Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gvvz8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T04:34:37.606Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

25 - The Normativity of Law

from Part V - Normativity and Values

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 January 2021

Torben Spaak
Affiliation:
Stockholms Universitet
Patricia Mindus
Affiliation:
Uppsala Universitet, Sweden
Get access

Summary

Brian considers the normativity of law within the framework of legal positivism, noting that the very idea of it has been understood differently by different authors. He proposes that we analyse the concept in terms of reasons for action, that such reasons must be something more than prudential reasons, that the proper question is whether law gives us reasons for actions of the relevant type that we would not have without law, and that Hume’s law makes this task difficult for legal positivists. He considers consequentialist justifications for the normativity of law proposed by Hobbes and Hume, Kelsen’s theory of the basic norm, Postema’s claim that the rule of recognition is a coordination convention, Shapiro’s planning theory of law, and Enoch’s triggering account, concluding that these accounts are all problematic in different ways. He observes that some authors see it as a specifically legal normativity that is neither moral nor prudential, while others conceive of it as moral normativity; he concludes that the former alternative needs elaboration and justification, while the latter is difficult to establish from within the legal positivist tradition.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alexy, R. 2002. The Argument from Injustice: A Reply to Legal Positivism. Trans. Paulson, B. L. and Paulson, S. L.. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 2007. ‘An Answer to Joseph Raz’. In Pavlakos, G. (ed.). Law, Rights, and Discourse. Hart: 3755.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 2011. ‘Normativity, Metaphysics and Decision’. In Bertea, S. and Pavlakos, G. (eds.). New Essays on the Normativity of Law. Hart: 219–28.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 2013. ‘Some Reflections on the Ideal Dimension of Law and on the Legal Philosophy of John Finnis’. American Journal of Jurisprudence 58: 97110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alexy, R. 2018. ‘The Special Case Thesis and the Dual Nature of Law’. Ratio Juris 31: 254–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aquinas, T. 1993. The Treatise on Law: St. Thomas Aquinas Summa Theologiae I–II; qq. 90–97. Ed. Henle, R. J.. University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Bix, B. H. 2018. ‘Kelsen, Hart, and Legal Normativity’. Revus 34: 2542.Google Scholar
Bix, B. H. 2019. ‘On the Nature of Legal Normativity: Response to Commentators’. Revus 37: 8391.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bratman, M. E. 1987. Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Bratman, M. E. 2011. ‘Reflections on Law, Normativity and Plans’. In Bertea, S. and Pavlakos, G. (eds.). New Essays on the Normativity of Law. Hart: 7385.Google Scholar
Broome, J. 2013. Rationality Through Reasoning. Wiley Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohon, R. 2018. ‘Hume’s Moral Philosophy’. In Zalta, E. N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/hume-moral/.Google Scholar
Coleman, J. L. 1998. ‘Incorporationism, Conventionality, and the Practical Difference Thesis’. Legal Theory 4: 381425.Google Scholar
Coleman, J. L. and Leiter, B. 2010. ‘Legal Positivism’. In Patterson, D. (ed.). A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Wiley-Blackwell: 228–48.Google Scholar
Copp, D. 1995. Morality, Normativity, and Society. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Copp, D. 2015. ‘Explaining Normativity’. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 89: 4873.Google Scholar
Copp, D. 2019. ‘Legal Teleology: A Naturalist Account of the Normativity of Law’. In Plunkett, D., Shapiro, S. J. and Toh, K. (eds.). Dimensions of Normativity. Oxford University Press: 4564.Google Scholar
Dancy, J. 2000. Practical Reality. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Delacroix, S. 2004. ‘Hart’s and Kelsen’s Concepts of Normativity Contrasted’. Ratio Juris 17: 501–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Delacroix, S. 2019. ‘Understanding Normativity’. Revus 37: 1728.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1986. Law’s Empire. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Edmundson, W. A. 2013. ‘Because I Said So’. Problema 7: 4161.Google Scholar
