Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T19:00:32.507Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Evolution and the American social sciences: An evolutionary social scientist's view

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 May 2016

Bradley A. Thayer*
Affiliation:
Department of Defense and Strategic Studies, Missouri State University, Hunter's Branch, 9302 Lee Highway, Fairfax, VA 22031, USA [email protected]
Get access

Abstract

American social scientists rarely ever use evolutionary concepts to explain behavior, despite the potential of such concepts to elucidate major social problems. I argue that this observation can be understood as the product of three influences: an ideologically narrowed political liberalism; a fear of “Social Darwinism” as a scientific idea, rather than a scientific apostasy; and a widely believed criticism of evolutionary thinking as deterministic, reductionistic, and Panglossian. I ask what is to be done to encourage social scientists to learn and to apply evolutionary lessons. I answer with four solutions. First, evolutionary social scientists should more effectively educate their non-evolutionary students and colleagues. Second, they should publicize, even popularize, accessible refutations of perennially misleading criticisms. Third, they should more credibly assure skeptics that evolutionary theory not only keeps the “social” in social science but better explains social behavior than can any individual-level theory, such as rational-choice theory. Fourth, they should recall that biology took generations to become Darwinian, and they must understand that the social sciences may take as long to become evolutionary.

Type
Field Notes
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Politics and the Life Sciences 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1.Thayer, Bradley A., Darwin and International Relations: On the Evolutionary Origins of War and Ethnic Conflict (Lexington: University Press of Kentucky, 2004).Google Scholar
2.Medvedev, RoyMedvedev, Zhores, The Unknown Stalin: His Life, Death, and Legacy (New York: Overlook Press, 2004), pp. 190208.Google Scholar
3.Sprinkle, Robert Hunt, Profession of Conscience: The Making and Meaning of Life-Sciences Liberalism (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1994).Google Scholar
4.Pinker, Steven, The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of Human Nature (New York: Viking, 2002).Google Scholar
5.Hofstadter, Richard, Social Darwinism in American Thought (Boston: Beacon Press, 1955).Google Scholar
6.Pinker, , The Blank Slate, p. 48.Google Scholar
7.Smith, John Maynard, “Commentary” in Gowaty, , ed., Feminism and Evolutionary Biology, pp. 522526, 524; Ullica Segerstråle, Defenders of the Truth: The Battle for Science in the Sociology Debate and Beyond (New York: Oxford University Press, 2000), pp. 391–396.Google Scholar
8.Wright, Sewall, “Comments,” in Moorhead, Paul S. and Kaplan, Martin M., eds., Mathematical Challenges to the Neo-Darwinian Interpretation of Evolution (Philadelphia: Wistar Institute Press, 1967), p. 117.Google Scholar
9.Pinker, , The Blank Slate, p. 113.Google Scholar
10.Ibid. p. 113.Google Scholar
11.Dawkins, Richard, The Blind Watchmaker: Why the Evidence of Evolution Reveals a Universe without Design (New York: Norton, 1986), p. 13; Williams, George C., “A Defense of Reductionism in Evolutionary Biology,” in Dawkins, R. and Ridley, M., eds., Oxford Surveys in Evolutionary Biology Vol. 2 (New York: Oxford University Press, 1985), pp. 1–27; Segerstråle, Defenders of the Truth, pp. 284–291.Google Scholar
12.Dawkins, , The Blind Watchmaker, p. 13.Google Scholar
13.Dennett, Daniel C., Darwin's Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1995), p. 81.Google Scholar
14.Ibid., p. 82.Google Scholar
15.Rosenberg, Alexander, The Structure of Biological Science (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1985), pp. 69120.Google Scholar
16.Gould, Stephen JayLewontin, Richard C., “The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme,” in Sober, Elliott, ed., Conceptual Issues in Evolutionary Biology, 2nd ed. (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1994), pp. 7390; Selzer, Jack, “Introduction,” in Selzer, Jack, ed., Understanding Scientific Prose (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1993), pp. 3–19.Google Scholar
17.Darwin, Charles, On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1964 [1859]), p. 201.Google Scholar
18.Simpson, George G., The Meaning of Evolution (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1949), quoted in Dobzhansky, “On Some Fundamental Concepts of Darwinian Biology,” in Theodosius Dobzhansky, Hecht, Max K., and Steere, William C., eds., Evolutionary Biology: Volume 2 (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1968), p. 31.Google Scholar
19.Ibid., p. 31.Google Scholar
20.Mayr, Ernst, Toward a New Philosophy of Biology: Observations of an Evolutionist (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1988), pp. 153, 105.Google Scholar
21.Ibid., p. 106.Google Scholar
22.Chang, Kenneth, “Scientists Find Signs of Meteor Crash That Led to Extinctions in Era Before Dinosaurs,” New York Times, February 23, 2001, <http://www.nytimes.com/2001/02/23/science/23EXTI.html/> Gugliotta, Guy, “Comet Tied to Mass Extinction,” Washington Post, February 23, 2001, p. A3; Hallam, A. and Wignall, P. B., Mass Extinctions and Their Aftermath (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997); Mayr, , What Evolution Is (New York: Basic Books, 2001), pp. 201–203.Google Scholar
23.Mayr, , Toward a New Philosophy of Biology, p. 106.Google Scholar
24.Jacob, François, “Evolution and Tinkering,” Science, vol. 196 (10 June 1977), pp. 11611166, 1163; Jacob, François, Of Flies, Mice, and Men, Weiss, Giselle, trans. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1998).Google Scholar
25.Gould, Stephen Jay, The Panda's Thumb (New York: Norton, 1980), pp. 5758.Google Scholar
26.Williams, George C., Natural Selection: Domains, Levels, and Challenges (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), p. 79.Google Scholar
27.Williams, George C., The Pony Fish's Glow: And Other Clues to Plan and Purpose in Nature (New York: Basic Books, 1997), p. 17.Google Scholar
28.Ibid., p. 17.Google Scholar
29.Ibid., pp. 1719.Google Scholar
30.Ibid., p. 19.Google Scholar
31.Ibid., p. 19.Google Scholar
32.Ibid., p. 19.Google Scholar
33.Mayr, , Toward a New Philosophy of Biology, p. 151.Google Scholar
34.Ibid., p. 151.Google Scholar
35.Ibid., p. 130.Google Scholar
36.Tooby, JohnDeVore, Irven, “The Reconstruction of Hominid Evolution Through Strategic Modeling,” in Kinzey, Warren G., ed., The Evolution of Human Behavior: Primate Models (Albany, N.Y.: SUNY Press, 1987), pp. 183237, 235.Google Scholar
37.Pálsson, GísliRabinow, Paul, Anthropology Today, vol. 15, No. 5 (October 1999), pp. 1418.Google Scholar