Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T05:13:19.671Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Strangers and Members: Equality in an Immigration Setting

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 June 2015

Get access

Extract

Immigration Law has as its primary subject the stranger: the outsider who is under no obligation of allegiance to the state, who is not represented in its political processes, and whose needs and interests are, in most situations, accorded less concern than those of people who already participate in the social and political life of a community. The immigrant stranger may, of course, appear in a variety of guises. He may be a wealthy entrepreneur or investor who belongs to another political community but who chooses to emigrate to advance his own or his family’s well-being. Alternatively, the stranger may be a person who has experienced life solely within the confines of a community that is plagued by economic deprivation. Such a person may be crippled by physical and emotional need or cultural fragmentation. His search is for a new social environment in which, it is hoped, these constraints will not be present in such exaggerated or severe measure. Sometimes the needy stranger will be seeking an immediate escape from a political regime which offers her no protection or which aims at her very destruction, and sometimes she will be searching for deliverance from the incessant, limbo-like tedium or the multitude of unspeakable terrors to which one is exposed in a refugee camp. Whatever the guise in which he or she appears, the stranger is someone with whom the modern political state must come to terms. He or she cannot be ignored.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 1994

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. A prime example is John Rawls who explicitly restricts his theory of justice to “the basic structure of society conceived…as a closed system isolated from other societies.” Rawls, J. A Theory of Justice (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1971) at 8.Google Scholar

2. Part I of the Constitution Act 1982, being Schedule B to the Canada Act 1982 (U.K.), c. 11 (hereinafter Charter).

3. R.S.C. 1985, c. 1–2 (as amended) (hereinafter, Immigration Act).

4. Cf.Walzer, M. Spheres of Justice: A Defence of Pluralism and Equality (New York: Basic Books, 1983).Google ScholarWalzer introduces his discussion of membership by noting at page 31, “The primary good that we distribute to one another is membership in some human community. And what we do with regard to membership structures all our other distributive choices: it determines with whom we make those choices, from whom we require obedience and collect taxes, to whom we allocate goods and services.” Walzer’s assumption that membership is an allocated primary good is open to attack. See text, infra at page 153.

5. Thus, while a legal positivist who identifies the criteria of membership to be unsettled would hold that extra-legal criteria will be the proper source of determinations of membership, non-positivists may believe that interpretive methodology can be utilized to construct the legal principle which applies. This difference in approach lies at the heart of the Hart-Dworkin debate. See Hart, H.L.A. The Concept of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961)Google Scholar and , The Model of Rules I” in Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge MA.: Harvard University Press, 1978)Google ScholarPubMed

6. Walzer, supra note 4 at 56.

7. See Singer, P. & R.The Ethics of Refugee Policy” in Gibney, M. ed., Open Borders? Closed Societies? (New York: Greenwood Press, 1988) 111;Google Scholar Carens, J.H.Aliens and Citizens: The Case for Open Borders” (1987) 49 Rev. of Pol. 251 Google Scholar and , Membership and Morality: Admission to Citizenship in Liberal Democratic StatesBrubaker, W.R. ed., Immigration and the Politics of Citizenship in Europe and North America (Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1989).Google Scholar

8. See Neuman, G.L.Whose Constitution?” (1991) 100 Yale L.J. 909.Google Scholar

9. For a brief but insightful account of the perils of relativism, see Doyal, L. & Gough, I. A Theory of Human Need (London: Macmillan, 1991) at 3031.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

10. See Carens, Joseph H.Refugees and States: A Normative Analysis” in Adelman, Howard ed.,Refugee Policy: Canada and the United States (Toronto: York Lanes Press, 1991) 18,Google Scholar and Galloway, DonaldThe Extraterritorial Application of the Charter to Visa Applicants” (1991) 23 Ottawa L.R. 335 esp. at 35759.Google Scholar

11. 1978 SOR/78–172, (as amended).

12. See Immigration Act,s.3.

13. Immigration Actas am., R.S.C. 1985 (4th. Supp) c.28, s.

14. See Galloway, supra note 10.

15. Ibid, at 357–58.

16. See Singh v. M.E.I., [1985] 1 S.C.R. 177.

17. Andrews v. Law Society of British Columbia, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 143.

18. See, for example, McKinney. University of Guelph, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 229, where Wilson J. states, at 357,“those who enacted the Charter … set] out basic constitutional norms rooted in a concern for individual dignity and autonomy which government should be compelled to respect when structuring important aspects of citizens’ lives.”

