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 25 (2022): 397413 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Favara, Greta, “Political Realism as Reformist Conservatism,” European Journal of Philosophy 30, no. 1 (2022): 326–44CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Cross, Ben, “Normativity in Realist Legitimacy,” Political Studies Review 19, no. 3 (2021): 450–63CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Heysse, Tim, “Power, Norms, and Theory: A Meta-Political Inquiry,” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 20, no. 2 (2017): 163–85CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Rossi and Argenton, “Property, Legitimacy, Ideology: A Reality Check.”

4 Geuss, Raymond, The Idea of a Critical Theory: Habermas & the Frankfurt School (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999)Google Scholar; Geuss, Raymond, History and Illusion in Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001)Google Scholar; Geuss, Raymond, Outside Ethics (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2005)Google Scholar; Geuss, Raymond, Philosophy and Real Politics (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2008)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Geuss, Raymond, Politics and the Imagination (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Geuss, Raymond, A World without Why (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2014)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Williams, Bernard, In the Beginning Was the Deed: Realism and Moralism in Political Argument (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2005)Google Scholar.

6 For various discussions and applications of radical realism, see Aytac, Ugur, “Global Political Legitimacy and the Structural Power of Capital,” Journal of Social Philosophy 54, no. 4 (2023): 490509 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Brinn, Gearoid, “Smashing the State Gently: Radical Realism and Realist Anarchism,” European Journal of Political Theory 19, no. 2 (2020): 206–27CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Westphal, Manon, “Against the Status Quo: The Social as a Resource of Critique in Realist Political Theory,” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 26, no. 3 (2022): 418–36CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Prinz, Rossi, Political Realism as Ideology Critique”; Janosch Prinz, “Raymond Geuss’ Radicalization of Realism in Political Theory,” Philosophy & Social Criticism 42, no. 8 (2016): 777–96CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Raekstad, Paul, “The Radical Realist Critique of Rawls,” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 27, no. 2 (2021): 183205 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Raekstad, Paul, “Realism, Utopianism, and Radical Values,” European Journal of Philosophy 26, no. 1 (2018): 145–68CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Rossi, “Being Realistic and Demanding the Impossible”; Thaler, Mathias, “Hope Abjuring Hope: On the Place of Utopia in Realist Political Theory,” Political Theory 46, no. 5 (2018): 671–97CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 Not all radical realists have sought to develop and employ ideology critique. The main proponents of such an approach have been Carlo Argenton, Ugur Aytac, Janosch Prinz, and Enzo Rossi. For the purposes of this essay, I shall talk of radical realists as the advocates of RIC, although that caveat should be kept in mind.

8 Sleat, Matt, “What Is a Political Value? Political Philosophy and Fidelity to Reality,” Social Philosophy & Policy 33, nos. 1–2 (2016): 252–72CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Hall, Edward, “How to Do Realistic Political Theory (and Why You Might Want To),” European Journal of Political Theory 16, no. 3 (2017): 283303 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Jubb, Robert, “On What a Distinctively Political Normativity Is,” Political Studies Review 17, no. 4 (2019): 360–69CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9 Sankaran, Kirun, “What’s New in the New Ideology Critique?Philosophical Studies 177 (2020): 1443 CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See Jaeggi, Rahel, “Rethinking Ideology,” in New Waves in Political Philosophy, ed. de Bruin, Boudewijn and Zurn, Christopher F. (Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2008), 6386 Google Scholar; Mills, Charles W., “White Ignorance,” in Charles W. Mills, Black Rights/White Wrongs (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017), 4971 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; T Shelby, Ideology, Racism, and Critical Social Theory,” The Philosophical Forum 34, no. 2 (2003): 153–88CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Shelby, Tommie, “Racism, Moralism, and Social Criticism,” Du Bois Review 11, no. 1 (2014): 5774 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Shelby, Tommie, Dark Ghettos: Injustice, Dissent, and Reform (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2016)Google Scholar; Stanley, Jason, How Propaganda Works (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2015)Google Scholar.