Ehrenberg, K. M. 2016. The Functions of Law. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Enoch, D. 2011a. ‘Giving Practical Reasons’. Philosophers’ Imprint 11(4): 122.Google Scholar
Enoch, D. 2011b. ‘Reason-Giving and the Law’. In Green, L. and Leiter, B. (eds.). Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law vol. 1. Oxford University Press: 138.Google Scholar
Fine, K. 2018. ‘Truthmaking and the Is-Ought Gap’. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01996-8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finnis, J. 2000. ‘On the Incoherence of Legal Positivism’. Notre Dame Law Review 75: 15971611.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 2011a. Natural Law and Natural Rights. 2nd ed. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 2011b. Philosophy of Law: Collected Essays vol. IV. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finnis, J. 2013. ‘Reflections and Responses’. In Keown, J. and George, R. P. (eds.). Reason, Morality, and Law: The Philosophy of John Finnis. Oxford University Press: 459583.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 2014. ‘Law as Fact and as Reason for Action: A Response to Robert Alexy on Law’s “Ideal Dimension”’. American Journal of Jurisprudence 59: 85109.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. L. 1958. ‘Positivism and Fidelity to Law: A Reply to Professor Hart’. Harvard Law Review 71: 630–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gizbert-Studnicki, T. 2019. ‘On Legal Things to Do: External and Internal Legal Reasons’. Revus 37: 2938.Google Scholar
Gkouvas, T. 2018. ‘The Metric Approach to Legal Normativity’. In Himma, K. E., Jovanavić, M. and Spaić, B. (eds.). Unpacking Normativity. Hart: 1737.Google Scholar
Gray, J. C. 1909. The Nature and Sources of the Law. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Green, L. 1999. ‘Positivism and Conventionalism’. Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 12: 3552.Google Scholar
Green, L. 2003a. ‘Legal Obligation and Authority’. In Zalta, E. N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-obligation/.Google Scholar
Green, L. 2003b. ‘Legal Positivism’. In Zalta, E. N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-positivism/.Google Scholar
Green, M. S. 2016. ‘Marmor’s Kelsen. In Telman, D. A. J. (ed.). Hans Kelsen in America: Selective Affinities and the Mysteries of Academic Influence. Springer: 3155.Google Scholar
Greenberg, M. 2011. ‘The Standard Picture and Its Discontents’. In Green, L. and Leiter, B. (eds.). Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law vol. I. Oxford University Press: 39106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greenberg, M. 2014. ‘The Moral Impact Theory of Law’. Yale Law Journal 123: 12881342.Google Scholar
Greenberg, M. 2017. ‘The Moral Impact Theory, the Dependence View and Natural Law’. In Duke, G. and George, R. P. (eds.). The Cambridge Companion to Natural Law Jurisprudence. Cambridge University Press: 275313.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1982. Essays on Bentham: Jurisprudence and Political Theory. Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 2012. The Concept of Law. 3rd ed. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hobbes, T. 1929. Leviathan. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Holmes, O. W. Jr. 1897. ‘The Path of the Law’. Harvard Law Review 10: 457–78.Google Scholar
Honoré, T. 1987. Making Law Bind. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hudson, W. D. 1969. The Is-Ought Question. Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. [1738]1978. A Treatise of Human Nature. 2nd ed. Ed. Nidditch, P. H.. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D. [1748]1994. ‘Of the Original Contract’. In David Hume: Political Essays. Ed. Haakonssen, K.. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurd, H. 1990. ‘Sovereignty in Silence’. Yale Law Journal 99: 9451028.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelsen, H. 1967. Pure Theory of Law. Trans. Knight, M.. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. 1992. Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory. Trans. Paulson, B. L. and Paulson, S. L.. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. 2008. The Constitution of Agency. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1969. Convention: A Philosophical Study. