Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T05:07:20.251Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Global Turn in Legal Theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 February 2016

Get access

Abstract

Familiar legal theories are epistemologically and politically stato-centric theories; they aim to rationalize intra- and inter-national legal systems. If this Westphalian approach were to be abandoned, then its replacement might be called Global Law, which invites theorizing that is not stato-centric. When that change happens, one would talk about a Global Turn in legal theory. Describing this turn is the aim of the paper.

This description is articulated around two ideas about the history and geography of the globalizing of Law, and three intuitions about the fate of legal theory itself once this Global Turn is taken. Namely, how theorizing Law from this perspective leads to focus on what is emerging and circulating, how the aesthetics of legal thinking shifts towards perspectivism and dissociation, and how more pluralistic, eclectic and pragmatic modes of reasoning and arguing about Law become dominant. What follows is neither a substantial or positivistic analysis, nor a prediction or a wish, but an attempt to point out tendencies which might be essential features of contemporary legal thinking.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Twining, William, General Jurisprudence, Understanding Law from a Global Perspective (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009) at 14-15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

2. See Gong, Gerrit, The Standard of “Civilization” in International Society (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984).Google Scholar The question is asked whether those conditions were really the ones explicitly required, or if there was something else necessary, as Japan believed to have discovered the condition of being itself a “civilizer” after 1895.

3. When anthropologists invented customary laws, they had the excuse of not having read the critical works of legal anthropology that had been published since. See Assier-Andrieu, Louis, Le droit dans les sociétés humaines (Paris: Nathan, 1996)Google Scholar. Teubner, Gunther & Fischer-Lescano, Andreas, “Cannibalizing Epistemes: Will Modern Law Protect Traditional Cultural Expressions?” in Graber, Christoph Beat & Burri-Nenova, Mira, eds, Intellectual Property and Traditional Cultural Expressions: Legal Protection in a Digital Environment (Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 2008) at 17-45.Google Scholar

4. See Kennedy, Duncan, “Savigny’s Family/Patrimony Distinction and its Place in the Global Genealogy of Classical Legal Thought” (2010) 58Google Scholar Am J Comp L 811.

5. In a mass of literature, see Fanon, Franz, Peaux noires, masques blancs (Paris: Seuil, 1952)Google Scholar or in another genre, ironic, subtle and hopeless, see Tanizaki, Junichirô, “L’éloge de l’ombre” in Œuvres, (Gallimard: Pleiade, 1997) at vol 1.Google Scholar

6. Duncan Kennedy uses the expression “nesting” to describe the phenomenon of reproduction of binary divisions within each of the terms of divisions. See Kennedy, Duncan, “The Semiotics of Legal Argument” (1991) 42Google Scholar Syracuse L Rev 75.

7. See Koskenniemi, Martti, The Gentle Civilizer of Nations: The Rise and Fall of International Law 1870-1960 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

8. On this case, see Benoît Frydman, “Total et ses enjeux” in Liber Amicorum Paul Martens: L’humanisme dans la Résolution des Conflits. Utopie ou Réalité ? (Bruxelles: Larcier, 2007) at 301-21.

9. See Kingsbury, Benedict, Krisch, Nico, & Stewart, Richard B, “The Emergence of Global Administrative Law” (2005) 68Google Scholar Law & Contemp Prob 15. See also Sabino Cassese, “Administrative Law without the State? The Challenge of Global Regulation” (2005) 37 NYUJ Int’l L & Pol 663. For a critique of this project, see Chimni, Bhupinder Singh, “Co-Option and Resistance: Two Faces of Global Administrative Law” (2005)Google Scholar 37NYUJ Int’l L & Pol 799.

10. See Onuma, Yasuaki, A Transcivilizational Perspective on International Law (Leiden/Boston: Martinus Nijhoff, 2010).Google Scholar

11. See Chimni, Bhupinder, Gathii, James, Nyamu, Celestine, Nesiah, Vasuki, Noworjee, Elchee & Sayed, Hani, TWAIL, Vision Statement, working paper, 1997.Google Scholar This text is available in James Thuo Gathii’s “Alternative and Critical. The Contribution of Research and Scholarship on Developing Countries to International Legal Theory” (2000) 41 Int’l LJ at 263-75.

