Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-cphqk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-01-28T02:31:56.608Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Refining Quinean Naturalism: An Alternative to Kemp’s Stimulus Field Approach

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 January 2025

Tolgahan Toy*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Bartın University, Bartın, TR, Turkey

Abstract

W. V. Quine suggests that meaning derives from the stimulus, the effects of the outside world on the subject’s nerve endings. However, the idiosyncrasy of the stimulus poses challenges to the intersubjectivity of meaning. Gary Kemp proposes the stimulus field approach as a solution. The stimulus field approach focuses on the forces affecting the subject, rather than the effects on the subject. In this article, I critique Kemp’s solution. Furthermore, I argue that the Quinean approach can be refined in a way that two agents may converge on the same meaning even without sharing the same stimuli or forces affecting them.

Résumé

Résumé

W. V. Quine suggère que la signification découle du stimulus, c’est-à-dire des effets exercés par le monde extérieur sur les terminaisons nerveuses du sujet. Cependant, l’idiosyncrasie du stimulus soulève des défis pour l’intersubjectivité du sens. Gary Kemp propose l’approche du champ de stimulation comme solution. Cette approche se concentre sur les forces qui influencent le sujet, plutôt que sur les effets qu’il subit. Dans cet article, je critique la solution de Kemp. De plus, je soutiens que l’approche quinéenne peut être affinée de manière à permettre à deux agents de parvenir à la même signification, même sans partager les mêmes stimuli ou sans être influencés par les mêmes forces.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Canadian Philosophical Association/Publié par Cambridge University Press au nom de l’Association canadienne de philosophie

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ferrer i Cancho, R., & Solé, R. V. (2003). Least effort and the origins of scaling in human language. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 100(3), 788791. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0335980100 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gauker, C. (2003). Words without meaning. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gori, S., Molteni, M., & Facoetti, A. (2016). Visual illusions: An interesting tool to investigate developmental dyslexia and autism spectrum disorder. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 10. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2016.00175 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hintikka, J. (1996). Ludwig Wittgenstein: Half-truths and one-and-a-half-truths. Kluwer Academic Publishers. https://link.springer.com/book/10.1007/978-1-4020-4109-9 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hintikka, M., & Hintikka, J. (1986). Investigating Wittgenstein. Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Kemp, G. (2022). Observation sentences revisited. Mind, 131(523), 807827. https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/fzaa103 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, J. (1975). An essay concerning human understanding (Nidditch, J., Ed.). Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Notredame, C.-E., Pins, D., Deneve, S., & Jardri, R. (2014). What visual illusions teach us about schizophrenia. Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience, 8, 116. https://www.frontiersin.org/journals/integrative-neuroscience/articles/10.3389/fnint.2014.00063/full CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Piantadosi, S. T., Tily, H., & Gibson, E. (2012). The communicative function of ambiguity in language. Cognition, 122(3), 280291. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2011.10.004 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Quine, W. V. (1957). The scope and language of science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 8(29), 117. https://www.jstor.org/stable/685377 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1959). Meaning and translation. In Brower, R. A. (Ed.), On translation (pp. 148172). Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1960). Word & object. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1969a). Epistemology naturalized. In Quine, W. V., Ontological relativity & other essays (pp. 6990). Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1969b). Propositional objects. In Quine, W. V., Ontological relativity & other essays (pp. 139160). Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1974). The roots of reference. Open Court Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1991). Two dogmas in retrospect. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 21(3), 265274. https://doi.org/10.1080/00455091.1991.10717246 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1992). Pursuit of truth (revised ed.). Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1993). In praise of observation sentences. Journal of Philosophy, 90(3), 107116. https://doi.org/10.2307/2940954 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1996). Progress on two fronts. Journal of Philosophy, 93(4), 159163. https://doi.org/10.2307/2940885 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1998). From stimulus to science. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. (2016). Preestablished harmony. In Janssen-Lauret, F. & Kemp, G. (Eds.), Quine and his place in history (pp. 2932). Palgrave Macmillan. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137472519_5 Google Scholar
Rey, G. (2020). Representation of language: Philosophical issues in a Chomskyan linguistics. Oxford University Press. https://global.oup.com/academic/product/representation-of-language-9780198855637?cc=ca&lang=en& CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Siegelmann, H. T., & Sontag, E. D. (1992). On the computable power of neural nets. Proceedings of the Fifth Annual Workshop on Computational Learning Theory (pp. 440449). https://doi.org/10.1145/130385.130432 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simões, D., Lau, N., & Reis, L. P. (2019). Multi-agent deep reinforcement learning with emergent communication. 2019 International Joint Conference on Neural Networks (IJCNN) (pp. 18). doi: 10.1109/IJCNN.2019.8852293 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solé, R., & Seoane, L. (2015). Ambiguity in language networks. Linguistic Review, 32(1), 535. https://doi.org/10.1515/tlr-2014-0014 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solomon, M. (1989). Quine’s point of view. Journal of Philosophy, 86(3), 113136. https://doi.org/10.2307/2027115 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spillmann, L. (2009). Phenomenology and neurophysiological correlations: Two approaches to perception research. Vision Research, 49(12), 15071521. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.visres.2009.02.022 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations (Anscombe, G. E. M., Trans.). Blackwell.Google Scholar
Zipf, G. K. (1949). Human behavior and the principle of least effort: An introduction to human ecology. Hafner Publishing Company. https://www.iqla.org/includes/basic_references/Zipf_1949_Human_Behavior_and_the_Principle_of_Least_Effort.pdf Google Scholar