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Maguire, B. 2018. ‘The Autonomy of Ethics’. In McPherson, T. and Plunkett, D. (eds.). The Routledge Handbook of Metaethics. Routledge: 431–42.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2001. Positive Law and Objective Values. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2002. ‘Exclusive Legal Positivism’. In Coleman, J. and Shapiro, S. (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law. Oxford University Press: 104–24.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2009. Social Conventions. Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marmor, A. 2011. ‘The Conventional Foundations of Law’. In Bertea, S. and Pavlakos, G. (eds.). New Essays on the Normativity of Law. Hart: 143–57.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2018. ‘Norms, Reasons, and the Law’. In Himma, K. E., Jovanavić, M. and Spaić, B. (eds.). Unpacking Normativity. Hart: 95118.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2019. ‘Conventions, Reasons, and the Law’. In Ramírez-Ludeña, L. and Vilajosana, J. M. (eds.). Legal Conventionalism. Springer: 4763.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matczak, M. 2019. ‘Non-Lewisian Conventionalism and Law’. https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3378565.Google Scholar
Murphy, J. G. 1978. ‘Hume and Kant on the Social Contract’. Philosophical Studies 33: 6579.Google Scholar
Paulson, S. L. 2012. ‘A “Justified Normativity” Thesis in Hans Kelsen’s Pure Theory of Law?’ In Klatt, M. (ed.). Institutionalized Reason. Oxford University Press: 61111.Google Scholar
Paulson, S. L. 2017. ‘Metamorphosis in Hans Kelsen’s Legal Philosophy’. Modern Law Review 80: 860–94.Google Scholar
Pigden, C. R. 1991. ‘Naturalism’. In Singer, P. (ed.). A Companion to Ethics. Blackwell: 421–31.Google Scholar
Pigden, C. R. 2016. ‘Hume on Is and Ought: Logic, Promises, and the Duke of Wellington’. In Russell, P. (ed.). The Oxford Handbook on Hume. Oxford University Press: 401–15.Google Scholar
Postema, G. J. 1982. ‘Coordination and Convention at the Foundations of Law’. Journal of Legal Studies 11: 165203.Google Scholar
Postema, G. J. 2011. Legal Philosophy in the Twentieth Century World: The Common Law World. Springer.Google Scholar
Postema, G. J. 2012. ‘Custom, Normative Practice, and the Law’. Duke Law Journal 62: 707–38.Google Scholar
Radbruch, G. 2006. ‘Statutory Lawlessness and Supra-Statutory Law’. Trans. Paulson, B. L. and Paulson, S. L.. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 26: 111.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1994. Ethics in the Public Domain. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1990. Practical Reason and Norms. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 2009. Between Authority and Interpretation. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 2010. ‘Reason, Reasons, and Normativity’. In Shafer-Landau, R. (ed.). Oxford Studies in Metaethics vol. 5. Oxford University Press: 523.Google Scholar
Rescorla, M. 2019. ‘Convention’. In Zalta, E. N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/convention/.Google Scholar
Rosati, C. S. 2016. ‘Normativity and the Planning Theory of Law’. Jurisprudence 7: 307–24.Google Scholar
Rosati, C. S. 2019. ‘Bix on the Normativity of Law’. Revus 37: 6974.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 2014. Being Realistic About Reasons. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sciaraffa, S. 2009. ‘On Content-Independent Reason: It’s Not in the Name’. Law and Philosophy 28: 233–60.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. J. 2011a. Legality. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. J. 2011b. ‘Planning Agency and the Law’. In Bertea, S. and Pavlakos, G. (eds.). New Essays on the Normativity of Law. Hart.Google Scholar
Smith, M. B. E. 1973. ‘Is There a Prima Facie Obligation to Obey the Law?’. Yale Law Journal 82: 950–76.Google Scholar
Spaak, T. 2005. ‘Kelsen and Hart on the Normativity of Law’. In Perspectives on Jurisprudence: Essays in Honour of Jes Bjarup. Ed. Wahlgren, P.. Stockholm Institute for Scandinavian Law: 397414.Google Scholar
Spaak, T. 2018. ‘Legal Positivism, Conventionalism, and the Normativity of Law’. Jurisprudence 9: 319–44.Google Scholar
Tiffany, E. 2007. ‘Deflationary Normative Pluralism’. Canadian Journal of Philosophy supp. 33: 231–62.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1981. Moral Luck. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×