Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T05:14:23.088Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Part V - Normativity and Values

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 January 2021

Torben Spaak
Affiliation:
Stockholms Universitet
Patricia Mindus
Affiliation:
Uppsala Universitet, Sweden
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

References

Blackburn, S. 1985. ‘Errors and the Phenomenology of Value’. Reprinted in Blackburn, S.. Essays in Quasi-Realism. 1993. Oxford University Press: 149–65.Google Scholar
Boyd, R. 1988. ‘How to be a Moral Realist’. In Sayre-McCord, G. (ed.). Essays on Moral Realism. Cornell University Press: 181228.Google Scholar
Cherniak, C. 1986. Minimal Rationality. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1980. Essays on Actions and Events. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1984. Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1981. Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1989. The Intentional Stance. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1967. ‘The Model of Rules I’. In Dworkin, R.. Taking Rights Seriously. 1977. Harvard University Press: 1445.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1986. Law’s Empire. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1994/2017. ‘Hart’s Posthumous Reply’. Harvard Law Review 130: 20962130.Google Scholar
Enoch, D. 2011. Taking Morality Seriously. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, K. 2002. ‘The Varieties of Necessity’. Reprinted in Fine, K.. Modality and Tense. 2005. Clarendon Press: 235–60.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 1980. Natural Law and Natural Rights. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Foot, P. 1958–9. ‘Moral Beliefs’. Reprinted in Foot, P.. Virtues and Vices. 1978. University of California Press: 110–31.Google Scholar
Gibbard, A. 1990. Wise Choices, Apt Feelings. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hare, R. M. 1981. Moral Thinking. Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1961/1994. The Concept of Law. 2nd ed. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1966. ‘Legal Duty and Obligation’. Revised and reprinted in Hart, H. L. A.. Essays on Bentham. 1982. Clarendon Press: 127–61.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1987. ‘Comment’. In Gavison, R. (ed.). Issues in Contemporary Legal Philosophy: The Influence of H.L.A. Hart. Clarendon Press: 3542.Google Scholar
Joyce, R. 2001. The Myth of Morality. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Leiter, B. 2009. ‘Explaining Theoretical Disagreements’. University of Chicago Law Review 76: 1215–50.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1989. ‘Dispositional Theories of Value’. Reprinted in Lewis, D.. Papers in Ethics and Social Philosophy. 1999. Cambridge University Press: 68–94.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 1998. ‘Constitutive Conventions’. Revised and reprinted in Marmor, A.. Positive Law and Objective Values. 2001. Oxford University Press: 124.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2009. Social Conventions: From Language to Law. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. 1985. ‘Values and Secondary Qualities’. Reprinted in McDowell, J.. Mind, Value, and Reality. 1998. Harvard University Press: 131–50.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. 1903/1993. Principia Ethica. 2nd ed. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Murphy, M. 2004. ‘Natural Law Theory’. In Golding, M. and Edmundson, W. (eds.). The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Blackwell: 1528.Google Scholar
Perry, S. 1987. ‘Judicial Obligation, Precedent and the Common Law’. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 7: 215–57.Google Scholar
Postema, G. 1982. ‘Coordination and Convention at the Foundations of Law’. Journal of Legal Studies 11: 165203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Postema, G. 1986. Bentham and the Common Law Tradition. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Railton, P. 1997. ‘Explanations Involving Rationality’. In Earman, J. and Norton, J. (eds.). The Cosmos of Science: Essays of Exploration. University of Pittsburgh Press: 530–70.Google Scholar
Railton, P. 2006. ‘Normative Guidance’. In Shafer-Landau, R. (ed.). Oxford Studies in Metaethics vol. 1. Oxford University Press: 133.Google Scholar