10 Sankaran, “What’s New in the New Ideology Critique?” 1443.

11 Sankaran, “What’s New in the New Ideology Critique?” 1444. Quotation from Jaeggi, “Rethinking Ideology,” 65.

12 Sankaran, “What’s New in the New Ideology Critique?” 1445.

13 Geuss, The Idea of a Critical Theory: Habermas & the Frankfurt School.

14 Aytac and Rossi, “Ideology Critique without Morality: A Radical Realist Approach,” 1215.

15 Haslanger, Sally, Resisting Reality (New York: Oxford University Press, 2012), 412 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

16 Aytac and Rossi, “Ideology Critique without Morality: A Radical Realist Approach,” 1216–17.

17 Williams, Bernard, Truth and Truthfulness: An Essay in Genealogy (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2002), 219–32Google Scholar.

18 Prinz and Rossi, “Political Realism as Ideology Critique,” 355.

19 Williams, Truth and Truthfulness: An Essay in Genealogy, 231.

20 Sleat, Matt, “Realism and Political Normativity,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 25 (2022): 465–78CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

21 For example, Prinz and Rossi, “Political Realism as Ideology Critique,” 349.

22 Geuss, Raymond, “Realismus, Wunschdenken, Utopie,” Deutsche Zeitschrift Für Philosophie 58, no. 3 (2010): 42 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

23 In this and the following three paragraphs I am mainly summarizing the argument of Aytac and Rossi, “Ideology Critique without Morality: A Radical Realist Approach.”

24 Aytac and Rossi follow Haslanger in using the broader term “cultural technes,” which includes beliefs, but also other socially generated cognitive mechanisms such as concepts, dispositions, and the like to explain the content of ideologies. However, all the examples they use and discuss tend to be straightforwardly about beliefs rather than anything else. Hence, for the sake of not adding an unnecessary layer of terminological complexity, I shall employ the term “belief” here and throughout, but I do not think anything is lost in the analysis by doing so.

25 Kahan, Dan M., “The Politically Motivated Reasoning Paradigm, Part 1: What Politically Motivated Reasoning Is and How to Measure It,” in Emerging Trends in the Social and Behavioral Sciences: An Interdisciplinary, Searchable, and Linkable Resource, ed. Robert A. Scott, and Buchmann, Marlis C. (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 2016), 1 Google Scholar.

26 Nozick, Robert, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974)Google Scholar.

27 Rossi and Argenton, “Property, Legitimacy, Ideology: A Reality Check,” 1055.

28 The use of work from the wider social sciences presumably means that whether beliefs have been arrived at through distorted belief-formation processes is intended to be a falsifiable claim.

29 Rossi and Argenton, “Property, Legitimacy, Ideology: A Reality Check.”

30 There is a question, which RIC does not but would need to address, as to how we are to identify who the relevant dominant and oppressed groups are in any situation. After all, one feature of contemporary politics is that there is little consensus about precisely which are the groups with power; accusations and counteraccusations of oppression abound. White males, for instance, might think they are oppressed by the power of the “culture war warriors,” whereas the latter will often point to the former as the source of their own oppression. It would be helpful to know more about how RIC intends to identify which account of where power lies is closer to reality.

31 Aytac and Rossi, “Ideology Critique without Morality: A Radical Realist Approach,” 1220.

32 In the language of technê: “Debunking this cultural technê by identifying how it was generated by an epistemically flawed social process of indoctrination shows that the technê lacks epistemic warrant in its specific social context, but it does not directly falsify the technê’s propositional content, so the genetic fallacy is not triggered.” Aytac and Rossi, “Ideology Critique without Morality: A Radical Realist Approach,” 1221.

33 Aytac and Rossi, “Ideology Critique without Morality: A Radical Realist Approach,” 1223–24.

34 Williams, Truth and Truthfulness: An Essay in Genealogy, 230.

35 I here summarize the argument from Bernard Williams, “Realism and Moralism in Political Theory,” in Williams, In the Beginning Was the Deed: Realism and Moralism in Political Argument.