19. See Canadian Council of Churches v. Canada Minister of Employment and Immigration, [1992] 1 S.C.R. 236 at 250.

20. See Galloway, D.Three Models of (In)Equality” (1993) 38 McGill L.J. 64.Google Scholar

21. See Dworkin, R. Law’s Empire (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1986) at 173 Google Scholar(hereinafter, Law’s Empire).

22. Ibid, at 206.

23. Andrews, supra note 47 at 174.

24. See Andrews, supra note 20.

25. Andrews, supra note 17, per Mclntyre J. at 184. See also the judgment of Wilson J. at 154.

26. Rosberg, Gerald M.The Protection of Aliens from Discriminatory Treatment by the National Government” (1977) Supreme Court Review 275 327.Google Scholar

27. Law’s Empire, at 206–15.

28. See R.v. Turpin, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 1296 at 1333. See also Galloway, supra note 20.

29. McKinney, supra note 18 at 391.

30. See Kymlicka, W. Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Introduction (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990) at 200.Google Scholar

31. See Kymlicka, W. Liberalism, Community, and Culture (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989) at 165.Google Scholar

32. Immigration Act, s. 3(h).

33. See Law’s Empire, at 211.

34. Résume, D.Is Integrity a Virtue? Dworkin’s Theory of Legal Obligation” (1989) 39 U.Tor.Law J. at 380 405.Google Scholar

35. See Hurd, H.M.Challenging Authority” (1991) 100 Yale L. J. 1611,Google Scholarand Hurd, "Sovereignty in Silence"(1990) 99 Yale L. J. 945. Hurd defends a model of political authority as theoretical authority, while criticizing the conception of practical authority developed by J. Raz.See Raz, J. The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986) at 23–109.Google Scholar

36. Immigration Statistics (Ottawa: Employment and Immigration Canada 1989) 8–9

37. Immigration Regulations {REVISED SOR 1978, c. 940) s.7(l) and Indochinese Designated Class (Transitional) Regulations SOR/90–627 s.5( 1), and Self-Exiled Persons Designated Class Regulations SOR/78–933 s.5(l) (as am. by SOR/89–386), and Political Prisoners and Oppressed Persons Designated Class Regulations SOR/82–9{9|7, s.5(l) {French version am. by SOR/89–499.)

38. Alan Nash, International Refugee Pressures and the Canadian Public Policy Response (Ottawa, Studies in Social Policy, 1989) at 67.

39. See Employment and Immigration Canada, “Women at Risk—Procedures and Guidelines” Operations Memorandum, IS 361, 20/4/1988; and Refugee Perspectives 1987–1988 (Ottawa: Employment and Immigration Canada, 1987) at 7.

40. See Dworkin, R. A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985) at 190.Google Scholar

41. See Martin, David A.The Refugee Concept: On Definitions, Politics, and the Careful Use of a Scarce Resource” in Refugee Policy, supra note 10, 30 at 41.Google Scholar

42. Ibid, at 40.

43. For Comments on the financial crisis being faced by UNHCR, see Iain Guest, “The United Nations, the UNHCR and Refugee Protection: A Non-Specialist Analysis” (1991) 3 Int’I. J. Refugee L. On the link between UNHCR and Canadian Refugee funding, see Moira Hart,“Canadian Overseas Assistance for Refugees” in Adelman, supra note 10 at 114.

44. See Oziewicz, E.Canada Resists Redefining Refugees: Tells U.N. Body Change UnfairGlobe and Mail, October 8, 1991, at A10.Google ScholarShannon’s error is to suppose that the funding for overseas aid is linked directly to the funding for internal administrative proceedings, such that an increase in one will necessitate a decrease in the other.

45. Hockè, Jean-PierreBeyond Humanitarianism” in Loescher & Monahan, Refugees and International Relations (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989) 37 at 4344.Google Scholar

46. Geneviéve Camus-Jacques, “Refugee Women: The Forgotten Majority” in Loescher & Monahan, supra note 45, 141 at 144.

47. See Elly-Elikunda Mtango, “Military and Armed Attacks on Refugee Camps” in Loescher & Monahan, supra note 45 at 87. See also Barry N. Stein, “The Nature of the Refugee Problem”, in Nash, A.E. Human Rights and the Protection of Refugees under International Law (Halifax: The Institute for Research on Public Policy, 1988) 47 at 56.Google Scholar

48. See Goodwin-Gill, GuyRefugees: The Functions and Limits of the Existing Protection System” in Human Rights and the Protection of Refugees Under International Law, supra note 47, 149 at 151.Google Scholar

49. Fiorella Capelli, “UNHCR and the Plight of Refugees: International Protection and Solutions in a Changing World Context” in Human Rights and the Protection of Refugees Under International Law, supra note 47, 27 at 28.