Railton, P. 2012. ‘That Obscure Object, Desire’. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 86: 2246.Google Scholar
Railton, P. 2016. ‘Morality and Prospection’. In Seligman, M., Railton, P., Baumeister, R., and Sripada, C.. Homo Prospectus. Oxford University Press: 225–80.Google Scholar
Railton, P. 2019. ‘“We’ll see you in court!”: The Rule of Law as an Explanatory and Normative Kind’. In Plunkett, D., Shapiro, S., and Toh, K. (eds.). Dimensions of Normativity: New Essays on Metaethics and Jurisprudence. Oxford University Press: 122.Google Scholar
Raz, J 1972. ‘Legal Principles and the Limits of Law’. Yale Law Journal 81: 823–54.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1979. ‘Legal Reasons, Sources, and Gaps’. Reprinted in Raz, J.. The Authority of Law. 1979. Clarendon Press: 5377.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1983. ‘The Problem About the Nature of Law’. Reprinted in Raz, J., Ethics in the Public Domain. 1994. Clarendon Press: 179–93.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1985. ‘Authority, Law, and Morality’. Reprinted in Raz, J., Ethics in the Public Domain. 1994. Clarendon Press: 194221.Google Scholar
Seligman, M., Railton, P., Baumeister, R. and Sripada, C. 2016. Homo Prospectus. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. 1962. ‘Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man’. Reprinted in Sellars, W.. Science, Perception and Reality. 1963. Routledge & Kegan Paul: 140.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. 2002. ‘Law, Plans, and Practical Reason’. Legal Theory 8: 387441.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. 2011. Legality. Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stevenson, C. L. 1937. ‘The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms’. Mind 46: 1431.Google Scholar
Stroud, B. 2000. The Quest for Reality: Subjectivism and the Metaphysics of Colour. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Toh, K. 2005. ‘Hart’s Expressivism and His Benthamite Project’. Legal Theory 11: 75123.Google Scholar
Toh, K. 2007. ‘Raz on Detachment, Acceptance, and Describability’. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 27: 403–27.Google Scholar
Toh, K. 2008. ‘An Argument Against the Social Fact Thesis (and Some Additional Preliminary Steps Towards a New Conception of Legal Positivism)’. Law and Philosophy 27: 445504.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Toh, K. 2010. ‘Some Moving Parts of Jurisprudence’. Texas Law Review 88: 12831321.Google Scholar
Toh, K. 2011. ‘Legal Judgments as Plural Acceptances of Norms’. In Green, L. and Leiter, B. (eds.). Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law 1: 107–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Toh, K. 2013. ‘Jurisprudential Theories and First-Order Legal Judgments’. Philosophy Compass 8: 457–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Toh, K. 2014/15. ‘Four Neglected Prescriptions of Hartian Legal Philosophy’. Law and Philosophy 33: 689724. Republished with corrections as ‘Erratum to: Four Neglected Prescriptions of Hartian Legal Philosophy’. Law and Philosophy 34: 333–68.Google Scholar
Toh, K. 2018. ‘Law, Morality, Art, the Works’. In Burazin, L., Himma, K., and Roversi, C. (eds.). Law as an Artifact. Oxford University Press: 6185.Google Scholar
Toh, K. 2019. ‘Legal Philosophy à la carte’. In Plunkett, D., Shapiro, S., and Toh, K. (eds.). Dimensions of Normativity: New Essays on Metaethics and Jurisprudence. Oxford University Press: 221–47.Google Scholar
Toh, K. (forthcoming). ‘Law and Collectivity’. In Marques, T. and Valentini, C. (eds.). Collective Action, Philosophy and the Law. Routledge.Google Scholar
Waluchow, W. J. 1994. Inclusive Legal Positivism. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Wiggins, D. 1987. ‘Sensible Subjectivism?’. In Wiggins, D.. Needs, Values, Truth. Basil Blackwell: 185214.Google Scholar

References

Alexy, R. 2002. The Argument from Injustice: A Reply to Legal Positivism. Trans. Paulson, B. L. and Paulson, S. L.. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 2007. ‘An Answer to Joseph Raz’. In Pavlakos, G. (ed.). Law, Rights, and Discourse. Hart: 3755.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 2011. ‘Normativity, Metaphysics and Decision’. In Bertea, S. and Pavlakos, G. (eds.). New Essays on the Normativity of Law. Hart: 219–28.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 2013. ‘Some Reflections on the Ideal Dimension of Law and on the Legal Philosophy of John Finnis’. American Journal of Jurisprudence 58: 97110.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 2018. ‘The Special Case Thesis and the Dual Nature of Law’. Ratio Juris 31: 254–9.Google Scholar