36 Williams, Bernard, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (London: Routledge, 2011)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For an excellent account of what Williams meant by “confidence” and how he believes it might be achieved in relation to specific values, see Hall, Edward, “Contingency, Confidence, and Liberalism in the Political Thought of Bernard Williams,” Social Theory and Practice 40, no. 4 (2014): 545–69CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

37 An insightful overview of Williams’s genealogic approach can be found in Queloz, Matthieu, The Practical Origins of Ideas: Genealogy as Conceptual Reverse-Engineering (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2021)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

38 Williams, BernardFrom Freedom to Liberty: The Construction of a Political Value,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 30, no. 1 (2001): 326 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

39 For a similar point against radical realists, see Favara, “Political Realism as Reformist Conservatism,” 335–36. In response, Ben Cross argues that radical realists do not assume “that all our normative ideas are guilty of being so distorted until they are proven innocent … but neither is it to say that they are innocent until proven guilty. Radical realists are suspicious of the distorting role of illusions in and amongst our normative ideas. The purpose of ideology critique, then, is to sift through our various ideas and weed out illusions where possible.” Cross, Ben, “How Radical Is Radical Realism?European Journal of Philosophy 30, no. 3 (2022): 1110–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar. That interpretation seems difficult to square with the blanket anti-moralist character of radical realism. As we saw, freedom was not given the benefit of the doubt before it was rejected as the basis for ideology critique, nor has subsequent analysis showed that it is the sort of illusion that we need to be rid of.

40 On Williams’s vindicatory genealogy, see Queloz, The Practical Origins of Ideas: Genealogy as Conceptual Reverse-Engineering. For radical realists’ discussions of genealogy, see Janosch Prinz and Paul Raekstad, “The Value of Genealogies for Political Philosophy,” Inquiry (2020): 1–20; Rossi and Argenton, “Property, Legitimacy, Ideology: A Reality Check”; Rossi, “Critical Responsiveness: How Epistemic Ideology Critique Can Make Normative Legitimacy Empirical Again.”

41 Sleat, “What Is a Political Value? Political Philosophy and Fidelity to Reality”; Williams, “From Freedom to Liberty: The Construction of a Political Value.”

42 Aytac and Rossi, “Ideology Critique without Morality: A Radical Realist Approach,” 1222.

43 I note that the way in which other realists understand moralism, and hence realist approaches as opposed to moralist approaches, is to say not that moralist political theories employ moral values or concepts, but, crudely put, they do so in ways that are not appropriately sensitive or responsive to what I call the constitutive features of politics or Edward Hall calls the “realist constraint.” Sleat, “What Is a Political Value? Political Philosophy and Fidelity to Reality”; Hall, “How to Do Realistic Political Theory (and Why You Might Want To).” In this regard, the charge is more like moralist political theorists have not adequately considered what it means for a value, including moral values, to be values appropriate for the political sphere; they are not political in the right way.

44 Edward Hall, “Ideological Self-Consciousness: Judith Shklar on Legalism, Liberalism, and the Purposes of Political Theory,” elsewhere in this volume.

45 Freeden, Michael, Ideologies and Political Theory: A Conceptual Map (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996), 4Google Scholar.

46 Freeden, Michael, “The ‘Political Turn’ in Political Theory,” Journal of Political Ideologies 19, no. 1 (2014): 7CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Freeden, Michael, “Interpretative Realism and Prescriptive Realism,” Journal of Political Ideologies 17, no. 1 (2012): 111 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Freeden, Michael, “Political Realism: A Reality Check,” in Politics Recovered: Realist Thought in Theory and Practice, ed. Matt Sleat, (New York: Columbia University Press, 2018), 344–68CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

47 One obvious option for the radical realist at this point would be to argue that although we may not be able to free ourselves from ideologies altogether, there are nonetheless more or less distorting forms of ideology and the latter are to be preferred over the former. Something like that may well be right, although making such judgments will require them necessarily to draw upon resources beyond the epistemic.

48 Nietzsche, Friedrich, On the Genealogy of Morality, ed. Ansell-Pearson, Keith, 3rd ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2017)Google Scholar.

49 Waldron, Jeremy, “Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism,” The Philosophical Quarterly 37, no. 147 (1987): 127–50CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

50 Russell, Bertrand, Philosophy and Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1947)Google Scholar.