12. “Everybody in Global Law can claim themselves legislators. But this is not all. Some can establish themselves as “watchdogs” of globalization, as long as they be in possession of an effective means of controlling the actions of others. Or, since it is often what happens in practice, those in a situation of control can be required by others, often against their will, to carry the burden of watching, and if the case warrants it, sanctioning the bad behavior of other agents. This mission will often be designated “responsibility,” but the word holds a different meaning than when the word is used for moral responsibility, legal responsibility, or accountability.” See Frydman, Benôit, “Comment penser le droit global?” in Chérot, Jean-Yves & Frydman, Benôit, eds, La science du droit dans la globalisation (Brussels: Bruylant, 2012) 17.Google Scholar

13. See Muir-Watt, H, “Private International Law Beyond the Schism” (2011) 2-Google Scholar 3 Tranat’l Legal Theory 347.

14. See Schuiten, François & Peeters, Benoît, Les cités obscures (Paris: Casterman, 1983).Google Scholar

15. Perhaps the paradoxical success of this conception having a worldwide destiny is what permits the States to be a part of the History of the World without losing their independence. The idea is suggested by Duncan Kennedy, “Three Globalizations of Law and Legal Thought: 1850-2000” in Trubek, David & Santos, Alvaro, eds, The New Law and Economic Development, A Critical Appraisal (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006) at 19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

16. For example see Shapiro, Martin, “The Globalization of Law” (1993)Google Scholar 1 Ind J Global Legal Stud 37. See also Stewart, Richard B, “US Administrative Law: a Model for Global Administrative Law?” (2005) 68:3Google Scholar Law & Contemp Prob 63.

17. It occurs sometimes that these “importing” communities perceive the GTGL as products that are “foreign” to cultural tradition and experience violence from this importation, which is under certain aspects analogous to the violence resulting from the forced cultural integration of non-Western historical worlds into western legalism.

18. See Twining, supra note 1.

19. The expression is Fernand Braudel’s.

20. See Ackerman, Bruce, “The Rise of World Constitutionalism” (1997) 83Google Scholar Va L Rev 771.

21. Moreover, it found itself a reflecting friend to decide, with excellent supporting reasons that the present article was, in certain ways, typical of state-centrism within the French legal doctrine.

22. See Ohji, Kenta, “Civilisation et Naissance de l’Histoire Mondiale Dans l’Historie des Deux Indes de Raynal” (2008) 129:1Google Scholar Revue de Synthèse 57.

23. Veyne, Paul, Comment On Ecrit l’Histoire (Paris: Seuil, 1971) at 111.Google Scholar

24. See Kennedy, Duncan, “A Transnational Genealogy of Proportionality in Private Law” in Brownsword, Roger, Micklitz, Hans-W, Niglia, Leone & Weatherill, Stephen, The Foundations of European Private Law (Oxford: Hart, 2011) 185.Google Scholar

25. See Schlag, Pierre, “The Aesthetics of American Law” (2001-2002) 115Google Scholar Harv L Rev 1048.

26. For more on this minimal definition of legal feminism, see Halley, Janet, Split Decisions: How and Why to Take a Break from Feminism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

27. Llewellyn, Karl N & Hoebel, E Adamson, The Cheyenne Way: Conflict and Case Law in Primitive Jurisprudence (Norman: University of Oklahoma Press, 1941) at 283.Google Scholar

28. See Tamanaha, Brian, “Understanding Legal Pluralism” (2008) 30Google Scholar Sydney L Rev 375.

29. “There is no power relation without the correlative constitution of a field of knowledge, nor any knowledge that does not presuppose and constitute at the same time power relations. These “power knowledge relations” are to be analyzed, therefore, not on the basis of a subject of knowledge who is or is not free in relation to the power system, but, on the contrary, the subject who knows, the objects to be known and the modalities of knowledge must be regarded as so many effects of these fundamental implications of power knowledge and their historical transformations.” Foucault, Michel, “Discipline and Punish” in Rivken, Julie & Ryan, Michael, eds, Literary Theory: An Anthology, 2d ed (Malden: Blackwell, 2004) at 551.Google Scholar