Aquinas, T. 1993. The Treatise on Law: St. Thomas Aquinas Summa Theologiae I–II; qq. 90–97. Ed. Henle, R. J.. University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Bix, B. H. 2018. ‘Kelsen, Hart, and Legal Normativity’. Revus 34: 2542.Google Scholar
Bix, B. H. 2019. ‘On the Nature of Legal Normativity: Response to Commentators’. Revus 37: 8391.Google Scholar
Bratman, M. E. 1987. Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Bratman, M. E. 2011. ‘Reflections on Law, Normativity and Plans’. In Bertea, S. and Pavlakos, G. (eds.). New Essays on the Normativity of Law. Hart: 7385.Google Scholar
Broome, J. 2013. Rationality Through Reasoning. Wiley Blackwell.Google Scholar
Cohon, R. 2018. ‘Hume’s Moral Philosophy’. In Zalta, E. N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/hume-moral/.Google Scholar
Coleman, J. L. 1998. ‘Incorporationism, Conventionality, and the Practical Difference Thesis’. Legal Theory 4: 381425.Google Scholar
Coleman, J. L. and Leiter, B. 2010. ‘Legal Positivism’. In Patterson, D. (ed.). A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Wiley-Blackwell: 228–48.Google Scholar
Copp, D. 1995. Morality, Normativity, and Society. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Copp, D. 2015. ‘Explaining Normativity’. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 89: 4873.Google Scholar
Copp, D. 2019. ‘Legal Teleology: A Naturalist Account of the Normativity of Law’. In Plunkett, D., Shapiro, S. J. and Toh, K. (eds.). Dimensions of Normativity. Oxford University Press: 4564.Google Scholar
Dancy, J. 2000. Practical Reality. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Delacroix, S. 2004. ‘Hart’s and Kelsen’s Concepts of Normativity Contrasted’. Ratio Juris 17: 501–20.Google Scholar
Delacroix, S. 2019. ‘Understanding Normativity’. Revus 37: 1728.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1986. Law’s Empire. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Edmundson, W. A. 2013. ‘Because I Said So’. Problema 7: 4161.Google Scholar
Ehrenberg, K. M. 2016. The Functions of Law. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Enoch, D. 2011a. ‘Giving Practical Reasons’. Philosophers’ Imprint 11(4): 122.Google Scholar
Enoch, D. 2011b. ‘Reason-Giving and the Law’. In Green, L. and Leiter, B. (eds.). Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law vol. 1. Oxford University Press: 138.Google Scholar
Fine, K. 2018. ‘Truthmaking and the Is-Ought Gap’. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01996-8.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 2000. ‘On the Incoherence of Legal Positivism’. Notre Dame Law Review 75: 15971611.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 2011a. Natural Law and Natural Rights. 2nd ed. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 2011b. Philosophy of Law: Collected Essays vol. IV. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 2013. ‘Reflections and Responses’. In Keown, J. and George, R. P. (eds.). Reason, Morality, and Law: The Philosophy of John Finnis. Oxford University Press: 459583.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 2014. ‘Law as Fact and as Reason for Action: A Response to Robert Alexy on Law’s “Ideal Dimension”’. American Journal of Jurisprudence 59: 85109.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. L. 1958. ‘Positivism and Fidelity to Law: A Reply to Professor Hart’. Harvard Law Review 71: 630–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gizbert-Studnicki, T. 2019. ‘On Legal Things to Do: External and Internal Legal Reasons’. Revus 37: 2938.Google Scholar
Gkouvas, T. 2018. ‘The Metric Approach to Legal Normativity’. In Himma, K. E., Jovanavić, M. and Spaić, B. (eds.). Unpacking Normativity. Hart: 1737.Google Scholar
Gray, J. C. 1909. The Nature and Sources of the Law. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Green, L. 1999. ‘Positivism and Conventionalism’. Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 12: 3552.Google Scholar
Green, L. 2003a. ‘Legal Obligation and Authority’. In Zalta, E. N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-obligation/.Google Scholar
Green, L. 2003b. ‘Legal Positivism’. In Zalta, E. N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-positivism/.Google Scholar
Green, M. S. 2016. ‘Marmor’s Kelsen. In Telman, D. A. J. (ed.). Hans Kelsen in America: Selective Affinities and the Mysteries of Academic Influence. Springer: 3155.Google Scholar
Greenberg, M. 2011. ‘The Standard Picture and Its Discontents’. In Green, L. and Leiter, B. (eds.). Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law vol. I. Oxford University Press: 39106.Google Scholar
Greenberg, M. 2014. ‘The Moral Impact Theory of Law’. Yale Law Journal 123: 12881342.Google Scholar
Greenberg, M. 2017. ‘The Moral Impact Theory, the Dependence View and Natural Law’. In Duke, G. and George, R. P. (eds.). The Cambridge Companion to Natural Law Jurisprudence. Cambridge University Press: 275313.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1982. Essays on Bentham: Jurisprudence and Political Theory. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 2012. The Concept of Law. 3rd ed. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hobbes, T. 1929. Leviathan. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Holmes, O. W. Jr. 1897. ‘The Path of the Law’. Harvard Law Review 10: 457–78.Google Scholar
Honoré, T. 1987. Making Law Bind. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hudson, W. D. 1969. The Is-Ought Question. Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. [1738]1978. A Treatise of Human Nature. 2nd ed. Ed. Nidditch, P. H.. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D. [1748]1994. ‘Of the Original Contract’. In David Hume: Political Essays. Ed. Haakonssen, K.. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hurd, H. 1990. ‘Sovereignty in Silence’. Yale Law Journal 99: 9451028.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelsen, H. 1967. Pure Theory of Law. Trans. Knight, M.. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. 1992. Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory. Trans. Paulson, B. L. and Paulson, S. L.. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. 2008. The Constitution of Agency. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1969. Convention: A Philosophical Study. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Maguire, B. 2018. ‘The Autonomy of Ethics’. In McPherson, T. and Plunkett, D. (eds.). The Routledge Handbook of Metaethics. Routledge: 431–42.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2001. Positive Law and Objective Values. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2002. ‘Exclusive Legal Positivism’. In Coleman, J. and Shapiro, S. (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law. Oxford University Press: 104–24.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2009. Social Conventions. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2011. ‘The Conventional Foundations of Law’. In Bertea, S. and Pavlakos, G. (eds.). New Essays on the Normativity of Law. Hart: 143–57.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2018. ‘Norms, Reasons, and the Law’. In Himma, K. E., Jovanavić, M. and Spaić, B. (eds.). Unpacking Normativity. Hart: 95118.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2019. ‘Conventions, Reasons, and the Law’. In Ramírez-Ludeña, L. and Vilajosana, J. M. (eds.). Legal Conventionalism. Springer: 4763.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matczak, M. 2019. ‘Non-Lewisian Conventionalism and Law’. https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3378565.Google Scholar
Murphy, J. G. 1978. ‘Hume and Kant on the Social Contract’. Philosophical Studies 33: 6579.Google Scholar
Paulson, S. L. 2012. ‘A “Justified Normativity” Thesis in Hans Kelsen’s Pure Theory of Law?’ In Klatt, M. (ed.). Institutionalized Reason. Oxford University Press: 61111.Google Scholar
Paulson, S. L. 2017. ‘Metamorphosis in Hans Kelsen’s Legal Philosophy’. Modern Law Review 80: 860–94.Google Scholar
Pigden, C. R. 1991. ‘Naturalism’. In Singer, P. (ed.). A Companion to Ethics. Blackwell: 421–31.Google Scholar
Pigden, C. R. 2016. ‘Hume on Is and Ought: Logic, Promises, and the Duke of Wellington’. In Russell, P. (ed.). The Oxford Handbook on Hume. Oxford University Press: 401–15.Google Scholar
Postema, G. J. 1982. ‘Coordination and Convention at the Foundations of Law’. Journal of Legal Studies 11: 165203.Google Scholar
Postema, G. J. 2011. Legal Philosophy in the Twentieth Century World: The Common Law World. Springer.Google Scholar
Postema, G. J. 2012. ‘Custom, Normative Practice, and the Law’. Duke Law Journal 62: 707–38.Google Scholar
Radbruch, G. 2006. ‘Statutory Lawlessness and Supra-Statutory Law’. Trans. Paulson, B. L. and Paulson, S. L.. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 26: 111.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1994. Ethics in the Public Domain. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1990. Practical Reason and Norms. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 2009. Between Authority and Interpretation. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 2010. ‘Reason, Reasons, and Normativity’. In Shafer-Landau, R. (ed.). Oxford Studies in Metaethics vol. 5. Oxford University Press: 523.Google Scholar
Rescorla, M. 2019. ‘Convention’. In Zalta, E. N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/convention/.Google Scholar
Rosati, C. S. 2016. ‘Normativity and the Planning Theory of Law’. Jurisprudence 7: 307–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosati, C. S. 2019. ‘Bix on the Normativity of Law’. Revus 37: 6974.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 2014. Being Realistic About Reasons. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sciaraffa, S. 2009. ‘On Content-Independent Reason: It’s Not in the Name’. Law and Philosophy 28: 233–60.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. J. 2011a. Legality. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. J. 2011b. ‘Planning Agency and the Law’. In Bertea, S. and Pavlakos, G. (eds.). New Essays on the Normativity of Law. Hart.Google Scholar
Smith, M. B. E. 1973. ‘Is There a Prima Facie Obligation to Obey the Law?’. Yale Law Journal 82: 950–76.Google Scholar
Spaak, T. 2005. ‘Kelsen and Hart on the Normativity of Law’. In Perspectives on Jurisprudence: Essays in Honour of Jes Bjarup. Ed. Wahlgren, P.. Stockholm Institute for Scandinavian Law: 397414.Google Scholar
Spaak, T. 2018. ‘Legal Positivism, Conventionalism, and the Normativity of Law’. Jurisprudence 9: 319–44.Google Scholar
Tiffany, E. 2007. ‘Deflationary Normative Pluralism’. Canadian Journal of Philosophy supp. 33: 231–62.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1981. Moral Luck. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

References

Alexy, R. 1986. Theorie der Grundrechte. Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 2003a. ‘Constitutional Rights, Balancing, and Rationality’. Ratio Iuris 16: 131–40.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 2003b. ‘On Balancing and Subsumption: A Structural Comparison’. Ratio Iuris 16: 433–49.Google Scholar
Atienza, M. 1998. El sentido del Derecho. Ariel.Google Scholar
Atienza, M. and Ruiz Manero, J. 1996. Las piezas del Derecho. Ariel.Google Scholar
Atria, F. 2002. On Law and Legal Reasoning. Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
Bayón, J. C. 2004. ‘Democracia y derechos: problemas de fundamentación del constitucionalismo’. In Betegón, J., Laporta, F., Páramo, J. R. and Prieto Sanchís, L. (eds.). Constitución y derechos fundamentals. Centro de Estudios Políticos y Constitucionales: 67118.Google Scholar
Bickel, A. M. 1962. The Least Dangerous Branch: The Supreme Court at the Bar of Politics. Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Bobbio, N. 1950. ‘Scienza del diritto e analisi del linguaggio’. Rivista trimestrale di diritto e procedura civile 4: 342–67.Google Scholar
Coleman, J. L. 2001. The Practice of Principle. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1977. Taking Rights Seriously. Duckworth.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1996. Freedom’s Law: The Moral Reading of the Constitution. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Farnsworth, W. 2008. The Legal Analyst: A Toolkit for Thinking about the Law. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Ferrajoli, L. 1970. Teoria assiomatizzata del diritto. Parte generale. Giuffrè.Google Scholar
Ferrajoli, L. 1989. Diritto e Ragione. Teoria del garantismo penale. Laterza.Google Scholar
Ferrajoli, L. 1999. Derechos y garantías. La ley del más débil. Trans. Ibáñez, P. Andrés and Greppi, A.. Trotta.Google Scholar
Ferrajoli, L. 2001. Diritti fondamentali. Un dibattito teorico. Ed. Vitale, E.. Laterza.Google Scholar
Ferrajoli, L. 2007. Principia Iuris. Teoria del diritto e della democrazia. Laterza.Google Scholar
Ferrajoli, L. 2011a. ‘Constitucionalismo principialista y constitucionalismo garantista’. Doxa. Cuadernos de Filosofía del Derecho 34: 1553.Google Scholar
Ferrajoli, L. 2011b. ‘El constitucionalismo garantista. Entre paleo-iuspositivimo y neo-iusnaturalismo’. Doxa. Cuadernos de Filosofía del Derecho 34: 311–62.Google Scholar
Ferrajoli, L. 2011c. ‘The Normative Paradigm of Constitutional Democracy’. Res Publica. 17: 355–67.Google Scholar
Ferrajoli, L. 2012. ‘La scelta come fondamento ultimo della morale’. Teoria Politica 2: 177–88.Google Scholar
Ferrajoli, L. 2016. La logica del diritto. Dieci aporie nell’opera di Hans Kelsen. Laterza.Google Scholar
Ferrajoli, L. 2018. Manifesto per l’uguaglianza. Laterza.Google Scholar
Ferrajoli, L. and Ruiz Manero, J. 2012. Dos modelos de constitucionalismo. Una conversación. Trotta.Google Scholar
Gardner, J. 2001. ’Legal Positivism: 5½ Myths’. American Journal of Jurisprudence 46: 199226.Google Scholar
Gargarella, R. 1996. La justicia frente al gobierno. Sobre el carácter contramayoritario del poder judicial. Ariel.Google Scholar
Greenberg, M. 2004. ‘How Facts Make Law’. Legal Theory 10: 157–98.Google Scholar
Gruber, T. R. 1993. ‘A Translation Approach to Portable Ontologies’. Knowledge Acquisition 5: 199220.Google Scholar
Hamilton, A., Madison, J. and Jay, J. 1788. The Federalist: A Collection of Essays, Written in Favour of the New Constitution. J. and A. M’Lean.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1958. ‘Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals’. Harvard Law Review 71: 593629.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1968. ‘Legal Excuses and Responsibility’. In Hart., H. L. A. Punishment and Responsibility. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1994. The Concept of Law. With the Postscript. Eds. Bulloch, P. and Raz, J.. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Himma, K. E. 2002. ‘Inclusive Legal Positivism’. In Coleman, J. L. and Shapiro, S. J. (eds.) The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law. Oxford University Press: 125–65.Google Scholar
Laporta, F. 1993. Entre el derecho y la moral. Fontamara.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2002. ‘Exclusive Legal Positivism’. In Coleman, J. L. and Shapiro, S. J. (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law. Oxford University Press: 104–24.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2011. Philosophy of Law. Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moreso, J. J. 2001. ‘In Defense of Inclusive Legal Positivism’. In Chiassoni, P. (ed.). The Legal Ought. Giappichelli: 3764.Google Scholar
Moreso, J. J. 2008. ‘Ferrajoli o el constitucionalismo optimista’. Doxa 31: 279–87.Google Scholar
Moreso, J. J. 2009. La Constitución: modelo para armar. Marcial Pons.Google Scholar
Moreso, J. J. 2011. ‘Antígona como defeater. Sobre el constitucionalismo garantista de Ferrajoli’. Doxa 34: 183–99.Google Scholar
Moreso, J. J. 2012a. ‘Legal Defeasibility and the Connection between Law and Morality’. In Ferrer Beltran, J. and Battista Ratti, G. (eds.). The Logic of Legal Requirements. Essays on Defeasibility. Oxford University Press: 225–37.Google Scholar
Moreso, J. J. 2012b. ‘Ways of Solving Conflicts of Constitutional Rights: Proportionalism and Specificationism’. Ratio Juris 25: 3146.Google Scholar
Prieto Sanchís, L. 2008. ‘Derecho y democracia constitucional. Una discusión sobre Principia iuris de Luigi Ferrajoli’. Doxa 31: 325–53.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1975. Practical Reason and Norms. Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1979. The Authority of Law. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1994. Ethics in the Public Domain. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 2004. ‘Incorporation by Law’. Legal Theory 10: 117.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 2009. ‘The Argument from Justice, or How Not to Reply to Legal Positivism’. In Raz, J.. The Authority of Law. 2nd ed. Oxford University Press: 313–36.Google Scholar
Schauer, F. 1991. Playing by the Rules. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. J. 1998. ‘On Hart’s Way Out’. Legal Theory 4: 469508.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. J. 2011. Legality. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Waldron, J. 1998. Law and Disagreement. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Waldron, J. 2006. ‘The Core of the Case against Judicial Review’. Yale Law Journal 115: 13461406.Google Scholar
Waluchow, W. J. 1994. Inclusive Legal Positivism. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×